wu conscious attention

28
What is Conscious Attention? wayne wu Carnegie Mellon University Everyone knows what attention is. It is the taking possession by the mind, in clear and vivid form, of one out of what seem several simul- taneously possible objects or trains of thought. Focalization, concen- tration, of consciousness are of its essence. It implies withdrawal from some things in order to deal effectively with others. William James Principles of Psychology 1. Introduction Perceptual attention is essential to both thought and agency, for there is arguably no demonstrative thought or bodily action without it. 1 Psychologists and philosophers since William James have taken attention to be a ubiquitous and distinctive form of consciousness, one that leaves a characteristic mark on perceptual experience. As a way of selecting specific perceptual inputs, attention influences the way things perceptually appear. It may then seem that it is a specific feature of perceptual representation that constitutes what it is like to consciously attend to an object. I shall argue, rather, that it is cognition that explains the quality James noted. The phenomenology of conscious attention to what is perceived involves not just a way of perceptually locking on to a specific object. It is a way of cognitively locking on to it as well. To begin, let us introduce the term phenomenal salience to refer to the way an object or property figures to a subject when she consciously attends to it in perception, a way that constitutes what it is like to 1 See Campbell (2002) on the former; Wu, forthcoming-b on the latter. WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 93 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXII No. 1, January 2011 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

Upload: adi-juliawan-pawana

Post on 27-Dec-2015

23 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Wu Conscious Attention

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Wu Conscious Attention

What is Conscious Attention?

wayne wuCarnegie Mellon University

Everyone knows what attention is. It is the taking possession by themind, in clear and vivid form, of one out of what seem several simul-taneously possible objects or trains of thought. Focalization, concen-tration, of consciousness are of its essence. It implies withdrawal fromsome things in order to deal effectively with others.

William JamesPrinciples of Psychology

1. Introduction

Perceptual attention is essential to both thought and agency, for there

is arguably no demonstrative thought or bodily action without it.1

Psychologists and philosophers since William James have taken

attention to be a ubiquitous and distinctive form of consciousness, onethat leaves a characteristic mark on perceptual experience. As a way of

selecting specific perceptual inputs, attention influences the way thingsperceptually appear. It may then seem that it is a specific feature of

perceptual representation that constitutes what it is like to consciouslyattend to an object. I shall argue, rather, that it is cognition thatexplains the quality James noted. The phenomenology of conscious

attention to what is perceived involves not just a way of perceptuallylocking on to a specific object. It is a way of cognitively locking on to

it as well.To begin, let us introduce the term phenomenal salience to refer to

the way an object or property figures to a subject when she consciouslyattends to it in perception, a way that constitutes what it is like to

1 See Campbell (2002) on the former; Wu, forthcoming-b on the latter.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 93

Philosophy and Phenomenological ResearchVol. LXXXII No. 1, January 2011! 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC

Philosophy andPhenomenological Research

Page 2: Wu Conscious Attention

attend to that object or property.2 Keeping in mind that it is possible

to attend to multiple items, this claim implies:

(P): Necessarily, a subject S consciously attends to an object oor property F i! o or F is phenomenally salient to S.3

We can give more specific versions of (P) such as for conscious percep-

tual or conscious visual attention where we focus on perceptual or visualphenomenal salience respectively. Our question, ‘‘What is conscious

attention?’’, then becomes the question, ‘‘What is phenomenal salience?’’Reflection on the experience of attention suggests two vivid forms.

The main focus of this essay is on what we can call the Jamesian form

captured by the epigraph. James noted that attending to an objectyields simultaneous contrast: we focus on one object while withdrawing

from others. Although he speaks here of thought, he writes in similarterms of attention in perception: ‘‘Accentuation and Emphasis are pres-

ent in every perception’’ (1890, 284). Contemporary psychologists haveechoed James in their talk of visual attention as a spotlight or zoom

lens. While these are metaphors for sub-personal information process-ing, they strike us as apt because they echo James’ description of thephenomenology. Philosophers give similar characterizations. John

Campbell presents the scenario of identifying the person to whom one’scompanion is pointing in a ‘‘sea of faces’’, and he notes that until we

‘‘experientially highlight’’ the relevant face, that is until we consciouslyattend to it, we do not know who is being referred to (2002, 7-8). Con-

sider also a scenario posed by David Chalmers: ‘‘one might look at twored pinpoint lights against a black background, and shift attention from

one to the other’’ (2004, 161). Chalmers points out that the attendedlight may be ‘‘represented as more salient than the other light’’ (ibid)

although he adds that it is not clear what salience amounts to.The upshot of these Jamesian descriptions is that conscious percep-

tual attention is characterized by simultaneous contrast between

attended versus unattended objects: the attended object is experiencedas highlighted, accentuated, spotlighted, emphasized or more salient in

contrast to unattended objects concurrently perceived. I shall refer tothis form as synchronic phenomenal salience, one that is most clearly

2 Note that in psychology what is salient is that which captures attention. ‘‘Salience’’is not used to describe a perceptual state. Thanks to Hemdat Lerman and DavidHilbert for emphasizing this to me.

3 I will not explicitly mention attention to properties or to multiple items in what fol-lows, but both will always be implicit. One can also attend to regions of space, andwhile I do not discuss this facet of attention explicitly, my proposal should alsoapply to the phenomenal salience of regions of space.

94 WAYNE WU

Page 3: Wu Conscious Attention

associated with voluntarily maintaining attention on an object. It is this

notion that has figured in recent debates about representationalaccounts of perceptual experience and the possibility of demonstrative

thought, debates we shall consider below.A second form is most strikingly associated with what is called

attentional capture although it is also associated with voluntary shiftsof attention. Consider the cases of attentional capture where stimuli

intrude on experience: a sudden increase in the volume of backgroundmusic, the movement of a stationary object at the periphery of vision,

or the sharp sensation of a cramp in one’s leg while swimming. Some-thing grabs our attention. The issue here is a contrast in the presenta-tion of a single object over time, what I will call diachronic phenomenal

salience. That object becomes salient.How can we explain these two forms of attention uniformly? In

section 2, I highlight distinctions necessary to adequately identify theexplananda. The next two sections provide a reductive representational

account of phenomenal salience. I consider what Chalmers calls pureand impure representational accounts, namely, accounts that appeal only

to representational content and those that appeal also to thepsychological mode respectively.4 I argue against pure reductive accountsof phenomenal salience but ultimately defend an impure account.

Section 3 highlights an intelligibility condition for reductive represen-tationalism, namely that representationalism requires not just the

supervenience of the phenomenal on the representational but also thatthe phenomenal must be intelligible in light of that representational

basis. I then consider pure reductive accounts of synchronic salienceand argue that they fail to meet this condition. I show this first for an

empirically motivated account of visual synchronic salience in terms ofvisual contrast although the point can be plausibly generalized to any

visually represented property and indeed to other sensory modalities aswell. I then consider whether diachronic phenomenal salience is themore fundamental notion since a pure representational account of it

appears available and it seems to correlate in the required way withsynchronic salience. Yet this correlation is illusory. The prospects for a

pure reductive account of synchronic salience are very dim.In section 4, I argue for an impure account of both forms of

phenomenal salience, one that appeals to psychological mode and rep-resentational content. Surprisingly, phenomenal salience associated with

conscious perception derives in part from cognition: the phenomenal

4 The distinction between pure and impure representationalism is made by Chalmers,op. cit. The term ‘‘psychological mode’’ is John Searle’s (1983). Chalmers speaks ofa ‘‘manner of representation’’.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 95

Page 4: Wu Conscious Attention

salience of an attended object correlates with one’s perceptual-based

demonstrative thought about it, specifically a demonstrative awarenessthat one is attending to that object. To put it another way, an attended

object is phenomenally salient to me because attention to it anchors mydemonstrative thoughts about it. This proposal yields a unified account

of synchronic and diachronic salience although within limits. Theaccount provides a blueprint for reductive representationalism about

phenomenal salience, not a full vindication of it. The reason is that tothe extent that perceptual-based demonstrative thoughts make a di!er-

ence to conscious experience, this derives in part from the phenomenalcharacter of the perceptual basis. Nevertheless, if the account I presentis correct, the phenomenon of conscious attention adds no further chal-

lenge for reductive representationalism beyond the extant challengesraised by the non-attentional phenomenal character of perception.5

Finally in section 5, I consider one consequence of the account inrespect of the role of conscious experience in demonstrative reference. In

an important discussion, John Campbell has argued that conscious atten-tion is necessary for demonstrative thought. I argue that while conscious

perception may be necessary for demonstrative thought, phenomenal sal-ience is not. Rather, demonstrative thought explains phenomenal salienceand not the other way round. Indeed, both are effects of a common

cause: the subject’s activity of perceptually selecting a specific object.

