boyd, richard - pity's pathologies portrayed

Upload: dudcr

Post on 02-Jun-2018

222 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    1/29

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/

    Political Theory

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/32/4/519Theonline version of this article can be foundat:

    DOI: 10.1177/0090591703258118

    2004 32: 519Political TheoryRichard Boyd

    Pity's Pathologies Portrayed : Rousseau and the Limits of Democratic Compassion

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:Political TheoryAdditional services and information for

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/32/4/519http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/32/4/519http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/32/4/519http://www.sagepublications.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://ptx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://ptx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://ptx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://ptx.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://ptx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.sagepublications.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/content/32/4/519http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    2/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    3/29

    by affluence, technology, and a highly refined social conscience? Liberal

    democracy rightly puts cruelty first, in the words of Judith Shklar, when it

    sides with compassion against a pitiless disregard for humanity.1

    And yet, ironically, this idea that democracy equals compassion has been

    advanced more often by democracys critics than by its defenders. In the

    midst of his criticisms, Alexis de Tocqueville admitted that

    in democratic ages men rarely sacrifice themselves for another, but they show a general

    compassion for all the human race. One never sees them inflict pointless suffering, and

    they aregladto relievethe sorrows ofothers when they cando so without much troubleto

    themselves.2

    Treating this general compassion as a vice, rather than a redeeming virtue

    of moderndemocracy, FriedrichNietzschediagnosedpity as a kind of demo-cratic sickness or nausea.3 Carl Schmitt similarly complained that the

    excessive humanity of modern democracies sapped them of the will to

    uphold the friend-and-enemy distinction even to the point of obliterating

    the concept of the political altogether.4

    Notwithstanding these and othernoteworthy criticisms of democracies as

    indiscriminately compassionate,paralyzed by their sensitivity to the pointof

    being kind when they should be cruel, and consequently cruel when they

    should be kind, remarkably few contemporary democratic theorists have

    actually appealed to compassion.5 As Nancy Hirschmann has observed, the

    concept of sympathy is not a major player in the world of political theory,

    which is generallymore concernedwith justice, freedom or rights.6 Influen-

    tial democratic theorists like Jrgen Habermas, Amy Gutmann and Dennis

    Thompson,andBenjaminBarber saylittle about theplaceof compassion inademocracy, and indeed seem suspicious of the role of affect or emotion in

    political life more generally.7 Among the few who explicitly make compas-

    sion central to democratic theory and practice are feminist theorists like

    Carol Gilligan or Joan Tronto who envision an ethic of care as an alterna-

    tive to an overly rationalistic emphasis on legalism or justice.8 And certain

    communitarian critics of liberalism seem to call for a more compassionate

    society, if onlyby implication,when theyfault the liberal individuals alleged

    indifference to fellow citizens and lack of deeper emotional commitments to

    public life.9

    This disconnect between our intuitive sense that democracies are, or at

    least ought to be, distinguished by their compassion and theapparent neglect

    of compassion by democratic theorists proper brings to mind the case of Jean-

    Jacques Rousseau. Rousseau is widely hailed for his commitments to both

    compassionandpolitical democracy.10 However, like so many other para-

    doxes of Rousseaus political theory, we should be wary of assuming that

    520 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    4/29

    these twovalues areeasilycombined with oneanother. His ambivalent treat-

    ment of compassion serves as a starting point for this articles twomain lines

    of analysis.Thefirst is todraw attentionto theproblematic, indeedpathologi-

    cal status of pity in Rousseaus system. This essay challenges the dominant

    scholarlyviewthat pity isa pleasurable sentimentthat inclinesus to theaid of

    our fellow man; instead, insofar as pity collapses back into self-preservation,

    it leads just as easily to aversion and avoidance. Rather than a pathway to the

    rediscoveryof our natural wholeness, pity serves as a dispiriting reminder of

    the profounddependency of thehuman condition.11 These ambivalent aspects

    of pity make it, in Rousseaus view, unsuitable for grounding the democratic

    political theory he develops in theSocial Contract(SC).

    The second and broader claim is that, following Rousseaus lead, we too

    should be cautious about trying to incorporate compassion more formallyinto contemporarydemocratic theory. If we think of liberal democracy notso

    much as a set of political institutions circumscribed by the limits of human

    sympathy, but rather, following George Kateb, as premised on an implicit

    recognition of moral equality, and in terms of the valorization of will and

    individual agency, as Richard Flathman has suggested, then Rousseaus idea

    of compassion comes up short on both counts.12 Although it is founded on the

    apprehension of the identity of our natures as fellow-creatures (semblables),

    even in Rousseaus account pity is inevitably bound up with relational differ-

    ences that are thevery antithesis of natural equality. Trying to make compas-

    sion central to democratic theory reifies the very distinctions it aims to over-

    come,inviting whatWilliam Connollydescribesas thedialecticalproblem of

    identity/differencewhereby anyvirtue creates a categoryof otherness or

    difference in those who do not possess it.13 Rousseaus treatment of com-passion also deepens the tension between human beings as actorsin the

    dual sense of playing a role and of agents engaging in conductand those

    who passively experience the emotion of pity only as reluctant spectators.

    In all these respects, Rousseaus treatment of pity underscores the moral

    discrepancies between compassionconjured up by the sentiments of the

    heartand liberal democratic demands for equal treatment and willful

    agency.

    II. THE NATURAL GROUNDING OF PITY

    In the Second Discourse (SD), Rousseau distinguishes two faculties

    anterior to reason that arepresent in natural man: self-preservation (amourde soi)andpity(piti), thelatter of whichinspiresin us a natural repugnance

    to see any sensitive being suffer, principally our fellow-men (SD, p. 95).14

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 521

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    5/29

    These faculties are presocial; they entail no necessity of introducing that

    [faculty] of sociability. Important for Rousseaus broader argument is the

    fact that these faculties are negative, in the sense that they are insufficient to

    incline us toward the society of others. Although they presumably imply

    duties toward other sensitive beings, including animals, the sum total of

    these issimplyto refrain fromharming or mistreating another(SD,p.96).

