what is cognitive science? what’s in the mind? how do we know? zenon pylyshyn, rutgers center for...

59
What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? enon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Upload: alanis-parcells

Post on 14-Dec-2015

217 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

What is Cognitive Science?

What’s in the mind? How do we know?

Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Page 2: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

What is special about cognition?• Cognition (from Latin “cogito”) refers to the capacity to

know, and by extension to reason, perceive, plan, decide, solve problems, infer the beliefs of others, communicate by language as well as by other ways, and all the other capabilities we associated with intelligent activity.

• What is central to all such activity is that it relies on representations of the (actual or imagined) world.Cognitive science is the study of systems that represent and that

use their representations rationally, e.g.,draw inferences.A computer is another such system, so computing has become

the basic paradigm of cognitive science.

• In the last 40 years, The Representational Theory of Mind has become The Computational Theory of Mind

Page 3: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Cognitive science is a delicate mixture of the obvious and the incredible

Granny was almost right:

Behavior really is governed by what we know and what we want (together with the mechanisms for representing and for drawing inferences from these)

Page 4: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

It’s emic, not etic properties that matterKenneth Pike

What determines our behavior is not how the world is, but how we represent it as being As Chomsky pointed out in his review of Skinner, if

we describe behavior in relation to the objective properties of the world, we would have to conclude that behavior is essentially stimulus-independent

Every behavioral regularity (other than physical ones like falling) is cognitively penetrable

Page 5: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

It’s emic states that

matter!

Page 6: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

The central role of representation creates some serious problems for a natural science

What representations are about is what mattersBut how can the fact that a belief is about some

particular thing have an observable consequence? • How can beliefs about ‘Santa Claus’ (or the ‘Holy Grail’) determine behavior when there is no Santa Claus?

In a natural science if “X causes Y” then X must exist and be causally connected to Y!

• It’s even worse than that; even when X exists, it is not X’s physical properties that are relevant!

e.g., the North Star & navigation

Page 7: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Is it hopeless to think we can have a natural science of cognition?

Along comes The computational theory of mind

“the only straw afloat”

Page 8: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

The major historical milestones

• Brentano’s recognition of the problem of intentionality: Mental States are about something, but aboutness is not a physical relation.

• The formalist movement in the foundations of mathematics: Hilbert, Kurt Gödel, Bertrand Russell & Alfred Whitehead, Alan Turing, Alonzo Church, … provided a technique by which logical reasoning could be automated.

• Representational/Computational theory of mind: The modern era: Newell & Simon, Chomsky, Fodor

Page 9: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Intelligent systems behave the way they do because of what the represent

• But in order to function under physical principles, the representations must be instantiated in physical properties

• To encode knowledge in physical properties one first encodes it in symbolic form (Proof Theory tells us how) and then instantiates those symbolic codes physically (computer science tells us how)

Page 10: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

How to make a purely mechanical system reason about things it does not understand or know about? The discovery of symbolic logic.

(1) Married(John, Mary) or Married(John, Susan) and the equation or “statement”,(2) not[Married(John, Susan)]. from these two statements you can conclude,(3) Married(John, Mary)

But notice that (3) follows from (1) and (2) regardless of what is in the parts of the equation not occupied by the terms or or not so that you could write down the equations without mentioning marriage or John or Mary or, for that matter, anything having to do with the world. Try replacing these expressions with the meaningless letters P and Q. The inference still holds:

(1') P or Q (2') not Q therefore, (3') P

Page 11: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Cognitive Science and the Tri-Level Hypothesis

Intelligent systems are organized at three (or more) distinct levels:

1. The physical or biological level

2. The symbolic or syntactic level

3. The knowledge or semantic level

This means that different regularities may require appeal to different levels

Page 12: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

How can we find out?

• Given these broad constraints on cognitive theory, how do we go about discovering how it works?

Page 13: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Weak vs Strong Equivalence

• Is cognitive science concerned with anything more than developing models that generate the same Input-Output behavior as people exhibit in certain problem domains?

• A theory that correctly predicts I-O behavior is said to be weakly equivalent to the psychological process it is supposed to explain. It is what some people mean by “simulating behavior”.

• Everyone in Cognitive Science is interested in strong equivalence – we want to explain not only the observed behavior, but also how it is generated. The how will take the form of an algorithm.

Page 14: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Simulating the Input-Output function

Black BoxInput Output

Can we do any better than I-O simulation without looking inside the black box?

If all you have is observed behavior, how can you go beyond I-O simulation?

Page 15: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Modeling the Actual Process (the algorithm used)

Black BoxInput Output

If all you have is observed behavior, how can you go beyond I-O simulation (mimicry)?

Answer: Not all observations are Inputs or Outputs: some are meta-behavior or indexes of processes.

Index of process

Page 16: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Example of the Sternberg memory search

• The initial input consists of the instructions and the presentation of the memory set (n items).

• On each trial the particular input to the black box consists of the presentation of a target letter.