2. Varieties of Attention

Attention is a highly complex phenomenon, and to adequately identify

our explanatory target, we need five distinctions: (1) the attentionalprocess versus product, i.e. the process of attending and the corre-sponding state of attention; (2) overt versus covert attention; (3) main-

taining versus shifting attention; (4) voluntary versus involuntaryattention; and (5) diachronic versus synchronic salience. (2)-(4) are per-

haps best seen as applying to the process of attending while (5) charac-terizes a state of attention.

(1) ‘‘Attention’’ can refer both to a process of attending or to its prod-uct, the resulting perceptual state. With respect to the process, we under-

stand attention as the selecting of particular perceptual inputs to informcognition or action. While psychologists are interested in a variety of

selective mechanisms in perceptual or cognitive systems, our interest is inthe subject’s activity of attending and thereby selecting specific inputs.With respect to the product, the idea is that the process of attending

yields a conscious state characterized by phenomenal salience. It will beimportant to remember that the process notion does not involve a

5 For another discussion of these issues, see Speaks (2010).

96 WAYNE WU

Page 5: Wu Conscious Attention

phenomenal characterization while the state notion can.6 I will account

for the phenomenology of states of conscious attention in terms of thenonphenomenal notion of selection, i.e. the process of attending (I will

speak of attentional selection to identify the process notion).(2) Overt versus Covert Attention: A subject’s attention to an object

is overt if the subject attends via movement that brings the relevantsense organ in a more optimal orientation towards the object attended.

In vision, overt attention involves movement of the eye or head so thatthe targeted object stimulates the fovea, the region of the retina that

yields greatest visual acuity. Attention is covert if it can shift indepen-dently of any movement.7 Cases of covert visual attention are typicallyillustrated by having the subject maintain eyes fixed on a given point.

The subject can still shift attention across the visual field.The Cocktail Party Effect illustrates both the capture of attention as

well as covert attention in the auditory domain. At a party, you areinvolved in conversation with the surrounding noise indistinct when

suddenly you hear your name mentioned in a group behind you. Theirconversation captures your attention while that of your group recedes

as you lock on to the new conversation, a shift that can quickly reverseitself. This effect does not require that one overtly attend; thankfully,covert mechanisms suffice. We can shift attention between different

sounds without moving our bodies. Similar effects can be found inbodily awareness and touch. Indeed, we can shift attention covertly

across sensory modalities, e.g. to attend first to what is seen and thento a sound.8 This is crossmodal attention.

(3) Maintaining versus Shifting Attention: A subject can either shiftor maintain attention on an object. The spotlight metaphor is helpfully

invoked here: we can move the spotlight to different objects or we cankeep it focused on a specific object.

(4) Voluntary versus Involuntary Attention: This distinction con-cerning the process of attention is given various glosses in psychology:top-down versus bottom-up; goal-directed versus stimulus-driven; vol-

untary versus involuntary; endogenous versus exogenous. I shall deploy

6 I think the subject level process notion should be understood as selection for action.This form of selection does not imply phenomenal consciousness. See my (forthcom-ing-a) for further details and Smithies (forthcoming) for a di!erent view on selec-tion. For further recent work on attention, see the papers in Mole et al.(forthcoming).

7 The surface of the human retina can be divided into a foveal (given a fovea about1mm in diameter) and parafoveal region that leads to di!erences in visual acuityand chromatic color perception. Given that overt attention involves foveation (i.e.allowing a specific object to stimulate the fovea), it would be easy to conflate thestriking e!ects of foveation for visual phenomenal salience. We must avoid this.

8 Thanks to Casey O’Callaghan for emphasizing the crossmodal case.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 97

Page 6: Wu Conscious Attention

a three-fold distinction that emerges from reflection on the volun-

tary ⁄ involuntary distinction. While the notion of involuntary attentionis appropriate for attentional capture, there are two forms of goal-

directed attention, one of which is intuitively voluntary, the other not.9

Perceptually attending to an object is often an action whether this

involves the subject’s shifting attention to an object or maintainingattention to it. Consider cases where a subject intends to shift attention,

overtly or covertly. Given one’s intention to attend in this way, attentionis a goal-oriented action, something voluntarily done. There are, how-

ever, non-voluntary goal-oriented shifts of attention. Here, the agentdoes not intend to shift attention, but in the course of his doing some-thing else intentionally, he shifts attention in a way that serves his goals.

The clearest case of this is saccadic movement of the eye during action(saccades), i.e., quick ballistic movements that happen between one to

four times per second. One can, using an eye tracker, follow the path ofan agent’s saccades, and the resulting pattern is intelligibly dependent on

the agent’s goals. Thus in a crowded room, an agent’s saccades may beby and large directed towards feet if his goal is to carry on a conversa-

tion about footwear while if his goal is to converse about jewelry, thesaccades will be directed to necks and ears.10 He does not, however,intend to attend in this precise way. Some claim that covert attention

precedes each saccade in order to program the movement of the eye;11 ifso, then many cases of overt and covert visual attention are goal-directed

though not explicitly intended. Moreover, we are not aware of each ofour saccades. We are typically surprised to learn about their frequency.

This suggests that the shift of covert attention associated with each sac-cade does not involve any distinctive phenomenology that we would

speak of as attentional.12 If so, much goal-oriented attention during nat-ural viewing, namely, non-voluntary covert shifts of attention, does not

exhibit phenomenal salience. The relevant forms of attention that elicitphenomenal salience are voluntary attention and stimulus driven invol-untary attention. More simply, phenomenal salience tracks both our

explicit acts of attending and cases where our attention is captured.

9 We could just as well speak of intentional and nonintentional attention. I use theseterms initially as evocative labels (psychologists invoke the voluntary ⁄ involuntarydistinction). The relevant senses are specified by the following discussion.

10 The classic demonstration of the goal-dependence of saccades is by Alfred Yarbus.For a recent discussion, see Land (2006). Yarbus’ eye tracing results are diagramedon p. 303.

11 Ho!man (1998). See Armstrong (forthcoming) for a recent review and di!erenttake.

12 I do not claim that saccades always fail to have e!ects on conscious perception northat we are fully unaware of them. Rather, there is no consistent phenomenal fea-ture that tracks our saccades, some way normal saccading is like.

98 WAYNE WU

Page 7: Wu Conscious Attention

(5) Diachronic versus Synchronic salience: There are two temporal

dimensions relevant to characterizing a state of conscious attention. Onthe one hand, an object that we attend to may differ from how it

appeared prior to attending to it. In this case, the difference in theappearance of an attended object is characterized relative to its appear-

ance in the past, and we have diachronic salience. The intuitive idea isthat we perceptually register an object’s becoming salient, a change in

how it is present to us over time. On the other hand, an attended objectmay di!er in respect of other objects in the perceptual field at the time of

attention. The attended object is accentuated or highlighted in contrastto co-perceived unattended objects. Here we have synchronic salience.

We can now say more clearly what the two forms of attention I noted

in the introduction come to. The phenomenon that James described is aperceptual attentional state characterized by synchronic salience of an

object typically arising from a voluntary process of maintaining attentionto it; the state characteristic of attentional capture is a perceptual atten-

tional state characterized by diachronic salience of its object typicallyresulting from involuntary shifts of attention. The associated processes

can be covert or overt. To simplify, I shall focus on covert processes.James emphasized synchronic phenomenal salience as the distinctive

phenomenal character of a state of conscious attention and it seems to

be what most philosophers have in mind when discussing consciousattention. I shall argue over the next two sections that synchronic sal-

ience must be explained by appeal to extra-perceptual factors, specifi-cally certain forms of demonstrative cognitive representations of the

object attended to. In other words, the phenomenal salience typicallyassociated with perception has a cognitive basis. The natural starting

point, however, is that conscious perceptual attention involves a spe-cific way its object perceptually appears. Can we account for syn-

chronic salience in terms of just perceptual content? The answer, I shallargue, is no.

