bekoff 2002_animal reflections

1
Marc Bekoff R esearchers are interested in animal awareness because they are curious to discover what animals might know about themselves. There are, however, long- held and polarized views about the degree of self-awareness in animals. Some people believe that only great apes have ‘rich’ notions of self — knowing who they are and/or having a ‘theory of mind’, which means being able to infer the states of minds of others — whereas others argue that it is methodologi- cally too difficult to address this question because animal (like human) minds are sub- jective and private. Many in this latter category do not attribute any sense of self to animals other than humans, and some, dismissing behavioural and neurobiological research on animal cognition, wonder whether animals are conscious of anything at all. What might animals know about them- selves? Most studies of animal self-awareness have been narrowly paradigm-driven. The ‘red spot’ technique was first used by Gordon Gallup to study animal self-awareness in chimpanzees; it and variations have been used on great apes and monkeys, as well as on a few dolphins and elephants. For primates, a spot is placed on the forehead of an anaes- thetized individual and self-directed move- ments towards the spot are scored after he or she awakens and catches sight of themselves in a mirror, a high score indicating the pres- ence of some degree of self-awareness. But in some cases, the data are derived from tests on small numbers of individuals, many of whom fail it because they do not make self-directed movements towards the spot. Those who pass the test might not be representative of wild relatives because they have had extensive human contact and previous experience with mirrors, factors that might influence their trainability and willingness to use a mirror. Those who fail the test might show some sense of ‘self’ in other contexts, and other individual differences might also play a role. Laboratory experiments can overlook the fact that many animals have evolved in com- plex webs characterized by variable social, sensory and other environmental features. A single technique based solely on visual cues is not the only valid test of self-awareness because many animals regularly use sensory modalities other than vision, either singly or together. Most wild animals do not know what they look like — although birds can acquire information about their plumage colour from reflections in drinking water — but they seem to know what they sound or smell like. Many birds distinguish their own from others’ songs and numerous mammals discriminate their own from others’ scents. Some rodents use odour to distinguish ‘self’ from ‘other’; they preferentially associate or play with those who smell like them, or shun individuals who smell like them to avoid inbreeding. Discriminating between ‘own’ and ‘other’ is not necessarily an indication of self- awareness, but in most cases we don’t know if it is or isn’t. Although no one has suggested that birds or rodents are self-aware to the degree that chimpanzees might be, we do not know precisely what these animals know about themselves. We must be careful neither to imbue animals with unknown cognitive capacities nor to rob them of skills that they might possess. Researchers often dismiss non-primates when they investigate self-awareness. Social carnivores, such as grey wolves, who live in closely knit, orderly and efficient packs, could turn out to have well-developed self-aware- ness. Wolves engage in coordinated hunts and rear their young communally. Analyses of the behaviour patterns of individual wolves during these (and other) activities show that they have at least some awareness of what they are doing, what others are doing, and where each is located spatially. Similar observations have been compiled for other species. Comparative data suggest that if we rely solely on mirror studies, we have been look- ing for self in the wrong places and on the wrong faces. The evidence also indicates that no other animal has the same degree of self as that possessed by most humans (an ‘I-ness’ or ‘I-self’, perhaps mediated by language). On the basis of traditional measures, many animals appear to have a sense of ‘body-ness’ or ‘mine-ness’, but not a sense of ‘I-ness.’ Answers to challenging questions about self-awareness have wide-ranging conse- quences because they are often used by researchers and lawyers as a litmus test for defending the sorts of treatments to which animals can be ethically subjected. However, it is not clear that self-awareness or other cognitive capacities should be used for such decisions. Some argue that a sense of ‘I-ness’ is morally relevant and necessary for experi- encing pain. But even if an animal does not know ‘who’ she is, this does not mean she cannot feel that ‘something painful is hap- pening to this body’. Even though the experi- ence of pain might not be the same across species, individuals of different species can still suffer their own type or version of pain. Self-awareness is not a reliable test for an objective assessment of well-being. The concept of animal self-awareness remains open to different interpretations, but we will probably learn more about the mysteries of ‘self’ and ‘body-ness’ by using non-invasive neuroimaging techniques in combination with cognitive ethological stud- ies. If we look at ‘self-awareness’ as ‘body- awareness’, we might also discover more about how animals think and the perceptual and neurobiological processes underlying various cognitive capacities. Darwin’s ideas about evolutionary continuity, together with empirical data (‘science sense’) and common sense, caution against the unyielding claim that humans — and perhaps other great apes and cetaceans — are the only species in which some sense of self has evolved. Marc Bekoff is in the Department of Environmental, Population, and Organismic Biology, University of Colorado, Boulder, Colorado 80309-0334, USA. FURTHER READING Bekoff, M. Minding Animals: Awareness, Emotions, and Heart (Oxford Univ. Press, New York & London, 2002). Bekoff, M., Allen, C. & Burghardt, G. M. (eds) The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition (MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 2002); see especially essays on self-awareness by Gallup, G. G., Anderson, J. R. & Shillito, D. J.; Mitchell, R. W.; Shumaker, R. W. & Swartz, K. B. Mitchell, R. W. in Handbook of Self and Identity (eds Leary, M. R. & Tangney, J.) 567–593 (Guilford, New York, 2002). Reiss, D. Nature 418, 369–370 (2002). Rilling, J. K. et al. Neuron 35, 395–405 (2002). Rilling, J. et al. Am. J. Phys. Anthropol. Suppl. 30, 263 (2000). Rilling, K. et al. Biol. Psychiat. 49, 146–157 (2001). Animal reflections concepts NATURE | VOL 419 | 19 SEPTEMBER 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 255 Awareness On traditional measures, many animals appear to have a sense of ‘body-ness’ or ‘mine-ness’, but no sense of ‘I-ness’. Social work: is the pack behaviour of grey wolves indicative of some degree of self-awareness? L. KENNEDY/CORBIS © 2002 Nature Publishing Group