    This inner impulse of commiseration is dictatedby ourcommonsensi-

    tivity, rather than by the belated lessons of reason. We share this sensitivity

    with animals, which entitles them to be brought within the province of natu-

    ral right.Nonetheless, beingdevoid of intellectand freedom, they [animals]

    cannotrecognize this law (SD, p. 96). What begins asan otherwiseflattering

    contrast between menand beastsgives wayto a deeperproblem: foralthough

    all individuals possess this immanent sensitivity inclining them toward com-passion, they, like beasts, may be incapable of attending to its dictates until

    they possess those perfected faculties of intellect and freedom that Rous-

    seau denies natural man. In this rendering, pity and compassion toward oth-

    erscan bear fruitonly once theprocess of human developmenthas begun.We

    mustfirst acquire themoral liberty, self-consciousness, imagination, and rea-

    son Rousseau grudgingly acknowledges as necessary for us to rise above the

    level of a stupid, limited animal and to become an intelligent being and a

    man (SC, I, viii, p. 57).

    Being able to accessournatural sensitivitypresumes that we have already

    becomemoralbeings, possessing souls, free will, moral agency, andpresum-

    ably also some elementary faculty of reason (SD, p. 114). In order to feel

    compassion we must already have become moral agents. Yet as we discover

    later inRousseaus treatment, it is this very process of developmentitself,andespecially our acquisition of a highly cultivated faculty of abstract ratiocina-

    tion, that renders us incapable of any longer attending to this sensible voice

    within our nature. With reason come vanity, self-consciousness, and cruelty

    (SD, Note O, p. 222). Rousseaus treatment leads us almost immediately to

    doubt that modern society and its accomplishments will in any way allow us

    to make good on that faculty of pity for other sensible beings.

    Rousseauobserves,albeitin theform of a conditional objection, that com-

    miseration isobscureandstrong insavageman, developed but feeblein civil

    man (SD, p. 132). At least the modern condition allows the potential for, if

    not the likelihood of, this more developed social conscience. But under

    what conditions might this otherwise feeble voice of pity become accessi-

    ble to us? As we see in both the Second Discourse andEmile (E), whether or

    not we heed this voice of sympathy hinges on our ability to recognize andidentify with another. Pity hinges on the problem of recognition or what

    Rousseau himself calls identification (SD, p. 132). Yet thedifficultyof rec-

    522 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    6/29

    ognizing something of ones self in another is exacerbated by the growing

    inequalities of civil society. Because commiseration will be all the more

    energetic as theobserving animalidentifieshimself more intimately with the

    suffering animal, it follows that this identification must have been infi-

    nitely closer in the state of nature than in the state of reasoning (SD, p. 132).

    Natural sensitivity and other common features of natural equality are over-

    whelmed by manifold conventional differences, to the point where individu-

    als are so different from one another that they can scarcely recognize any

    common humanity beneath the layers of acculturation. This is a lamentable

    consequence of thegrowth of reason, which engenders vanity andturns

    man back upon himself, preventing him from identifying himself with the

    man who is being assassinated (SD, p. 132).

    Butif reasonbearssome responsibility forrobbing us of themore elemen-talability to identify with another by apprehending thenatural sensibility we

    all share, it also supplies us with the surrogate faculty of imagination. As

    Rousseau distinguishes, Imagination, which causes so much havoc among

    us, does not speak to savage hearts (SD, p. 135). Only once we have gone

    some distance along the philosophical anthropology of mankind can we

    identifywith another by imaginingourselves inhisposition, soas tocommis-

    erate with his pain or rejoice in his happiness. Although the details of this

    identification are blurry, Rousseau does suggest an important difference

    between theobscure andstrong sentiment of natural pity and that compas-

    sion that is developed but feeble in civilized man.15

    Presumably, the natural pity of the state of nature depended only on our

    ability to hear its gentle voice wholly within ourselves (SD, p. 133). How-

    ever, what Rousseau describes as compassion is no longer a sentiment con-tingent on our natural wholeness and self-sufficiency, requiring neither wis-

    dom nor self-knowledge. Instead, it is a force that, moderating in each

    individual the activity of love of ones self, demands that we look outward

    and consciously attempt to see the world through the eyes of another ( SD,

    p. 133). Imagination apparently moderates the influence or activity of

    self-love neither by conquering or repressing it, nor by restoring our natural

    wholeness, aswemight imagine, but bydrawing us further outof ourselves:

    To become sensitive and pitying,the childmust know that there are beings like him who

    suffer what he has suffered, who feel the pains he has felt . . . how do we let ourselves be

    moved by pity if not by transporting ourselves outside of ourselves and identifying with

    thesufferinganimal, byleaving. . . ourown beingto take onhisbeing. (E, IV, pp.222-23)

    Unlike the natural wholeness and self-sufficiency that Rousseau else-

    where recommends as uniquely commensurate to the natural goodness of

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 523

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    7/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    8/29

    insists that the compassionate presumably acquire something even more

    valuable. For thevery possibilityof tasting thesweetest human sentiments

    requires that some should suffer in order for others to experience happiness:

    Pity is sweet because, in putting ourselves in the place of the one who suf-

    fers, we nevertheless feel the pleasure of not suffering as he does (E, IV,

    p. 221).

    Maybe thebest evidence of this voyeuristic, pleasurable aspect of com-

    passion is Rousseaus stipulation that the sad spectacle of human suffering

    ought to be used, but not overused, as an object lesson in Emiles education,

    lest he become callous by an early overexposure to human misery. Rousseau

    raises as a possibility, and then summarily dismisses, the life of a Mother

    Theresa, who rushes from hospital to hospital and from sickroom to sick-

    room, as too likely to obscure human sentimentality: The object is not tomake your pupil a male nurse or a brother of charity, not to afflict his sight

    with constant objects of pain and suffering. . . . He must be touched and not

    hardened by thesightof human miseries (E, IV, p. 231). This isagain tosug-

    gest that human suffering should be attended to not so much out of a desire to

    relieve those who suffer but instead for the development of Emiles charac-

    ter.20 Describing human suffering as an object, sight, scene, impres-

    sion, picture, or spectaclerevealsit tobe,likenature, anobjectto bepor-

    trayed, instrumentalized, and manipulated in the interest of human conve-

    nience (E, IV, pp. 222, 226, 227, 230-32). Suffering is neither simply

    inevitable nor lamentable. It exists for the sake of sensitive spectators like

    Emile to develop their highest human faculties.21

    In fairness,Rousseau does appear to be genuinelymoved by thecondition

    of sufferinghumanity. That he shouldbe so intentto definecrueltyas thepre-eminent human vice testifies to his sentimentality and humanism. But in the