3. Pure Representationalism and the Challenge of SynchronicPhenomenal Salience

While this paper presents a reductive account of phenomenal salience,non-reductivists can endorse my account of phenomenal salience while

maintaining that there are other irreducible phenomenal features.Indeed, in this section they have a temporary ally. I shall argue that no

pure reductive representationalist account of synchronic phenomenalsalience is defensible.13

13 In what follows, when I speak simply of representationalism, I always mean reduc-tive representationalism.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 99

Page 8: Wu Conscious Attention

All forms of representationalism endorse supervenience:

(S) Necessarily, for any experiences E1 and E2, if there is a

phenomenal di!erence between E1 and E2, then there is arepresentational di!erence between them.

As with (P) above, (S) can come in various versions restricted to specific

psychological kinds or modalities. In various forms, (S) has been the pri-mary target of anti-representationalist arguments. Anti-representational-

ists attempt to refute (S) by identifying experiences where there arephenomenal changes with no representational changes. The representa-tionalist responds by uncovering an unnoticed representational change.

Not any representational change, however, will do. The representationalproperty must in addition be ‘‘appropriate related’’ to the phenomenal

property. What the appropriate relation comes to is an open questionalthough reductive representationalists typically will require some

explanatory relation: the relevant representational change must bearsome intelligible relation to the phenomenal change.

To see why the intelligibility condition is required, recall ChristopherPeacocke’s (1983) example of monocular and binocular vision: whilekeeping your eyes fixed on some point before you, look first with both

eyes and then with just the right. One could argue that there is a phe-nomenal di!erence associated with the experience of depth but no dif-

ference in what is represented for it is the same scene visualized.Michael Tye responded that there are two di!erences at the representa-

tional level: first, the representation of depth is more determinate andsecond, we see a little more at the periphery of the visual field.14 These

phenomenal and representational changes track the switch between bin-ocular and monocular vision so they will covary in normal cases.

The phenomenology at issue concerns the difference in one’s experi-ence of depth, and this feature is plausibly accounted for by differencesin the determinacy of representations of spatial information of rele-

vance to computation of depth. The second representational difference,however, seems not appropriately related at all. After all, what does

representing more at the left edge of the visual field have to do withone’s experience of depth say in the center? Whatever intelligibility

comes to, it seems safe to say that the former will not contribute to theintelligibility of the latter. Had we only been able to appeal to the sec-

ond di!erence, I submit that the response would fail to save reductive

14 Tye (2002), p. 453; cf. the original presentation in Tye (1992). There is no mentionof the periphery of the visual field in the latter (p. 174). The addition does not bol-ster the defense.

100 WAYNE WU

Page 9: Wu Conscious Attention

representationalism—or at least any interesting version of it—even if it

identifies a representational property that covaries with the change inphenomenology. It is thus possible to save supervenience, (S), without

saving representationalism. Not every representational di!erence willdo. Representationalists must endorse the stronger:

(S*) Necessarily, for any experiences E1 and E2, if there is a

phenomenal di!erence between them, then there is a repre-sentational di!erence between them that makes the phenom-

enal di!erence intelligible (i.e. bears some explanatoryrelation to it).

Representationalist responses to attacks on (S) must emerge from(S*): the proposed representational feature must be intelligibly related

to the phenomenal feature. What intelligibility comes to is a big ques-tion, but it implies the following correlation condition: necessarily, if

an experience has phenomenal feature F then it has the representationalbasis R invoked to explain it.15 After all, how could the representa-

tional basis render the phenomenal feature intelligible if the latter canoccur without the former? In light of (S*), it will be su"cient to refutea proposed reductive account by showing that we can have the phe-

nomenal feature without the proposed representational basis. I shallargue that a pure reductive representationalist account of synchronic

phenomenal salience is unavailable.Chalmers suggested that the two red light case noted above might

pose the strongest counterexample to reductive representationalism. Inthat case, there is a phenomenal change as covert attention shifts,

namely a change in synchronic phenomenal salience, without anychange in the representation of the scene. To experience this sort of

effect for yourself, draw two black dots on a paper with sufficientspatial separation along a line, the midpoint at which one can draw across as the point of fixation. Holding the paper at a comfortable

distance while maintaining fixation on the cross, shift attention fromone dot to the other (one can do something similar with natural scenes).

Note two points. First, the effects are subtle and do not immediatelyinspire one to speak of a visual spotlight. Second, in visually perceiving

natural scenes, unless we are spying, we do not keep our eyes fixed;rather, we constantly move them. One might then doubt that there is any

15 Characterizations of reductive representationalism attribute to it commitment tobiconditionals of the form: necessarily, an experience E has phenomenal property Pi! E has representational property R (where R is the reductive basis of P). SeeChalmers op. cit., p. 156. In what follows, I shall frame the proposals I consider inthis form although I shall mostly ignore the right to left direction.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 101

Page 10: Wu Conscious Attention

phenomenal upshot of covert attention but recall the Cocktail Party

Effect where there is a striking phenomenal change that accompaniesattention. There are also covert crossmodal cases that are vivid such as

focusing on the soothing sound of the sea to lessen one’s physical pain.Thus, there is prima facie support for the Jamesian notion of synchronic

phenomenal salience. But can synchronic salience be a matter of how theobject is perceptually represented to be as per pure representationalism?

Returning to Chalmers’ case, a representationalist will need to findsome representational difference in how the lights are presented that is

intelligibly related to synchronic phenomenal salience. In fact, the rep-resentationalist can appeal to empirical work that shows that in respectof contrast, covertly attending to an object makes it appear of greater

contrast than it is prior to attending to it. Covert attention does alterappearances. Marisa Carrasco (2004) and coworkers found that in the

perception of contrast patches (Gabor patches), attention seems toboost apparent contrast from 3 to 6%. One can experience this e!ect

by examining fig. 1. The Gabor patches, when covertly attended to,appear to be of higher contrast than when unattended. This gives rep-

resentationalists an empirical basis to claim that there is a representa-tional di!erence of the right sort when attention is covertly deployed.

Carrasco’s finding suggests a representationalist notion of salience

upon which phenomenal salience supervenes. Focusing on contrast asthe relevant parameter:

(CON) Necessarily, for any object x and y in S’s field of view,

x is more salient* than y to S if and only if x is ofhigher perceived contrast than y to S (where x is repre-

sented as having higher contrast than y).

We do not have a true necessary condition here as an object could be sali-ent* along other visual parameters (see below). Still I believe my argu-ment applies to any of these and their combination, so I’ll simplify and

speak of contrast as giving a necessary and sufficient condition. Thus, anobject is visually synchronically phenomenally salient relative to other

visible objects if and only if it is more salient* than those objects.Unfortunately, this representationalist account fails: salience* is nei-

ther necessary nor sufficient for phenomenal salience. First, we can attendto the object of least salience* and thereby render it phenomenally salient

(e.g. a lower contrast Gabor patch versus many visibly higher contrastones). Greater perceived contrast is not necessary for phenomenal salience.Nor is it sufficient, for we need not attend to those higher contrast objects

that we simultaneously perceive; they are not themselves thereby phenome-nally salient. As per James, we can withdraw from and ignore them.

102 WAYNE WU

Page 11: Wu Conscious Attention

One might object that I am simply assuming that phenomenal salience

arises when attending to the object of lowest contrast and need not arisewith respect to an object that has the highest contrast in the visual

field.16 I agree that what happens in each case is an empirical matter, butthere are general grounds for taking my predictions to be true at least in

some cases. Recall (P): necessarily, S consciously attends to o i! o isphenomenally salient to S. For those who endorse the Jamesian meta-

phors, the relevant notion is synchronic phenomenal salience. Now if wedrop across the board the possibility of synchronic phenomenal salience

as invoked in my proposed counterexamples, it follows that it is impossi-ble to consciously attend to lower contrast Gabor patches in the face ofmuch higher contrast Gabor patches concurrently perceived and also

that there must be conscious attention to the higher contrast Gaborpatches as only these can be phenomenally salient.