• The output consists of a binary response (present or absent). The time taken to respond is also recorded. That is called the “Reaction Time”.

• The reaction time is not part of the output but is interpreted as an index of the process (e.g., an indication of how many steps were performed).

Page 17: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Example of the input-output of a computational model of the Sternberg

task

• Inputs: Memory set is (e.g.) C, D, H, N

• Inputs: Probe (e.g., C or F)

• Output: Pairs of Responses and Reaction Times (e.g. output is something like “Yes, 460 msecs”)

• Does it matter how the Output is derived?It doesn’t if all you care about is I-O behavior It does if you care about Strong Equivalence (i.e.,

HOW it works)

Page 18: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Example of the input-output of a computational model of the Sternberg

task• Inputs are: (1) Memory set = C,D,H,N

(2) Target probe = C (or R)• Input-Output prediction using a table:

Input to model Model prints out

C Yes 460 ms

N Yes 530 ms

R No 600 ms

H Yes 520 ms

M No 620 ms

Is this model weakly- or strongly-equivalent to a person?

Page 19: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Example of a weakly equivalent model of the Sternberg task

1. Store memory set as a list L, assign set size = n2. Read target item I (If I = “end” quit)3. Check if I is one of the letters in the list L4. If found in list, assign R=“yes” otherwise R=“no”5. If R=“yes”, set T= 500 + K * n Rand(20 x 50)6. If R=“no”, set T= 800 + K * n Rand(20 x 50)7. Print R, Print T8. Go to 2

Is this the way people do it? How do you know?

Page 20: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

How do you know?

• Because in this case time should not be one of the computed outputs, but a measure of how many steps it took.

• The same is true of intermediate states (e.g., determined by what subjects say), error rates, eye tracking, judgments about the output, and so on.

• Question: Is time always a valid index of processing complexity?

Page 21: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Results of the Sternberg memory search taskWhat do they tell us about how people do it? Is this Input-Output equivalent or is it strongly equivalent to human performance?

Self-terminating searchExhaustive search

Page 22: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

More examples – arithmetic

How can we tell what algorithm is being used when children do arithmetic?

Consider these examples of students doing addition and subtraction. What can you tell from these few examples?

3279521826 + + - - -

?? 54621 53511 10969 11179 11875

How else could we try to find out what method they were using?

Page 23: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Studying human arithmetic algorithms

• Arithmetic (VanLehn & Brown. “Buggy”)Buggy – a model of children’s arithmetic – has about

350 “rules” which help uncover “deep bugs”

• Newell & Simon’s study of problem solvingProblem behavior graph and production systems

Use of protocols, eye tracking

• Information-Processing style of theory. Computational but not always a computer model.

Page 24: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Does intentionality (and the trilevel hypothesis) only apply to high-level processes such as reasoning?

• Examples from language.

John gave the book to Fred because he finished itJohn gave the book to Fred because he wanted it

• The city council refused to give the workers a permit for a demonstration because they feared violence

• The city council refused to give the workers a permit for a demonstration because they were communists

Page 25: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Representation in perception

• What does perception (especially vision) tell cognition?

• What is the “output” of the visual system?

Page 26: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

This is what our conscious experience suggests goes on in vision…

Page 27: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

This is what the demands of explanation suggests must be going on in vision…

Page 28: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Completions …

Where’s Waldo?

Page 29: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Standard view of saccadic integration by superposition

Page 30: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Does intentionality (and the trilevel hypothesis) only apply to high-level processes such as reasoning?

Examples from vision seeing as: It’s what you see the figure as that determines behavior – not its physical properties.

What you see one part as determines what you see another part as.

Page 31: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Is it possible to specify a set of ways of physically presenting a visual stimulus for it to be perceived in a certain way?

Page 32: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Can you think of other ways of presenting a stimulus so it is perceived as e.g., a Necker Cube?

Page 33: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Errors in recall suggest how visual information is encoded

• Errors in relative orientation often take a canonical form

• Errors in reproducing a 3D image preserve 3D information

Children have very good visual memory, yet often make egregious errors of recall

Page 34: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Errors in recall suggest how visual information is encoded

• Children more often confuse left-right than rotated forms

• Errors in imitating actions is another source of evidence

Page 35: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Ability to manipulate and recall patterns depends on their conceptual, not geometric, complexity

• Difficulty in superimposing shapes depends on they are conceptualizedLook at first two shapes and superimpose them in your mind; then draw (or select one) that is their superposition

Page 36: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Many studies have shown that memory for shapes is dependent on the conceptual

vocabulary available for encoding theme.g., recall of chess positions by beginners and masters

Page 37: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Other examples showing that it is how you represent something that is relevant to cognitive science

• Examples from color vision.

“Red light and yellow light mix to produce orange light”

This remains true for any way of getting red light and yellow light:e.g. yellow may be light of 580 nanometer wavelength, or it may be a mixture of light of 530 nm and 650 nm wavelengths. So long as one light looks yellow and the other looks red the “law” will hold.