Upload: who222

Post on 11-Sep-2015

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Marc Bekoff

    Researchers are interested in animalawareness because they are curious todiscover what animals might knowabout themselves. There are, however, long-held and polarized views about the degree of self-awareness in animals. Some peoplebelieve that only great apes have rich notionsof self knowing who they are and/or having a theory of mind, which means beingable to infer the states of minds of others whereas others argue that it is methodologi-cally too difficult to address this questionbecause animal (like human) minds are sub-jective and private. Many in this latter categorydo not attribute any sense of self to animalsother than humans, and some, dismissingbehavioural and neurobiological research onanimal cognition, wonder whether animalsare conscious of anything at all.

    What might animals know about them-selves? Most studies of animal self-awarenesshave been narrowly paradigm-driven. Thered spot technique was first used by GordonGallup to study animal self-awareness inchimpanzees; it and variations have beenused on great apes and monkeys, as well as ona few dolphins and elephants. For primates, aspot is placed on the forehead of an anaes-thetized individual and self-directed move-ments towards the spot are scored after he orshe awakens and catches sight of themselvesin a mirror, a high score indicating the pres-ence of some degree of self-awareness. But insome cases, the data are derived from tests onsmall numbers of individuals, many of whomfail it because they do not make self-directedmovements towards the spot. Those whopass the test might not be representative ofwild relatives because they have had extensive

    human contact and previous experience withmirrors, factors that might influence theirtrainability and willingness to use a mirror.Those who fail the test might show somesense of self in other contexts, and otherindividual differences might also play a role.

    Laboratory experiments can overlook thefact that many animals have evolved in com-plex webs characterized by variable social, sensory and other environmental features. Asingle technique based solely on visual cues is not the only valid test of self-awarenessbecause many animals regularly use sensorymodalities other than vision, either singly ortogether. Most wild animals do not know whatthey look like although birds can acquireinformation about their plumage colour fromreflections in drinking water but they seemto know what they sound or smell like. Manybirds distinguish their own from others songsand numerous mammals discriminate theirown from others scents. Some rodents useodour to distinguish self from other; theypreferentially associate or play with those who smell like them, or shun individuals whosmell like them to avoid inbreeding.