Such restrictions are hard to maintain, for it means that a given con-trastive difference of a specific magnitude renders conscious attention

to a specific object either impossible or necessary depending on the dis-tribution of levels of contrast. There do not, however, seem to be such

general restrictions on conscious attention. Consider perception of nat-ural scenes. Our visual world is filled with objects that differ in con-trast, brightness, saturation, etc. Our capacity for conscious attention

to an object, and thereby rendering it phenomenally salient, is not inprinciple limited by the relative magnitude of these parameters

although attention can be correspondingly more or less difficult inspecific cases. It is then highly plausible that in respect of a scene of a

Figure 1: While fixating on any of the black dots, shift attention

to the gabor patch on the left. It should appear to be of the samecontrast as the one on the right. Thanks to Marisa Carrasco for

providing this figure.

16 Thanks to Hemdat Lerman for pressing me to say more here.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 103

Page 12: Wu Conscious Attention

sufficiently low contrast Gabor patch among much higher contrast

ones, one can consciously attend to and thereby render phenomenallysalient the former. So, the counterexamples stand.

Contrast provides a plausible, empirically grounded proposal thatfails to satisfy the correlation condition implied by (S*), but we can

generalize the point. Given any visual parameter that can plausibly beused to define salience* including parameters that have continuous

magnitudes such as brightness or (color) saturation, it seems that wecan always consciously attend to the object in the visual field that is

lowest in magnitude along that parameter. Similarly, we can ignore anobject of greater magnitude. For example, if the process of attentionalselection was shown to boost apparent brightness of the attended

object and thus literally act as a spotlight (this is speculation), it wouldstill be possible to render that object synchronically salient even if it is

not the brightest object in the visual field despite the boost from atten-tion (e.g., attend to a dark spot on a white wall). We can attend to the

least brightest object in view rendering it rather than the other objectssalient to us; moreover, we can ignore the brighter objects. Similar

points would apply to the possibility of boosting apparent saturationor, as far as I can see, to other visual properties that can plausibly fillin for contrast in (CON). Accordingly, phenomenal salience will not

track salience* where we give an account of the latter in terms ofvisually represented magnitudes like contrast, brightness, saturation

etc. It seems that no single or indeed disjunction of visible propertiesused to define salience* necessarily correlates with synchronic salience

as required by (S*). Indeed, the argument is plausibly extended toother sensory modalities: for each modality and transposition of

(CON) in terms of a suitable property represented in that modality(e.g., intensity of sound in audition), it seems possible to find counte-

rexamples of the same form where salience* does not correlate withsynchronic phenomenal salience. Thus, salience* does not explain syn-chronic salience.

There is, in any event, a serious difficulty facing any modality spe-cific account of synchronic phenomenal salience, namely crossmodal

conscious attention. We can not only render an object synchronicallysalient in contrast to other objects concurrently perceived within a

specific perceptual modality, but we can also render an object synch-ronically salient relative to other objects perceived in di!erent modali-

ties. Thus, I can attend to an object pressing on my palm and renderit synchronically salient as against other objects concurrently presentto me in vision, audition and so on. A represented feature specific to

one modality, like visual contrast, cannot provide an account of syn-chronic phenomenal salience of su"cient generality so as to explain

104 WAYNE WU

Page 13: Wu Conscious Attention

synchronic salience in other modalities or across multiple modalities.

We need a representational feature that can meet this generality condi-tion.17

There remains one representational property that might plausiblycorrelate with synchronic salience, namely diachronic phenomenal sal-

ience. Moreover there is a prima facie plausible pure representationalaccount of diachronic salience. What diachronic attention suggests is a

salient di!erence in the appearance of an object over time. In the typi-cal case, the relevant times are right before a shift in attention (t1) and

right after attention has shifted to an object, x (t2). Let us now charac-terize a related notion of salience, salience^, that highlights this tempo-ral dimension. It will be helpful first to characterize possible changes in

salience^ for the visual case:

(CHN+) Necessarily, for any object x perceived by S at timest1 and t2: for S, x at t2 is more salient^ than x at t1 if

and only if for S, x at t2 is of greater perceived con-trast than x at t1 (again, simplifying to focus only on

contrast).

(CHN<) Necessarily, for any object x perceived by S at times

t1 and t2: for S, x at t2 is less salient^ than x at t1 ifand only if for S, x at t2 is of lesser perceived con-

trast than x at t1.

(CHN0) Necessarily, for any object x perceived by S at times t1and t2: for S, x at t2 is equally salient^ as x at t1 if

and only if for S, x at t2 is of the same perceived con-trast than x at t1.

We can add for the sake of argument that this temporal contrast inappearance is represented in one’s current experience. We can then say

that x is diachronically salient if and only if x is more salient^ for thetime periods at issue (i.e. we are dealing just with CHN+). Given Carr-

asco’s results, this is a plausible representationalist account of dia-chronic salience. Since it also seems plausible that diachronic and

synchronic salience have a common cause, namely the shift of theattentional mechanism between two objects, we may expect at least

nomological correlation between the two.

17 Theoretical inelegance aside, can we give a disjunctive account of synchronic sal-ience invoking some preferred represented feature for each modality? This pro-posal, however, inherits for each modality the type of problems we noted for(CON) in the visual case.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 105

Page 14: Wu Conscious Attention

In the next section, I point out that the diachronic salience of an

object implies its synchronic salience, but in this section I show thatthe reverse implication does not hold and hence that the required

correlation fails. Still both are forms of phenomenal salience, and itwill be helpful to consider the current proposal carefully so as to map

out their interrelations. The initial problem with the proposal is thatgiven that (S*) presents the relevant condition, salience^ as used to

explicate diachronic salience is plausibly not appropriately relatedto synchronic salience. Salience^ is understood in terms of the

representation of a di!erence in the same object at di!erent timeswhereas synchronic salience is understood as the representation of a dif-ference between di!erent objects at the same time. Thus, even if the

current appeal to diachronic salience saves (S), (S*) is threatened.What we need is a synchronic feature plausibly grounded in a dia-

chronic feature. Perhaps we can secure intelligibility by considering thesalience^ of all objects perceived at a time? For example, in Chalmers’

two lights case, perhaps synchronic salience arises because the attendedlight is diachronically salient (more salient^) while the other light is not:

the light to which attention shifts will increase in salience^, the light fromwhich attention is moved will decrease. Let us also add to Chalmers’example a third light on which attention is never directed during the time

periods in question and which is of equal salience^ over time. Thus, thelight to which attention shifts is synchronically salient because it is the

only one that is diachronically salient (i.e. increasing in salience^) whilethe others are constant or decrease in salience^. Synchronic salience

derives from relative differences in salience^, roughly whether the objectsin question are diachronically salient or not.

To meet the generality condition noted above, let us recall crossmo-dal attention. In crossmodal shifts of attention, we can covertly shift

attention between objects as perceived in each modality, say from thesensation of pressure on our back as we sit to the dancer visible beforeus. Since visual contrast will not help us capture synchronic salience in

this case as different perceptible properties will be at issue in eachmodality, we can focus on changes in value in respect of salience^.

Thus, we need only consider whether there is an increase or not alongsalience^ however we define it. This leads to a fairly simple picture. Of

the three lights, the one to which we shift attention is synchronicallysalient in respect of the others perceived at that time because it is

diachronically salient while the others are not: it is the only onethat increases in salience^. This seems to me the most promising purereductionist account.

The problem remains that we are using a notion that refers tochanges across times to explicate a notion that applies specifically at a

106 WAYNE WU

Page 15: Wu Conscious Attention

time. When we maintain attention to one of the lights without making

further shifts of attention, the light attended to remains synchronicallysalient even if nothing about it changes over the relevant period of

time. Yet in the absence of any changes in salience^, the notion of dia-chronic salience doesn’t get a grip as that notion is tied to the percepti-

ble changes in an object over time. Indeed, in maintaining attention toone of the lights, the other lights also need not change in respect of sal-

ience^. So where attention doesn’t shift over time but is maintained onan object, there is no change in the diachronic salience of any object,

yet the attended light is synchronically salient. Moreover even in casesof perceptible changes over time, it is clear that a subject can maintainattention on an object and render it synchronically salient even as it

decreases in magnitude along any perceptible parameter andthus decreases in salience^ (think of focusing on the light as it fades to

nothing).18

I conclude that there is no adequate pure reductive account of

synchronic salience that satisfies our intelligibility and generalityconditions.19 For such accounts, (S*) is genuinely threatened. If a

representationalist wants to pursue a reductive account of phenomenalsalience, the only option seems to be an impure account.20 In the nextsection I argue for such an account.