    end, human suffering becomes a kind of spectacle to be controlled,

    showcased, and manipulated for the edification of the few. Let him see, let

    him feel the human calamities, Rousseau admonishes (E, IV, p. 224). Like

    the syphillitics whose suffering becomes an object lesson for the prodigal

    son, sufferinghumanity exists for thesake of Emiles educationandeventual

    happiness, and not vice versa (E, IV, p. 231). All this seems bad enough. But

    Rousseau goes further still: whatever limited prospects we retain for human

    happiness can be attainedonly when, after immersing ones self in anothers

    misery, we return to our selves and experience sublime pleasure in the real-

    ization that we do not share the others misfortunes. Only this voyeuristic

    thrill can possibly make us happy with our lot. The resultant sweet sensa-

    tion of pleasure, according to Rousseau, is the negative, paradoxical versionof that frail happiness that consists only in the absence of suffering (E, IV,

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 525

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    9/29

    p. 221;SD, p. 132). Yet its very sweetness appears to be parasitical on the

    suffering of another, just as the contentment and status of the master rests on

    the subordination of the slave.

    Tragically, Emile can find the key to happiness only in viewing (but not

    actingupon) the sufferings of others. In part, this is theunfortunate corollary

    to Rousseaus pessimism: livingin civil society ensures thatwe cannot regard

    the good fortune of others without falling prey to the vices of vanity, envy,

    and jealousy (E, IV, pp. 228-30). Seeing another happy appeals to the lowest

    forms of our imagination. Yet the perversity of Rousseaus alternative is that

    while denying the vicarious pleasures of the friend or lover, who experience

    pleasure by partaking in the happiness of others, Rousseaus compassionate

    soul becomes a kind of moral voyeur. After imagininghimself in theplace of

    suffering humanity he achieves the heady rush of sweet relational happi-ness that comes upon returning to his own superior condition.

    IV. PITY AND PERFORMANCE:

    COMPASSION AND THE RELUCTANT SPECTATOR

    Rousseau repeatedly emphasizes the visual aspects of suffering humanity

    the salutary effects of witnessing it, if notof actingupon it.One must, he

    notes, have seen corpses to feel the agonies of the dying (E, IV, p. 226). At

    first glance, the theater promises an alternative to this view of human suffer-

    ing as a slaughter bench of history whose ultimate goal is to foster perfection

    and happiness in the sentimental few. In the theater, at the very least, the

    object lesson of human suffering may stoke the fires of human imaginationwithout requiring real persons to suffer: itis there that they go to forget their

    friends, neighbors and relations in order to concern themselves with fables in

    order to cry for the misfortunes of the dead, or to laugh at the expense of the

    living (Politics and theArts: Letterto M. DAlembert on theTheatre [LDT],

    p. 17).

    But this quote is also suggestive of how the theater may function as an

    escape fromeverydaymoralobligations.Rather thanprotecting an otherwise

    virtuous society from the corrupting influence of the arts, as Rousseau is

    often read, his criticism of the theater may also be taken as a further indict-

    ment of the lack of compassion in bourgeois society.22 In bourgeois society,

    after all, we are all actors and spectators.23 From the elementary songs and

    dances in the Second Discourse that give rise to vanity andaffectationwe are

    soon confronted by a world where tobe and to seem to be became two alto-gether different things (SD, pp. 149, 155). Living mediated lives in bour-

    geois society means that oursense of self comes only through theeyes of oth-

    526 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    10/29

    ers. We are constantly engaged in performance and dissimulation. As a

    microcosm of this imaginary world of performance, the theater epitomizes

    this alien,bourgeoisconditionof seemingrather than being. Thetheater,

    in the words of David Marshall, teaches people how to become spectators,

    how to act like spectators.24

    Despite theseapparentcontinuities between theworldof spectacleand the

    politics of the ordinary, the force of Rousseaus criticism rests on stressing

    the discrepancy between our moral position as spectators and our status as

    political actors in everyday life. Rousseau disparages the false sensitivity of

    average theatergoers whoaremoved by pity for those whosufferat thehands

    of a fictional tyrant while they themselves would aggravate hisenemys tor-

    ments even more if allowed for even a moment to take the tyrants place.

    Like bloodthirsty Sulla, so sensitive to evils he had not caused (and hencepresumably indifferent to those he has?) they aremoved by a love of human-

    ityin theabstractthat they areincapable of conjuringup in theparticular (SD,

    p. 131).

    Rousseaus examples of the tyrants Sulla and Alexander of Pherae sug-

    gest, optimistically, that even the hardest of heartsliteral tyrantscan still

    be moved by human suffering. And yet the very extremity of Rousseaus

    examples goes to suggest an even more damning criticism of the quotidian.

    Thefact that wesoeasily cryat this imaginaryspectacle implies a criticismof

    the sentimentality of modern civilization, where the cultivation of the fine

    arts takes the place of the more authentic natural sentiments of pity or com-

    passion. In our everyday conduct we are untroubled by our own propensity

    for cruelty. This gross disparity between the love of humanity in the abstract

    and callousness toward real particular beings in the here-and-now is hardlyconfined to the likes of Sulla and Alexander of Pherae. Modern compassion

    mayprove, as Rousseau suggestedit would, simultaneously developed but

    feeble. As moral spectators we unavoidably feel pity when we witness suf-

    fering, but in everyday life we are unlikely to act upon these feelings.25

    Even if we ignore Rousseaus complaints about these sentiments as

    effeminate or corrosive of civic virtue, this sentimentalism invites problems

    on itsownterms.26 No doubt theeasewith which we identifywith thetortured

    character, and readily imagine ourselves in her place, is due in part to the

    romance of the theater. When performed in the theater the suffering of

    humanity becomes dramatic, romantic, andsympathetic.By wayof contrast,

    Rousseau himself admits that the suffering of the mass of humanity is ugly

    (E, IV, p. 225). One danger of blurring the line between theperformative and

    personal dimensions of suffering is that misery comes to be seen as the stuffof fiction.Sufferinghumanitybecomes an abstract, imaginarycategoryiden-