    Discriminating between own andother is not necessarily an indication of self-awareness, but in most cases we dont know ifit is or isnt. Although no one has suggestedthat birds or rodents are self-aware to thedegree that chimpanzees might be, we do not know precisely what these animals know about themselves. We must be carefulneither to imbue animals with unknowncognitive capacities nor to rob them of skillsthat they might possess.

    Researchers often dismiss non-primateswhen they investigate self-awareness. Socialcarnivores, such as grey wolves, who live inclosely knit, orderly and efficient packs, couldturn out to have well-developed self-aware-ness. Wolves engage in coordinated hunts andrear their young communally. Analyses of the behaviour patterns of individual wolves during these (and other) activities show thatthey have at least some awareness of what theyare doing, what others are doing, and whereeach is located spatially. Similar observationshave been compiled for other species.

    Comparative data suggest that if we relysolely on mirror studies, we have been look-ing for self in the wrong places and on thewrong faces. The evidence also indicates thatno other animal has the same degree of self asthat possessed by most humans (an I-nessor I-self , perhaps mediated by language).On the basis of traditional measures, manyanimals appear to have a sense of body-nessor mine-ness, but not a sense of I-ness.

    Answers to challenging questions aboutself-awareness have wide-ranging conse-

    quences because they are often used byresearchers and lawyers as a litmus test fordefending the sorts of treatments to whichanimals can be ethically subjected. However,it is not clear that self-awareness or other cognitive capacities should be used for suchdecisions. Some argue that a sense of I-nessis morally relevant and necessary for experi-encing pain. But even if an animal does notknow who she is, this does not mean shecannot feel that something painful is hap-pening to this body. Even though the experi-ence of pain might not be the same acrossspecies, individuals of different species canstill suffer their own type or version of pain.Self-awareness is not a reliable test for anobjective assessment of well-being.

    The concept of animal self-awarenessremains open to different interpretations,but we will probably learn more about themysteries of self and body-ness by usingnon-invasive neuroimaging techniques incombination with cognitive ethological stud-ies. If we look at self-awareness as body-awareness, we might also discover moreabout how animals think and the perceptualand neurobiological processes underlyingvarious cognitive capacities. Darwins ideasabout evolutionary continuity, together withempirical data (science sense) and commonsense, caution against the unyielding claimthat humans and perhaps other great apesand cetaceans are the only species in whichsome sense of self has evolved. nMarc Bekoff is in the Department of Environmental,Population, and Organismic Biology, University ofColorado, Boulder, Colorado 80309-0334, USA.

    FURTHER READINGBekoff, M. Minding Animals: Awareness, Emotions, andHeart (Oxford Univ. Press, New York & London, 2002).Bekoff, M., Allen, C. & Burghardt, G. M. (eds) The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and TheoreticalPerspectives on Animal Cognition (MIT Press,Cambridge, Massachusetts, 2002); see especiallyessays on self-awareness by Gallup, G. G., Anderson,J. R. & Shillito, D. J.; Mitchell, R. W.; Shumaker, R. W. & Swartz, K. B. Mitchell, R. W. in Handbook of Self and Identity (edsLeary, M. R. & Tangney, J.) 567593 (Guilford, NewYork, 2002). Reiss, D. Nature 418, 369370 (2002). Rilling, J. K. et al. Neuron 35, 395405 (2002). Rilling, J. et al. Am. J. Phys. Anthropol. Suppl. 30,263 (2000).Rilling, K. et al. Biol. Psychiat. 49, 146157 (2001).

    Animal reflectionsconcepts

    NATURE | VOL 419 | 19 SEPTEMBER 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 255

    AwarenessOn traditional measures, manyanimals appear to have a sense of body-ness or mine-ness, but no sense of I-ness.

    Social work: is the pack behaviour of grey wolvesindicative of some degree of self-awareness?

    L. K

    EN

    NE

    DY

    /CO

    RB

    IS

    2002 Nature Publishing Group