18 In the second case, we might hold that if the light on which we have been main-taining attention decreases in salience^, then it is in that way diachronically salient.Thus, we can say that an object is diachronically salient i! it increases or decreasesin salience^. This won’t work as we can see in Chalmers’ two lights case. In shiftingattention away from one of the lights, its salience^ decreases but it is not diachroni-cally salient.

19 It is sometimes said that attention to an object renders it figure as opposed toground, a reference to figure ⁄ ground segregation in early vision, a necessary step inthe computation of visual representations of natural scenes. If we treat Chalmers’lights as actual objects, figure ⁄ ground organization must have already been com-pleted. If the appeal to the distinction is to do any work in characterizing salience,it must refer to some property that can be visibly presented. Stephen Palmerrecounts the phenomenological characterizations of Edgar Rubin who first dis-cussed figure ⁄ ground segregation. Rubin noted that phenomenologically, the figureappears to be a thing while the background does not (See Palmer (1999) p. 281!).This will not aid the representationalist since our case involves the presentation ofmultiple things only one of which is salient. The critical feature evoked by talk offigure-ground is spatial. Thus, Rubin noted that the figure appears in front of theground or appears closer to the observer. But again, these factors will not under-write phenomenal salience: unattended objects can appear in front of the attendedobject, can appear closer etc. The appeal to figure versus ground does not help.

20 As an anonymous referee has emphasized to me, (S*) has a di!erent import forthe pure and impure representationalist. In part, the impure representationalist hasmore leeway in what is available to meet (S*). I make use of this advantage inwhat follows. Thanks also to John Campbell for suggesting more explorationneeded here.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 107

Page 16: Wu Conscious Attention

4. An Impure Reductive Representational Account of PhenomenalSalience

The core idea of this section is that phenomenal salience is to beexplained not just by the selectivity of perceptual attention but also by

what we can call the selectivity of demonstrative cognition. This is partof an impure reductive account that appeals to a cognitive way of rep-

resenting the attended object as the relevant impure representationalproperty. What is surprising is that the phenomenal salience of a per-

ceptually attended object has its roots in cognition contrary to ourintuition that it is a purely perceptual phenomenon. My account begins

with recognizing that attending to an object is often a form of agencyand that in such cases, the subject is typically aware that she is attend-ing to that object. This awareness is (broadly) a cognitive way of select-

ing a specific object and provides the relevant representational propertyto give an impure reductive account of phenomenal salience. The

power of the proposal is that it gives a unified account of synchronicand diachronic salience.21

James’ own characterization in the epigraph emphasizes that atten-tion is often an action involving active selection: one takes possession

of an object in a way that requires concentration and effort while with-drawing from others. Consequently, the impure representationalist can

argue that an object is synchronically phenomenally salient because thesubject actively targets it rather than other concurrently perceivedobjects. It is voluntarily selected so as to make it available for thought

and further action. Voluntary attentional selection is an intentionalaction. We can then think of the process of attention functionally in

terms of intentionally selecting specific objects in this way.The impure account attempts to correlate synchronic salience with

a specific manner of representing a content, and the initial proposalspeaks of a perceptual attentional manner of representation. Yet

James’ point suggests that attention is not itself a perceptual mannerof representation but a response to what is perceptually represented.In speaking of the process notion of attention, we are not speaking

of selection as itself representing but as the subject’s response towhat is already perceptually represented. That is, we are speaking

21 A word of clarification is needed on my broad use of ‘‘cognition’’. The central fea-ture is the agent’s awareness of her attending to that object, a form of action-awareness I am calling cognitive so as to (a) emphasize its non-perceptual natureand (b) to emphasize its direction of fit. Perhaps further work on the phenomenol-ogy of agency will show that this awareness is a distinct form of awareness thatought to be separated from thought in some more narrow sense. I am open to thatpossibility; the central issue then is that such awareness is not perceptual. Ouractions, in the normal case, and especially our acts of perceptual attention are notthe objects of perception.

108 WAYNE WU

Page 17: Wu Conscious Attention

in the voluntary case of an intentional action of selecting, not of

representing (if the latter can be thought of as an action at all).Thus, an impure reductive account must identify something in

addition to attentional selection if it is to identify a relevant mannerof representation.

There will be worries in any event if we appeal only to attentionalselection characterized in functional terms, namely as making informa-

tion available for control of action and thought. After all, it has alwaysbeen controversial whether a functionalist reduction of a phenomenal

property is viable. We can make the worry concrete given the distinc-tion noted in section 2 between two goal-oriented forms of attention. Inoted that some goal-oriented forms lack any phenomenal feature that

is intuitively attentional, namely the frequent non-voluntary covertforms that spatially program or are at least correlated with saccadic

movement of the eye. These processes involve selection without phe-nomenal salience. This shows that attentional selection as such is not

sufficient for synchronic salience. Rather, it must be some specific formof selection. In particular, it is only with voluntary attention that syn-

chronic salience arises in goal-oriented cases. Thus if we aim for areductive impure representational account, we must explain the distinc-tion between voluntary and non-voluntary goal-directed attentional

selection. Specifically we must identify the nature of an action’s beingvoluntary such that we see why that property or some specific variant

of it necessarily covaries with and is intelligibly related to synchronicsalience. It seems plausible, however, that the account of an

action’s being voluntary moves the basis of synchronic salience toextra-perceptual factors. Voluntariness after all is a property of mental

and bodily actions. I will now develop this claim. The central idea isthat the relevant manner of presentation is demonstrative cognitive

representation, a manner that is made available by voluntaryattentional selection of that object.

Our starting point must be to understand what difference attention’s

being voluntary makes. While it will not be possible here to explainwhat it is for an action to be voluntary, it does seem that a necessary

feature of voluntary action is that one can be aware of what one is vol-untarily doing. In the case of voluntary attention, it seems that we are

typically aware of what we are doing. Indeed it is hard to find caseswhere voluntary attention and awareness of it come apart. In general,

when we voluntarily or intentionally attend to x, whether in directingattention to x or simply maintaining attention on it, we do so with anawareness that we are so doing.

We can leave it open exactly what this form of action awareness is,but treat it as a cognitive state in that it represents the world in such a

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 109

Page 18: Wu Conscious Attention

way as to be assessable for veridicality (it has, in Searle’s terminology,

a mind-to-world direction of fit).22 It is a state such that being in itmakes a di!erence to what it is like for the subject at that time, for it

accounts for the awareness that typically accompanies voluntary atten-tion. The initial idea then is that an attended object is synchronically

salient in contrast to concurrently perceived objects precisely because involuntarily acting on that object (attentionally selecting it) one is cogni-

tively aware of it as the target of one’s so acting.To elaborate the proposed account, we should recall two types of

voluntary attention: shifting versus maintaining attention. Take shiftingattention first so as to set it aside momentarily. The relevant contrastwith the voluntary case of visually shifting attention is the frequent

non-voluntary saccades we make as well as the covert attentional shiftsthat program or at least accompany them. When we first enter the

kitchen to make a sandwich, our eyes rapidly scan in a pattern that isintelligibly related to that goal, flitting between the utensil drawer,

refrigerator, counter, bread, etc. We need not be aware of the sequenceof eye movements and objects targeted. Phenomenal salience need not

arise. Contrast this to the case where we voluntarily shift attention inthe same order to these objects because we intend to shift in thatsequence. Whereas in the former, it is not the case that there is phe-

nomenal salience that tracks the shift in attentional selection, it is pres-ent in the latter voluntary case but initially as diachronic salience. That

is, each object to which we voluntarily shift attention becomes salient.Let us then move to voluntarily maintaining attention, for it is here

that synchronic salience is most clearly seen. I shall speak of this pro-cess of attentionally selecting an object as one way of anchoring one’s

subjectivity to it, specifically tying one’s cognitive awareness to it. Thisdependence of awareness on attentional selection suggests that the

awareness is demonstrative. In voluntarily maintaining attention to anobject, we are typically aware of what we are doing with respect to thatobject. Such demonstrative awareness is anchored to that object pre-

cisely because we have voluntarily selected it and only it among theobjects currently perceived. The synchronic salience of the object to the

subject is constituted by this demonstrative representation of that andonly that object at a time. What is salient is what one voluntarily main-

tains attention to and thereby demonstratively represents in beingaware of one’s so attending.