    tified with charismatic actors rather than the particular individuals we know

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 527

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    11/29

    in everyday life. Insofar as the suffering of real human beings is never so

    glamorous, noble, or epic as its romanticized theatrical counterpart, we may

    become less able than ever to sympathize with it. The continual emotion

    which is felt in thetheatreexcites us,enervates us,enfeeblesus, andmakes us

    less able to resist our passions. And the sterile interest taken in virtue serves

    only to satisfy our vanity without obliging us topractice it (LDT, p.57). The

    pathologies of this kind of escapism are easy to anticipate. In everyday life

    we areactors in the sense that we pretend and dissimulate,but merelypas-

    sive spectators when the practice of compassion is actually called for. We

    lack agency and will. Worse still: like those animals that are reluctant to pass

    near a dead member of their species, real suffering yields a kind of aversion.

    We may flock to the theaters to viewthe heady rush of human suffering, trag-

    edy, and commiseration, but in our own lives, like Rousseaus animals, weavert our eyes and cross to the other side of the street. Leaving the theater we

    ignore the homeless outside the door.

    V. PITY AS AVERSION AND AVOIDANCE

    Rousseaus point hingeson themoralcontradictionbetween ourdelight in

    witnessing sufferingin the theater andour revulsion when confronted by it in

    reality. And yet this dissonance itself presupposes two mutually exclusive

    accounts of the moral psychology of pity. There is on the one hand Rous-

    seaus description of compassion as being thesweetestof sentiments.27 We

    feel an undeniable, vicarious pleasure in imaginingour self in theposition of

    another who suffers and then returning to our own more enviable position.Andyetthisnotionof compassion as being a pleasurable sensationone that

    persons mightselfishly seek outstands in stark contrast with theaccount of

    pity to which we have just alluded. Pity, in this other view, is among the most

    unpleasant of sentiments insofar as it reminds us that we, too, might sufferor

    even perish. Theissue is notwhether we aremore or less capable of attending

    to the natural voice of compassion in modern society; rather, it is the sub-

    stance of what those sentiments suggest to us that may prove most troubling

    of all.28

    Rousseau beginshis discussion of natural pity on a curious note by setting

    aside oneof themost conspicuous examplesof sympathy, Withoutspeaking

    of thetenderness of mothers for their young, andof theperils they must brave

    in order to guard them, only to posit the more ambiguous example of the

    aversive behavior of feral animals (SD, p. 130). Could his implicit rejectionof the analogy between pity and maternal affection be because to label this

    sentiment pity would ask too much of pity, suggesting the very fact that

    528 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    12/29

    Rousseau aims to deny, namely, the existence of some kind of natural socia-

    bility? Or because, in what becomes Rousseaus ironically Hobbesianworld-

    view, the care a mother lavishes upon her child is not in fact an act of natural

    sympathy at all, but simply thebiological necessityof dispensing milk belat-

    edly sentimentalized out of habit or convenience (SD, p. 121, cf. pp. 108-9,

    142, 146-48, 191-92n.)?29

    Rousseaus subsequent observations about the daily repugnance of

    horsesto trample a living body underfoot or theuneasiness of ananimalto

    pass near a dead animal of its specieshardly yield a society of simple souls

    eagerly rushing to theaidof others. Instead they aresuggestive of themecha-

    nisms of aversionor avoidance (SD, p. 130). Connecting pity with the lowing

    of animals in the presence of death does more than just highlight the prob-

    lems of a modern society where pity has been lost or corrupted. The deeperand more troubling suggestion is that aversion and avoidance may be rooted

    in the elemental sentiment of pity itself:

    [Emile] willbeginto havegut reactionsat the soundsof complaints andcries, the sightof

    bloodflowing will make himavert hiseyes;the convulsions of a dyinganimal will cause

    him an ineffable distress before he knows whence come these new movements within

    him. (E, IV, p. 222)

    This uneasiness when confronted by signs of our own vulnerability is

    enough to make us want to shun the suffering altogether. Rousseaus exam-

    ples of feral animals and the lowing of cattle entering the stockyards stress

    that pity has less to do with a compassionate concern for thewelfare of others

    than with the even more elemental sentiment of self-preservation.30 Rather

    than pity successfully moderating or regulating the activity of our self-

    love, as Rousseau suggests, his examples reinforce the notion that pity only

    collapses back into this most elemental Hobbesian faculty of self-preserva-

    tion. Moderating the activity of our self-regard is different from extin-

    guishing thatself-regard altogether. Whatever pity theseanimals feel is not

    for other dead or injured animals, but stems from therecognition of a similar,

    and indeed inevitable, mortality in themselves (E, IV, pp. 226-27).31 As

    Derrida notes,

    We neither cannor shouldfeelthe pain ofothers immediatelyand absolutely, forsuchan

    interiorization or identification would be dangerous and destructive. That is why the

    imagination, the reflection, and the judgment that arouse pity also limit its power and

    hold the suffering of the other at a certain distance.32

    Looking more closely at Rousseaus invocation of pity explodes the care-

    ful theoretical distance he seeks to maintain between solicitude for others, or

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 529

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    13/29

    pity, and self-regard,or amour de soi.33 Incapableof imaginingor fearing

    death in theabstract, animals cannonethelesssensetheirmortalitywhen con-

    fronted by its immediatepresence (SD, p. 130). Natural man would retreat in

    fear at the least prospect of suffering harm rather than risk the dangers of

    communingwith other sensiblebeings(SD, pp. 107,129). Far froma primor-

    dial dose of natural sociability, theemotion of pity makes Rousseaus natural

    beings less inclined toward society than even Hobbess emphasis on mans

    desirefor fameandrecognition,which may, after all, prove thestrongest psy-

    chological impetus of all for individuals to seek the company of others and

    departthe Hobbesianstateof nature.34 Ironically, then, itis by makinghis nat-

    ural psychology more purely Hobbesian even than Hobbes that Rousseau

    differentiates his natural condition from a state of war.35

    Similarly, although pity will dissuade every robust savage from robbinga weak child or an infirmold manof hishard-earnedsubsistence, this is only

    if or so long as, he himself hopes to be able to find his own elsewhere

    (SD, p. 133). This statement is proscriptive or negative (notice: this is not the

    same as the positive disposition which carries us without reflection to the

    aid of those we see suffering) as well as conditional. Whatever small mea-

    sure of self-restraint is imposed by pity (Do what is good for you with as lit-

    tleharm as possible to others) remains hostage to conditions of scarcity and

    to subjective judgments about the dangers of this forbearance to ones own

    self-preservation.Andyetby depriving natural manof thefacultiesof reason

    and judgment that Hobbes and Locke allowed him, Rousseau seems to call

    into question just howsubstantialare thekindsof mercythat pity might yield.