Page 38: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

If cognitive processes are at a different level of organization from the physical level, how can we ever find out what they are – i.e., how can we discover what algorithm is being used?

We are limited only by the imagination of the experimenter, e.g., Relative complexity evidence (RT, error rates…) Intermediate state evidence

Eye tracking Stage analysis (additive factors method) Event Related Potentials (EEG) fMRI clinical observations of brain damage Psychophysical methods (SDT) Etc…

Page 39: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Two other considerations that are special to cognitively determined behavior1. The Cognitive Penetrability of most cognitive

processes. A regularity that is based on representations (knowledge) can be systematically altered by imparting new information that changes beliefs.

2. The critical role of "Cognitive Capacity". Because of an organism's ecological or social niche, only a small fraction of its behavioral repertoire is ever actually observed. Nonetheless an adequate cognitive theory must account for the behavioral repertoire that is compatible with the organism's structure, which we call its cognitive capacity.

Page 40: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Strong Equivalence and the role of cognitive architecture

Page 41: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

The concept of cognitive architecture

If differences among behaviors (including differences among individuals) is to be attributed to different beliefs or different algorithms, then there must be some common set of basic operations and mechanisms. This is called the Cognitive Architecture• The concept of a particular algorithm, or of being “the same

algorithm” is only meaningful if two computers have the same architecture. Algorithm is architecture-relative.

The architecture is the part of the system that does not change when beliefs change. So it defines the system’s Cognitive Capacity.

Page 42: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

On the difference between explanations that appeal to mental architecture and those that appeal to tacit knowledge

Suppose we observe some robust behavioral regularity. What does it tell us about the nature of the mind or about its intrinsic properties?

Page 43: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

An illustrative example: Mystery Code Box

What does this behavior pattern tell us about the nature of the box?

Page 44: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

An illustrative example: Mystery Code Box

What does this behavior pattern tell us about the nature of the box?

Careful study reveals that pattern #2 only occurs in this special context when it is preceded by pattern A

Page 45: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

The Moral: Regularities in behavior

may be due to either:

1. The inherent nature of the system or its structure or architecture.

2. The content of what the system represents (what it “knows”).

Page 46: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Why it matters:

A great many regular patterns of behavior reveal nothing more about human nature than that people do what follows rationally from what they believe. The example of human conditioning

Page 47: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Another example where it matters:The study of mental imagery

Application of the architecture vs knowledge distinction to understanding what goes on when we reason using mental images

Page 48: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Examples of behavior regularities attributable to tacit knowledge

• Color mixing, conservation of volume

• The effect of image size ?

• Scanning mental images ?

Page 49: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Color mixing example

Page 50: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Conservation of volume example

Page 51: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Our studies of mental scanning

0

0.2

0.4

0.6

0.8

1

1.2

1.4

1.6

1.8

2

1 2 3 4

Relative distance on imageL

aten

cy (

secs

)

scan image

imagine lights

show direction

(Pylyshyn & Bannon. See Pylyshyn, 1981)

There is even reason to doubt that one can imagine scanning continuously (Pylyshyn & Cohen, 1998)

Page 52: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Can you rotate a mental image?

Which pair of 3D objects is the same except for orientation?

Page 53: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Do mental images have size?Imagine a very small mouse. Can you see its whiskers? Now imagine a huge mouse. Can you see its whiskers?

Which is faster?

Page 54: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science
Page 55: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Why do so many people deny these obvious facts about mental

imagery?

• The power of subjective experience (phenomenology). The mind-body problem is everywhere: but subjective experience does not cause behavior! (e.g., conscious will)

• The failure to make some essential distinctionso Content vs form (the property of images vs the property of

what images are about) {compare the code box example}

o An image of X with property P can mean (An image of X) with property P or An image of (X with property P)

• Capacity vs typical behavior: Architecture vs knowledge

Page 56: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

Are there pictures in the brain?

• There is no evidence for cortical displays of the right kind to explain visual or imaginal phenomena

Page 57: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

So what is in the brain?

• The best hypothesis so far (i.e., the only one that has not been shown to be clearly on the wrong track) is that the brain is a species of computer in which representations of the world are encoded in the form of symbol structures, and actions are determined by calculations (i.e., inferences) based on these symbolic encodings.

Page 58: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

So why does it not feel like we are doing computations?

Because the content of our conscious experience is a very poor guide to what is actually going on that causes our experiences and our behavior. Science is concerned with causes, not just correlations.

Because we can’t assume that the way things seem has much to do with how it works (e.g., language understanding) As in most sciences, the essential causes are far from obvious

(e.g., why does the earth go around the sun? What is this table made of ? etc.).

In the case of cognition, what is going on is a delicate mixture of the obvious (what Granny or Shakespeare knew about why people do what they do) and the incredible

Page 59: What is Cognitive Science? What’s in the mind? How do we know? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science

We can’t always be sure we have the right method or instrument