22 There is an assumption here that may be controversial, namely that the form ofaction awareness is not plausibly modeled as similar to perception. This pointdeserves more discussion, but many philosophers do opt for a non-perceptualaccount of introspection (see Sydney Shoemaker’s influential work, especially his(1996)).

110 WAYNE WU

Page 19: Wu Conscious Attention

The anchoring of one’s awareness of that to which one is voluntarily

maintaining attention is the basic limiting case, but as voluntary formsof attention are also goal-directed, other intentional states directed at

the attended object are often present and can contribute to the vivid-ness of the phenomenology. Voluntary goal-directed attention is the

selection of an object for the sake of further thought and action on it.In response to voluntarily attending to a specific object, the subject

actively thinks about it as opposed to other objects perceived, makesplans or deliberates about it as opposed to others, is aware of moving

towards and acting on it rather than others and so on. We can say thatthe attended object also anchors such broadly cognitive activity. One isin general then aware of what one is variously doing, activities that are

united by a common anchor: the attended object. To the extent thatthese states make a subjective di!erence to the subject, they do so

because the selected object rather than others is at the center of expla-nations of that subjective di!erence. That is, the subject is demonstra-

tively cognitively representing that object and not others concurrentlyperceived. Thus, the proposed account can plausibly meet the explan-

atory demand imposed by (S*): the selectivity found in synchronicphenomenal salience is intelligibly related to the selectivity of perceptu-ally-based demonstrative thought, namely that one is thinking in a

specific way about just that object in contrast to other concurrentlyperceived objects. Just as perceptually-based demonstrative thought is a

type of targeting of a specific perceived object, that specific objectanchors such thought. This notion of anchoring demonstrative thought

is the basis of synchronic and (as we shall see) diachronic salience.Phenomenal salience is constituted by anchored demonstrative

awareness, what I shall call the subject’s (perceptually anchored cogni-tive) activities. These activities minimally involve one’s awareness of

attending to a specific object but also to associated thoughts about thatobject given one’s attending to it. The salient object is just what occu-pies our thought in light of the process of attending to it. Thus:

(PS) Necessarily, for any subject S, object o perceived by S

and S’s (broadly) cognitive activities A: o is phenomenallysalient to S i! S attends to o (selects o) such that o

anchors S’s activities A (A involves demonstrative repre-sentations of just o).

Note that ‘‘attends’’ on the right hand side refers to a process of selec-tion which is functionally and not phenomenally characterized. The

characteristic experiential character of conscious attention, the salienceof an object to the subject, is then explained in terms of anchored

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 111

Page 20: Wu Conscious Attention

mental states and activities in which the subject partakes, states which

demonstratively represent just the object attended to. Thus the relevantmanner of representation is not attentional selection but rather demon-

stratively anchored cognitive representation of the object that dependson such selection. Since demonstrative thought is in its way selective of

specific objects, this manner of representation is intelligibly related tophenomenal salience.

The distinction between synchronic and diachronic salience is speci-fied using the framework given by (PS). Let us begin with synchronic

salience:

(SPS) Necessarily, for any objects o, p, q… consciously per-

ceived by S in modality M at t and S’s activities A at t:o is synchronically salient to S at t relative to p, q… in

modality M i! at t, S attends to o rather than p, q… inM such that only o anchors S’s activities A (A involves

demonstrative representations of o).

We can also formulate a crossmodal condition by dropping talk of aspecific modality M. Where we have the phenomenon that Jamesdescribed, the salience of the object at t implies that it and not other

objects currently perceived anchors demonstrative cognitive representa-tions at t. We can thus explain why non-voluntary goal directed atten-

tion fails to give rise to synchronic salience: it does not anchorappropriate demonstrative representations of o. The question is

whether anchoring is su"cient for synchronic salience, a question Iwill consider below, but first let us extend the account to diachronic

salience.In the last section, I noted a prima facie plausible pure reductive rep-

resentational account of diachronic salience in terms of salience^. Wemust, however, reject this account. The reason is that the diachronicsalience of an object implies its synchronic salience. That is, when I

come to render an object diachronically salient by shifting attention toit, that object is now also synchronically salient relative to other per-

ceived objects (although as argued above, the reverse implication doesnot hold). Yet the characterization of diachronic salience in terms of

salience^ does not entail (SPS). Rather, we need a uniform accountthat subsumes both forms of salience. (PS) also gives us the right

framework for diachronic salience whether from voluntary shifts ofattention or from attentional capture. It thus satisfies the generalitycondition noted in section 3.

Consider voluntary shifts of attention and the following notion ofdiachronic salience:

112 WAYNE WU

Page 21: Wu Conscious Attention

(DPS) Necessarily, for any object o consciously perceived by

S in modality M from t1 to t2 and S’s activities A:o is diachronically salient to S at t2 relative to t1 in

modality M i! in M, at t1 S was not attending to o, butS’s attentional selection shifts only to o at t2 such that

S’s activities A come to be anchored only to o at t2, i.e.A involves demonstrative representations of o.

Intuitively, the diachronic salience of an object to which we shift atten-

tion is that of its coming to occupy our thoughts by anchoring themwhereas prior to attending to it, it did not anchor those thoughts. Theshift in what our demonstrative thoughts target is what intelligibly

tracks diachronic salience in voluntary shifts of attention, namelychanges in the objects that are phenomenally salient over time. Notice

also that given (DPS) and (SPS), diachronic salience implies syn-chronic salience: if o is diachronically salient, then S’s activities come

to be anchored to o at t2 (rather than to other objects) and this is suffi-cient for the synchronic salience of o at t2.

Suitably understood, (DPS) also covers attentional capture. Recallthat attentional capture can be driven by the sudden appearance of owhere it was not perceived, and hence not attended to, at t1. Moreover,

the shift of attention only to o at t2 is driven in the way characteristicof capture, namely involuntarily. (DPS)’s mention of selection of o at

t2 covers both voluntary and involuntary attentional processes. The dif-ferences between voluntary and involuntary attention can be made

explicit by formulating two versions of (DPS), but I shall not do sohere. The fundamental point is that (PS), with its invocation of

anchoring and demonstrative representation, provides a uniform frame-work to explain both diachronic and synchronic salience in its volun-

tary and involuntary manifestations.We were interested in phenomenal salience as associated with con-

scious perception and now we are told that salience has its roots partly in

demonstrative cognitive awareness of that to which we are attending.The account may seem overly cognitive. But why are we so sure that the

original phenomenon was purely perceptual in the sense of ruling out acognitive component? Despite the ease with which we can get someone to

acknowledge the existence of phenomenal salience, I disagree with Jamesthat it is obvious and with those who think it is relatively clear what con-

scious attention is. The results of the last section suggested that while wemay concur on cases where phenomenal salience arises, we cannot findan adequate pure representational account. The case changes when we

consider impure accounts, but what tracks phenomenal salience is anawareness that one is attending to the object in question or otherwise

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 113

Page 22: Wu Conscious Attention

demonstratively thinking about it. Indeed, recall the example of shifting

attention between two black dots offered to elicit your intuitions aboutsynchronic salience. Given the task instructions, namely to explicitly

attend to one object, then to the other and to reflect on the experience ofso doing, one is exemplifying the cognitive awareness I have emphasized.