    Ultimately, pity does not so much moderate self-love as deepen and rein-

    force thenatural self-regardthat leads us toavoiddanger,pain,or sufferinginourselves and in others.36 So the very same pity Rousseau depends upon to

    dissuade natural man from unnecessarily harming another also discourages

    him from willfully intervening on behalf of another suffering being.

    This permeable line between natural sensitivity and self-regard is further

    blurred in Rousseaus example of the prisoner-spectator. Does Mandevilles

    prisoner suffer because of the intrinsic horror of a wild beast tearing a child

    from hismothers breast, breaking hisweak limbs in itsmurderous teeth,and

    ripping apart thepalpitatingentrailsof this childin thestreet beneath hiscell

    (SD, p. 131)? Or rather does his horrible agitation stem from the fact that,

    being imprisoned, he has no place to turn and hence cannot avert his gaze? It

    is significant that Rousseaus presentation of this pathetic image actually

    servesto redirect ourown sympathyawayfrom thesufferingsof thechildand

    mother and toward the prisoner-witness. We are asked to consider Whatanguish musthesuffer, when, being confined, this witness is forced to

    530 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    14/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    15/29

    Therearealso therequisite democratic values of individual will andpoliti-

    cal agency to be taken into account. At its best, pity may awaken our natural

    repugnance to seeing human misery. But we have seen that this need not

    incline us to do anything much about remedying it. Avoidance proves the

    unfortunate side effect even of the refined modern compassion grounded in

    pity that Rousseau elsewhere praises. In hisReveries(RSW), he tells of his

    initial delight in giving alms to a lame, homeless child he regularly passedon

    hiswalks. Andyetaftertimethis pleasure,having graduallybecome a habit,

    was inextricably transformed into a kind of duty that Rousseau finds oner-

    ous and takes special pains toavoid by changing his usual route (RSW, p. 74).

    So long as the act of compassion involves only the heart ityields the sweetest

    of pleasures. Once transformed into duty by habituation,as Rousseau alleges

    it must inevitably be, it quickly loses its charm and becomes burdensome:Constraint, though in harmony with my desire, suffices to annihilate it and

    to change it into repugnance, even into aversion, as soon as it functions too

    strongly (RSW, p. 77).

    Rousseau alludes to the special, permanent relationship that develops

    between benefactor and sufferer. Among the natural effects of the rela-

    tionship are that a single, heartfelt act of kindness engenders further obli-

    gations. Knowing this full well, however, Rousseau admits that he has often

    abstained from a good actionI hadthe desireand thepowerto do,frightened

    of the subjection I would submit myself to afterward if I yielded to it without

    reflection (RSW, p. 78). This suggests allsorts of thingsaboutobligation and

    dependency. One of the reasons Rousseau wishes to cultivate pity in Emile is

    to make him aware of his dependence on others. Imagination yields the rec-

    ognition that no single being is self-sufficient. Against all his best intentionsRousseaus portrayal of this dependency leads ineluctably toward a conclu-

    sion he adamantly denies: because all alike experience misery and misfor-

    tune, to be human is by definition to be dependent upon others. Looking

    beyond themirageof human autonomy suggestedby the liberal fiction of the

    rights-bearing individual, or indeed the Rousseauian rhetoric of the nobility

    of savage freedom, Rousseaus individual, rightly thinking, arrives at an

    almost Christian recognition of his natural indebtedness and the burdens of

    the human condition. Pity is, as Rousseau observes, a disposition that is

    appropriate to beings as weak and as subject to as many ills as we are (SD,

    p. 130).Still, beingaware of ones hypothetical conditionof dependency, like

    Emile, is very different than actually living up to the reciprocal obligations

    this would apparently impose upon us. Instead, dependency and obligation

    are moral duties to be fled simply because they are duties. Our lamentableconditionof natural andconventionaldependency canhardlybe improved

    532 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    16/29

    andis in fact only deepenedwhen we engender further obligations by help-

    ing others.

    Rousseaus criticism of the dialectic of compassion and dependency

    strikes familiar, contemporary chords. First, in our role as benefactors we

    shouldresist thetug of ourheartand withholdcompassion because it subjects

    us to additional, unwanted obligations in the future: whether it is jumping in

    to stop a crimeor only phoning thepolice,dont getinvolved lest youbecome

    further entangled. Andsecond, theaspiration to eliminate dependencyin oth-

    ers provides a convenient justification for denying those who seek our help.

    Better that we do the hard thing and refuse them now lest we render them

    dependent on us in the future.41 The awful paradox is that a life in which we

    studiously strive for autonomy and avoid forging dependenciesboth for

    ourselvesand in othersseems fully compatiblewithRousseaus account ofpity.

    More than just illustrations of his own misanthropy, Rousseaus discus-

    sion here underscores an important point about the moral theory of compas-

    sion. Inorder forcompassion tohaveany moral significance, itmust beheart-

    felt. We must actually feel compassion. Otherwise, one is simply being

    forced to perform actions that she experiences as onerous and alien. And yet

    if a kind action is done only because it is expected, or in the last resort, com-

    pelled by Good Samaritan laws, howcan oneexpect anything other than that

    it will be resented? Rousseaus discussion would seem to reveal both thevir-

    tues and vices of compassion. Compassion is admirable in that it transcends

    our ordinary rationalistic concerns with justice, statistics, or even utilitarian

    consequences. Getting to know just one family on welfare may do more to

    stir us than volumes full of poverty statistics. This explains why it is oftenhard to swallow the more abstract notion that charity to others around the

    worldmayhavemoresalutaryconsequencesthanhelping thoseweknow and

    seein ourown nationor community. Andyetif compassion is tobe dispensed

    only on a sentimental whim, or worse yet, withheld for fear of engendering

    further obligations and dependencies, it loses whatever power it might have

    as a source of democratic community.42 If forwhatever reasonourheartdoes-

    nt moveus, we may eitherfail toact,like Rousseau, or act onlyout of resent-

    ment for being required to play a role or honor an obligation we have not

    imposed upon ourselves.