Synchronic salience is apparent to us in this example precisely becausethe nature of the task encourages the required form of cognition.23

Yet if extra-perceptual features are central to accounting for phe-nomenal salience, why are philosophers so confident in attributing syn-

chronic salience as solely a property of perception? There are, ofcourse, the cited effects of attention on perception as in Carrasco’sresults, but none of these covary in the required way with phenomenal

salience (the crossmodal case brings this out effectively). Moreover,even if philosophers tend not to question this attribution, some cogni-

tive scientists I have informally polled do. The dispute, in any event,will not be settled by dueling introspective reports. While James was

right about many things, the obviousness of the nature of attentionwas not one of them. The account I have provided explains the lack of

uniformity as reflecting uncertainty as to whether the feature is tied toperception or cognition precisely because both are involved and inter-twined. After all, given that my account of synchronic salience high-

lights the role of demonstrative thought and given the dependence ofsuch thought on voluntary perceptual attention, we can explain why

reflection on conscious attention may give different answers, dependingon how one weighs these contributions. On the one hand, we may

emphasize the perceptual aspect, one’s perceptually selecting an object;on the other, we may emphasize the cognitive, demonstrative core that

secures our talk of focusing on that specific object. Given the tight con-nection between the two in conscious attention, the noted lack of uni-

formity among theorists is intelligible, even expected.Let us take stock of impure representationalism by returning to

the question whether anchored representations are sufficient for

23 This paragraph is prompted by comments from an anonymous referee. The refereeraises an additional query: isn’t it intuitive that animals that are not capable of thesort of action awareness or demonstrative thought invoked above neverthelessexperience phenomenal salience? I agree that any creature capable of action mustbe capable of attention in the process sense (for an argument for this, see my forth-coming), but it is not obvious to me that they must have phenomenal salience.Alternatively, some animals may be capable of the required form of action aware-ness and demonstrative thought or at least thought that has the selective targetingcharacteristic of demonstrative thought (what we might call a cognitive deixis).These points remain to be explored, but there may be a more abstract specificationof (PS) that subsumes conceptual demonstrative thought and a more primitiveform of cognitive deixis as both exemplifying the cognitive targeting at issue here.

114 WAYNE WU

Page 23: Wu Conscious Attention

phenomenal salience. What we have learned is that an impure reductive

account cannot stop at attentional selection of an object for this is nota manner of representation but rather a voluntary or involuntary

response to what is perceptually represented, an activity that itself leadsto the relevant manner of representation, namely cognitive demonstra-

tive representation of what is attended to.24 This yields a plausibleimpure account of phenomenal salience that says more than (P) in a

way that elucidates the phenomenon.On my account, the demonstrative representation carries the bulk of

the explanatory role, for it provides the intelligible link between animpure representational property, namely the way certain objects arerepresented, and the phenomenal salience of what is perceived. Still, per-

ceptual consciousness remains essential to phenomenal salience, for thedemonstratives at issue are demonstratives that are grounded in ongo-

ing perception, demonstratives that are available precisely because whatis demonstrated is consciously perceived. Anchored demonstrative rep-

resentations make a difference to what it is like for the subject in partdue to this dependence on conscious perception. The phenomenology

of demonstrative thought will partly reflect the phenomenology of per-ception on which it is based. Where the relevant anchored demonstra-tive representations of an object are conscious in this way, then a

particular object consciously perceived is rendered salient to the sub-ject. Thus, (PS) does identify a su"cient condition given the perceptual

basis of the demonstrative thought at issue.At the same time, we see that an impure reductivist account is not

fully vindicated by (PS) as it stands since the notion of demonstrative

24 Rather than invoke the demonstrative manner of representation in cognitive states,might not the demonstrative be part of perceptual content, drawing on a view thathas been advocated by John McDowell (1994) and Bill Brewer (1999)? This pro-posal agrees that the relevant manner is demonstrative, but locates it in perceptionnot cognition. I cannot take this option. I agree with Gareth Evans (1982), asRichard Heck (2000) has interpreted him, and with John Campbell (2002), that toexplain demonstrative thought by emphasizing its relation to perception, we cannotthen appeal to demonstratives at the level of perception. Thus, I endorse an explan-atory aspiration that precludes invoking demonstratives in perceptual content (seenext section). Still how might one fashion an account appealing to demonstrativesin perceptual content? The most plausible, it seems to me, is this: where we attendto (i.e. select) X in perception, the relevant perceptual representation of X isdemonstrative. This captures the distinctive feature of perceptual attention at thelevel of content while giving up the project of substantively explaining the percep-tual basis of demonstrative thought. We cannot, however, then say that an objectis phenomenally salient i! it is perceptually demonstratively represented, for thereis the phenomenon noted above of nonvoluntary attention that does not yield phe-nomenal salience. Note that in cognitive science, there is talk of demonstrative-likeelements in visual representation, but this is attributed to early vision and is preat-tentive, i.e. prior to the deployment of attentional mechanisms (see Pylyshyn,(2001)).

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 115

Page 24: Wu Conscious Attention

thought that is deployed implies some perceptual phenomenal charac-

ter, namely that characterizing the perceptual state on which demon-strative thought is anchored. So the analysans as stated implicitly

appeals to some perceptual phenomenal character. This appeal, how-ever, is not an appeal to phenomenal salience, so the account is not cir-

cular even as it falls short of being reductive. The picture that isemerging is that at the level of conscious perception, there are what we

can call ‘‘first-order’’ phenomenal features, precisely those features thatrepresentationalists and nonrepresentationalists have been debating.

Perceptual-based demonstratives in cognition depend on a link to con-scious perception as exemplifying these features. Phenomenal saliencearises when conscious perception anchors demonstrative thought on

the basis of attentional selection of the right sort. It is just a higher-ordered feature built up from perception and thought, but it does not

add any further challenge to the reductive representationalist beyondthe challenge of explaining in reductive terms the first-order phenome-

nal features of perceptual states. Still a reductionist account of phe-nomenal salience will be fully vindicated only to the extent that the

phenomenal character associated with a given perceptual experience ofo necessary for demonstrative thought about o can be given a reductivecharacterization. This returns us to the ongoing debates about repre-

sentationalism and perceptual consciousness that cannot be settledhere. It will be enough to have the framework for explaining conscious

attention as given by (PS), a framework available to reductive andnonreductive representationalists.

Demonstrative thought is an important part of the explanation ofphenomenal salience. Yet on some accounts of demonstrative thought,

this puts the cart before the horse, for they claim that phenomenal sal-ience explains the possibility of demonstrative thought. In the last sec-

tion I shall briefly discuss the proposed order of dependence.

5. Conscious Attention and Demonstrative Thought

John Campbell has argued that perceptual attention to an object isnecessary for demonstrative thought about it or at least the initial

demonstrative targeting of such thought (we can disengage attentionafter the initial selection as when I continue to think about that object

after it disappears from view). On this point I agree, but Campbellemphasizes that the form of attention here must be conscious percep-tual attention to the object.25 This is vividly brought out in his example

of a ‘‘sea of faces’’:

25 For another, di!erent, argument for this claim, see Smithies (2010).

116 WAYNE WU

Page 25: Wu Conscious Attention

you and I are sitting at a dinner table with a large number of

people around and you make a remark to me about ‘‘thatwoman’’. There are a lot of people around; I can’t yet visually

single out which one you mean. So on anyone’s account, I donot yet know which woman you are talking about.

To know who is referred to as ‘‘that woman’’, to be able to understand

the demonstrative, one must visually single out that woman, i.e. attendto her. But Campbell goes on to add that one must ‘‘experientially

highlight’’ that person in the sea of faces and this suggests synchronicphenomenal salience.

To say that we can think demonstratively about an object only if we

at some point consciously attend to it is to say that the object must bephenomenally salient. Indeed, James’ characterization suggests that

synchronic salience is the notion needed to explain demonstrativethought since this is thought that can select a specific object among a

multitude of concurrently presented objects. In contrast, the explanationI have given of synchronic salience implicitly deploys demonstrative

reference to the attended object in an account of anchoring. Thus, syn-chronic salience cannot explain how demonstrative thought is possible.The order of explanation is reversed.

Two further possibilities might be thought available to cash out theclaim that conscious perceptual attention is necessary for demonstrative

thought. On the one hand, in the visual case we have noted that overtattention to an object does make a difference to how the object percep-

tually appears. On the other hand, we have noted that there is the dis-tinct notion of diachronic phenomenal salience.