    VI. PITYS PLACE IN THE DEMOCRATIC POLITY

    Imagining ourselves in the position of another creates challenges for dif-

    ferent groups. For the lower classes this imaginary flight of fancy is easier.

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 533

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    17/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    18/29

    consideration as fellow sensible beings. Judith Shklar has aptly noted that

    once anyrecognitionof theidentityof our natures hasbeen obscured,cruelty

    cannot be far behind.44

    But thinking about the kinds of differences that usually evoke pity raises

    fundamental questions about whether pity canever take place simplyby rec-

    ognizing the identity of our common natures. Instead, as Connolly has sug-

    gested, doesnt pity (ostensibly grounded inidentit) inevitably entail some

    reference to difference?45 Colored by self-consciousness and invidious com-

    parisons with the other, modern pity can assume many forms. Compassion

    may thinly disguise condescension. These poor suffering souls deserve our

    pity because we are stronger, more intelligent, wealthier, or more fortunate

    than they. Even at its best, this bond of commiseration rests upon the very

    sorts of relational differences Rousseau is concerned to extirpate.As Rousseau wonders, what are generosity, clemency, humanity, if not

    pity applied to the weak, to the guilty, or to the human species in general

    (SD, p. 131)? Here at long last are examples of the modern ages ability to

    marshal the sentiment of pity toward concrete, positive ends. Yet it is note-

    worthy that Rousseau raises this as a rhetorical, perhaps even purposefully

    ironic question that he is reluctant to answer in the affirmative. Are these

    accomplishments of modern compassionreally thedeveloped andgeneral-

    ized versions of the elemental faculty of pity that remains obscure in sav-

    ageman?Andinwhat respect is theirdevelopedstatus incivilsocietycom-

    patible with his complaints about their alleged feebleness?

    Rousseaus categories apply not to concrete, particular individuals qua

    individuals but instead as members of abstract groups. In this formulation,

    we pity the weak not as equal, fellow sensible beings but because of theirconditionof weakness,which Rousseau elsewhere insists is an unnaturaldif-

    ference. Thestatus of guiltwith itsconventionalnotions of criminality or

    moral approbation and disapprobationis what evokes our sympathy. And

    even in the case of the universal love for all of humanity, compassion is

    awarded based on the recipients membership in the highlyabstract category

    of humanity, rather than by her particular, concrete presence as a fellow

    sentient being.46 Such abstract and conventional categories as Rousseau

    invokes are irrelevant to and beyond the conceptualization of natural man.

    Pity may also be colored by vanity and invidious comparisons. The strong

    pity the weak because they are beneath them. The guilty deserve clemency

    from the guiltless because they are in some respect their moral superiors.

    Thinking long and hard about these relational comparisonsand the secret

    feelings of self-importance and righteousness they often disguiserevealsjust how much they color and inspire much of what passes for pity in modern

    society.47 Pity is either so universal as to be based on membership in abstract

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 535

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    19/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    20/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    21/29

    native, sentimental souls like Emile who livewithincivil society butare not a

    part of it. Yet this is an individual rather than a political response to the ail-

    ments of civil society. Rousseau also holds out the prospects of a more gen-

    eral, political solution to modern alienation and dependency in the compen-

    satory realm of citizenship. Whatever conventional differences divide us,

    there is at least one respect in which all remain equal and free. Citizenship,

    such as Rousseau describes in theFirst Discourseand theSocial Contract,

    offers a much-needed ground of commonality whereby love of ones fellow

    citizens presumably displaces love of self. At first glance, it seems that the

    generalization of compassion might be an important part of this enterprise,

    forming the constitutive bond of citizenship that is written not in laws but in

    the hearts of citizens.56 But reinstating pity as a conventional and publicas

    opposed to a natural and privatevirtue raises further difficulties.It is unclear howan ultimately privatevirtuelikepity might begeneralized

    into the imaginary realm of the public sphere without surrendering the

    intensely personal sensibilities that gave it its original force. As difficult as it

    mayseem, theact of imaginingwhat we share with a single, sensible individ-

    ual requires considerably less of us than recognizing something of ourselves

    in the abstract construct of an entire nation. And even if stretching pity to

    encompass the abstract category of citizenship might conceivably yield

    something likeHabermass constitutional patriotism, this Kantian concep-

    tion of patriotism as somethingrational, abstract, andunemotional seems the

    very antithesis of Rousseaus description of pity.57

    Thedifficulty of seeingcompassion as a sourceof democratic community

    is exacerbated by Rousseaus recurrent linkage between citizenship and mar-

    tial virtue. His ultimate expression of citizenship embraces the Spartan idealof a citizen-soldier willing to fight for the political community. But presum-

    ably such a citizen in the truest sense of the termone who kills and even

    dies for his political communitymust be capable of bracketing the natural

    sensitivity to see another suffer harm. Citizenship in its extreme guise of

    friends andenemies demands that we repress thenaturalandsensible in favor

    of a pitilessness that is profoundly unnatural to human beings. As Shklar has

    observed, citizenship in large part rests on a suppression of the natural,

    including most notably that natural faculty of pity.58

    Furthermore, linking pity to citizenship and the public sphere serves only

    to reintroduce the problem of difference at a higher level. Even if we could

    stretch our natural sympathy to include all members of the political commu-

    nity, thecategory of citizenship is by itsvery natureexclusionary. Inprefer-

    ring one part of humanity to the rest, Tzvetan Todorov has observed, thecitizen transgresses a fundamental principle, thatof equality. Withoutexplic-

    itly saying it, he accepts the notion that men are not equal.59 Too often, love

    538 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    22/29

    of all members of our own political community is allied withressentiment

    toward those of another. Pitys moral othersemergefull-blown in theform of

    nationalism, xenophobia, and exclusion when one attempts to transpose

    compassion onto the political sphere.