We can quickly dispose of the proposal that overt attention to anobject is necessary for demonstrative thinking about it because we can

think demonstratively about an object that we are covertly attending toas the Cocktail Party effect shows. Consider as well foveal vision. Oneway to show how an overtly attended object is highlighted relative to

an unattended object is to note the difference between foveal and par-afoveal vision. But visually-based demonstrative thought about an

object does not require that that we foveate that object. So overt atten-tion to an object does not identify a necessary condition on demonstra-

tive thought. The other possibility is that the diachronic salience of anobject is necessary for demonstrative thought about it. But this is not

so, for one can maintain attention to an object and think demonstra-tively about it even as it becomes less prominent over time, say as itslowly fades to nothing, or when it does not change at all.

Campbell is right that attention at some point to a particular is nec-essary for perceptually-based demonstrative thought about it. As noted

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 117

Page 26: Wu Conscious Attention

above, we can speak of the required form of attention here as in a way

synchronic: to think demonstratively about an object requires that ourthought be anchored by information regarding just that object, and this

requires that information from a specific object as opposed to otherobjects in the perceptual field be selected. As is clear from the last sec-

tion, I am also inclined to agree that demonstrative thought dependson conscious perception; that is, the selection at issue concerns

information that is presented consciously. Still, in granting all of this, itdoes not follow that conscious attention, i.e. phenomenal salience, is

needed for demonstrative thought.Phenomenal salience seems explanatorily idle. Let us return to

Campbell’s sea of faces case. You comment on a woman you point out

in a crowd, but I cannot identify her, the crowd appearing as a sea offaces. As I want to understand who it is you speak of, I intend to visu-

ally attend to the woman you point to. Now, I agree with Campbellthat in this case, until I have attentionally selected the woman, I cannot

demonstratively think about her. Thus, I cannot form an intention witha demonstrative content, namely to visually attend to that woman. My

way of identifying the target of attention must be descriptive: I intendto visually attend to the woman you refer to. Nevertheless, I can ulti-mately succeed in targeting the specific person, and this is how an

underlying mechanism might go. Perhaps you describe her further tome to help me identify the relevant person and this description informs

my intention. After forming the descriptive intention, my attentionalsystem shifts to the object that satisfies the description (via top-down

e!ects on information processing). This is a form of goal-directedattention that leads to informational selection where the visual system

(i.e. the ‘‘subpersonal’’), driven by some ‘‘description’’ of the target,identifies it and prioritizes information from it to anchor thought and

action. Once the woman is perceptually selected, it seems that undernormal conditions I now intend to attend to that woman, specificallyto maintain attention on her. I have come to think demonstratively

about her. She is only at that point, I claim, phenomenally salient tome.

Yet all that seems to be required to move from the descriptive to thedemonstrative intention is consciously given inputs and a goal-directed

mechanism of selection (the process notion of attention) that allowscertain information to control and anchor thought. It is not clear what

is missing in this generative story that synchronic phenomenal saliencewould provide. Notice as well that typically, one will immediately fove-ate the targeted object in a sea of faces and this will lead to changes in

visual appearance after demonstrative thought is secured. Thus, ‘‘fove-ational’’ highlighting is typically concomitant with perceptually-based

118 WAYNE WU

Page 27: Wu Conscious Attention

demonstrative thought, but on my account such foveational effects as

well as phenomenal salience and demonstrative thought are differenteffects of a common cause: attentional selection. When I am in a posi-

tion to have the demonstrative intention, the object is then synchroni-cally salient to me. Phenomenal salience, and thus conscious attention,

does not play a causal role in grounding demonstrative thought.Strikingly, James’ original characterization of attention, centered on

thought, also provides the explanatory tools to account for the experi-ence of attention to perceived objects. The phenomenal salience of per-

ceived objects, and hence our consciously attending to them, depends onthose objects anchoring thought. And since this thought is demonstra-tive thought grounded in conscious perception, we can understand why

the phenomenology has seemed so closely tied to perception as to leadus to ignore the cognitive component. But perhaps the close connections

between cognition, perception, and action should not surprise us, forthey are all intertwined and attention often serves as a common thread.26

Bibliography

Armstrong, Katherine (forthcoming) ‘‘Covert Spatial Attention and

Saccade Planning,’’ in C. Mole, D. Smithies and W. Wu eds.(forthcoming).

Brewer, Bill (1999) Perception and Reason. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.

Campbell, John (2002) Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

Carrasco, Maria, et al. (2004) ‘‘Attention Alters Appearance,’’ NatureNeuroscience 7: 308–313.

Chalmers, David (2004) ‘‘The Representational Character of

Experience.’’ The Future for Philosophy. B. Leiter. Oxford, OxfordUniversity Press: 153–181.

26 I am very grateful to an anonymous referee whose comments led to numerousimprovements to the paper. Earlier versions were presented to the ConsciousnessDiscussion Group at the Center for the Neural Basis of Cognition, CMU, at theAssociation for the Scientific Study of Consciousness meeting (Oxford, UK), at theDepartment of Philosophy, Ohio State, and to Marlene Behrmann’s group, Dept.of Psychology, CMU, all in the summer of 2006. I’m grateful to the audience ateach venue for questions and comments and especially to Sarah Schomstein andHemdat Lerman for discussion and to Kate Humphreys for bringing Carrasco’sarticle to my attention. James Genone gave helpful feedback as a commentator asdid members of the audience in a colloquium presentation at the Central DivisionMeeting of the APA in 2008. Carolyn Suchy-Dicey recently provided useful writtenfeedback. Finally, special thanks to John Campbell, Casey O’Callaghan, SusannaSchellenberg, and Declan Smithies for very helpful suggestions on the manuscriptat various stages.

WHAT IS CONSCIOUS ATTENTION? 119

Page 28: Wu Conscious Attention

Cherry, E. Colin (1953) ‘‘Some Experiments on the Recognition of

Speech, with One and with Two Ears,’’ Journal of the AcousticalSociety of America, 25: 975–9.

Evans, Gareth (1982) The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford Uni-versity Press.

Heck Jr., Richard G. (2000) ‘‘Nonconceptual Content and the ‘Spaceof Reasons’.’’ Philosophical Review. 109 (4): 483–523.

Ho!man, James (1998) ‘‘Visual Attention and Eye Movements,’’ in H.Pashler ed. Attention. Hove: Psychology Press, pp. 119–53.

James, William (1890) Principles of Psychology, volume 1. New York:Henry Holt and Co.

Land, Michael. F. (2006) ‘‘Eye Movements and the Control of Action in

Everyday Life,’’ Progress in Retinal and Eye Research. 25: 296–324.McDowell, John (1994) Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard Univer-

sity Press.Mole, Chris, Smithies, Declan and Wayne Wu (forthcoming) Attention:

Philosophical and Psychological Essays. New York: Oxford Univer-sity Press.

Palmer, Stephen (1999) Vision Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.Peacocke, Christopher (1983) Sense and Content. Oxford: Oxford Uni-

versity Press.

Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Shoemaker, Sydney (1994) ‘‘Self Knowledge and ‘Inner Sense’,’’ Philos-ophy and Phenomenological Research. 54: 249–314.

Smithies, Declan (2010) ‘‘What is the Role of Consciousness inDemonstrative Thought?’’, The Journal of Philosophy.

—— (forthcoming) ‘‘Attention is Rational-Access Consciousness,’’ inC. Mole, D. Smithies and W. Wu eds. (forthcoming).

Speaks, Je! (2010) ‘‘Attention and Intentionalism,’’ PhilosophicalQuarterly. 60: 325–42.

Tye, Michael (1992) ‘‘Visual Qualia and Visual Content,’’ in T. Crane,

ed., The Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress. pp. 158–176.

—— (2002) ‘‘Visual Qualia and Visual Content,’’ in D. Chalmers ed.,Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford:

Oxford University Press.Wu, Wayne (forthcoming-a) ‘‘Attention as Selection for Action’’ in

C. Mole, D. Smithies and W. Wu eds. (forthcoming).—— (forthcoming-b) ‘‘Confronting Many-Many Problems: Attention

and Agentive Control,’’ Nous.

120 WAYNE WU