    We should hardly be surprised, then, that Rousseaus political ideal of

    democratic citizenship under the socialcontract does not rest on compassion

    for others. Instead, as John Scott has argued, Rousseaus political thought

    aims to restore the natural wholeness of the state of nature by instituting a

    socialcontractwhoseexplicitgoal is toputevery citizen ina position ofper-

    fect independence from all the others, while remaining excessively depen-

    dent on the political community as a whole (SC, bk. 2, chap. 12, p. 77,

    emphasis added).60

    The irony is that pity carries within itself virtually all of the vices Rous-seau most criticizes in hismoral andpoliticaltheory: first, thefact that pity is

    aversive means that it discourages willful agency; second, it rests inescap-

    ably upon the very differences and inequalities that ultimately alienate and

    separate us from ourselves andothers; and third, itspractice apparentlyentails

    the creation of altogether new dependencies between otherwise autonomous

    individuals. In fairness, these problems with compassion are not unforeseen

    by those who envision a larger role for compassion in political theory. Joan

    Tronto has misgivings about what she calls the otherness, paternalism,

    and privileged irresponsibility of an ethic of care. Because

    care arisesout of thefact that notall humansor othersor objects in theworld areequally

    able,at all times, to take care ofthemselves. . . . The result is that those who receive care

    are oftentransformedinto the other, and identifiedby whatevermarksthem as needingcare: their economic plight, their seeming disability, and so forth.61

    Tronto further notes that the convenient fiction of human equality is just

    thata fictionand thus a moral theory of compassion that takes these fun-

    damental dependencies and inequalities into account maybe preferable to a

    moral theory, that because it presumes that all people are equal, is unable

    even to recognize them.62

    The consequences of this last move are, I think, problematic for many of

    the reasons Rousseau suggests. Even if the governing principle of political

    equality is, as Tronto rightly notes, in some sense fictional, and the justice

    of liberal political theoryis toooften sentimentally unaware of private differ-

    ences and inequalities among citizens, it is unclear that as a consequence

    these underlying differences should be made more morally relevant withrespect to the political sphere.63 The danger is that in trying to make political

    theory more attentive to difference, especially by displacing the centrality of

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 539

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    23/29

    justice, rights, and equality, the political sphere may be tainted by the other-

    ness,privilege, and paternalism that Tronto herself admits sometimesplague

    an ethic of care, and which Rousseau earlier foresaw lurking in the emotions

    of pity and compassion. Tronto is not interested in debating theproposition

    that politics necessarily involves the corruptionof whatever moral principles

    enter its arena, and she has a good sense of what these kinds of debates

    obscure.64 But the difficulty raised by Rousseau would seem to be precisely

    theopposite one: rather than compassion being corruptedby politics, thereal

    danger is that the pathologies of pity, as described by Rousseau, might actu-

    ally distort theideals of democratic politicallifewhen onetries to make com-

    passion more central to democratic theory and practice. Hannah Arendt, for

    example, complains that in its extreme political analogue, compassion may

    even

    shun the drawn-out wearisome processes of persuasion, negotiation and compromise,

    which are theprocessesof lawand politics,and lendits voice to thesufferingitself,which

    must claim for swift and direct action, that is, for action with the means of violence.65

    Inspired instead by theKantian thrustof Rousseaus political theoryin the

    social contract, contemporary democratic theorists have sought ways of

    securing a kind of compensatorypoliticalequality that supercedes thediffer-

    ences and inequalities of civil society and encourages more willful agency

    and self-legislation on the part of citizens.66 We have seen why Rousseaus

    account of political compassion is of little help on both of these scores.

    Despite theallureof a kind of generalized compassion, which might, like the

    ideal political citizenship of the social contract, serve as a way of transcend-ing the invidious distinctions of civil society, Rousseaus account of pity

    seemingly founders on the problem of difference. What democratic political

    life most needs is some groundfor equality or likeness that transcends differ-

    ence. And yet we have seen that pity carries within itself thevery differences

    it is supposed to transcend. Conversely, at those moments in democratic

    political life when we aremost in need of theability to make judgmentsfor

    example, in determining when cruelty needs to be met with force, or who

    truly deserves our compassionpitys indiscriminacy becomes a stumbling

    block.Finally, pitys negativeor aversive characterwould seem to beget only

    reluctant spectators and thus does little to encourage the kind of political

    agency and willful actors necessary for a truly democratic political life.

    540 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    24/29

    NOTES

    1. Judith Shklar,Ordinary Vices(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).

    2. Alexis de Tocqueville,Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper,

    1988), vol. 2, pt. 3, 564. This generalized compassion perhaps stems, as Tracy Strong argues,

    from the kind of equality and transparency that democracies alone permit. Tracy Strong,Jean-

    JacquesRousseau and thePoliticsof theOrdinary(ThousandOaks,CA: Sage,1994),145-46.

    3. Nietzsches complaints aboutmoderncompassionarecomplex.Most conspicuous is his

    contempt for pity as a sickness or nausea endemic to democratic society. Friedrich Nietz-

    sche,Genealogy of Morals, esp. Preface, 5-6; III, 14. But he also alludes to a kind of noble or

    aristocraticmercy, borneof thepathosof distanceand theconsciousnessof power, as a fitting

    attitude of the powerful toward the weak or parasites beneath them. Nietzsche,Genealogy, II,

    10. Cf.Beyond Good and Evil, V, 201-2; VII, 225.

    4. Carl Schmitt,The Concept of the Political (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University

    Press, 1976), esp. pp. 28-29, 35-37, 54, 68.

    5. On this latter point about how, notwithstanding their veneer of compassion, modern

    democracies may still vent their cruelty upon those who are outside or alien, see Nietzsche,

    Genealogy of Morals, I, 11, p. 40:

    thesamemenwho areheldso sternly incheckinterpares ...andwhoontheotherhandin

    their relations with one another show themselves so resourceful in consideration, self-

    control,delicacy, loyalty, pride, andfriendshiponcetheygo outside,where thestrange,

    thestrangeris found, they are not much better than uncaged beasts of prey.

    6. NancyHirschman,Sympathy, EmpathyandObligation, in Feminist Interpretations of

    David Hume, ed. Anne Jaap Jacobson (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press,

    2000), 174.

    7. Jrgen Habermas, Citizenship and National Identity, inBetween Facts and Norms

    (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson,Democracy and

    Disagreement(Cambridge, MA: Belknap,1996);BenjaminBarber, StrongDemocracy: Partici-

    patoryPolitics for a New Age (Berkeley: Universityof California Press,1984).Fora treatmentof

    the more general problem of affect in democratic theory, which raises questions about thischaracterization of Habermas and problematizes the strict antinomy between reason and affect,

    see PatchenMarkell, MakingAffectSafe forDemocracy?PoliticalTheory28(2000):38-63.

    8. Notably, Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press, 1982); Joan Tronto,Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care (New

    York:Routledge,1993). Thiscase has beenrecentlymade in similar termsbut without reference

    to Rousseau by Maureen Whitebrook, Compassion as a Political Virtue,Political Studies50

    (2002): 529-44.

    9. Robert Bellah et al.,Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American

    Life(New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni,The New Golden Rule: Community and

    Morality in a Democratic Society(New York: Basic Books, 1996), esp. chap. 5.

    10. Consider, for example, the widely differinginterpretationsthat make Rousseau into the

    apostle of compassion: Allan Bloom, Introduction, inEmile, or On Education, ed. and trans.

    Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books,1979), 17-20.Or, as LeoStrauss puts it,Compassionis

    thepassionfrom whichall social virtuesderive.NaturalRight andHistory(Chicago:University

    of ChicagoPress, 1953),270;and those others whoread Rousseauas theharbingerof contempo-rarydemocratic theory, JamesMiller,Rousseau: Dreamerof Democracy (NewHaven,CT: Yale

    University Press, 1984).

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 541

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    25/29

    11. On naturalfreedom,wholeness,and goodnessas Rousseaus intendedgoals,see Strauss,

    NaturalRight and History, 277-83.For a contraryviewof thenaturalness of humandependency,

    see Joel Schwartz,The Sexual Politics of Jean-Jacques Rousseau(Chicago: University of Chi-

    cago Press, 1984).

    12. On thinking of liberal democracy as distinguished not by any particular set of political

    institutions but in terms of its commitment to these procedures and the intrinsic value of moral

    equality, see George Kateb,The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture(Ithaca,

    NY: Cornell UniversityPress, 1992), esp.chaps. 2 and3; onwillfulness andindividualagencyas

    essential to aliberaldemocracy, see Richard Flathman,Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and

    Individualismin Political Theory and Practice(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992); as

    essential for astrongdemocracy, see Barber,Strong Democracy, chap. 6.

    13. William Connolly, Identity/Difference: Democratic Negotiations of Political Paradox

    (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002), esp. xxiv-xxv, 158-60, 172-73; William

    Connolly,Why I Am Not a Secularist(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999), 144-

    45.

    14. Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are toThe First and Second Dis-courses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martins, 1964);On the Social Contract, ed. Roger

    Masters andtrans.JudithR. Masters (New York:St. Martins, 1978);Emile,or OnEducation,ed.

    and trans. Allan Bloom (NewYork:Basic Books, 1979); TheReveriesof theSolitaryWalker, ed.,

    trans., and withan introductionby Charles Butterworth (NewYork: NewYorkUniversityPress,

    1979); andPolitics and the Arts: Letter to M. DAlembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free

    Press, 1960).

    15. Foran excellentdiscussion of hownaturalpity is activated by the imaginationand trans-

    formed into compassion, see David Marshall,The Surprising Effects of Sympathy: Marivaux,

    Diderot,Rousseau, and Mary Shelley(Chicago:University ofChicagoPress, 1988),148-52.See

    also Jacques Derrida,Of Grammatology(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997),

    182-87.

    16. Compare Arthur Melzer,The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseaus

    Thought(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 93.

    17. Clifford Orwin, Rousseau and the Discovery of Political Compassion, inThe Legacy

    of Rousseau, ed. Clifford Orwin and Nathan Tarcov (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,1997), 309.

    18. Contrast the reading of Mira Morgenstern, for whom the sweetness of pity derives at

    leastin partfrom thediscoveryof individual empowerment and independence.Rousseauand the

    Politics of Ambiguity(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), 65, 68-69.

    19. Rousseaus choice of the term commiseration is noteworthy. Literally, sharing the

    misery of anotherthis may be the necessary condition for us to think about acting to relieve

    that misery, but it is, as we will see below, far from a sufficient condition for this kind of willful

    human agency.

    20. Compare Alexis Philonenko, Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la Pense du Malheur:

    Apothose du Dsespoir(Paris: Librairie Philosophique, 1984), 183: Le malheur devient un

    instrument de la pdagogie philosophique.

    21. Compare Orwin, Rousseau and the Discovery, 302, 307-8: Within the context of

    Emile, the greatest importance of compassion is not to society but to Emile himself. Cf. John

    Charvet,The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-

    versity Press, 1974), who assumes that the purpose of pity is to produce good for others and to

    serve as the foundation of a new social order (see esp. pp. 83-93).

    542 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    26/29

    22. Compare C. N. Dugan andTracy Strong,Music, Politics,Theaterand Representation,

    in TheCambridge Companion to Rousseau, ed. PatrickRiley (Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUni-

    versity Press, 2001), esp. 333, 339, 343.

    23. Morgenstern has developed this point at greater length:Rousseau and the Politics of

    Ambiguity, esp. 35-47.

    24. Marshall,Surprising Effects of Sympathy, 142.

    25. Cf. Elizabeth Wingrove,who interestinglysuggests that the theater representsnot just a

    suspension of will, but a willing complicity in the crimes of others,Rousseaus Republican

    Romance(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), esp. 175-76; for a more extended

    discussionof theperformativeaspectof sympathyin the theater,see Marshall,SurprisingEffects

    of Sympathy, esp. 143-48.

    26. Christopher Kelly offers a concise account of Rousseaus ambivalence toward the arts.

    Rousseau and the Case against (and for) the Arts, inThe Legacy of Rousseau, esp. 20-25.

    27. Thereare major scholarlydebatesabout theconsistencyofRousseaus account ofpityas

    either an immanent or an active virtue (or both), and my analysis addresses these controversies

    implicitly. ButI am mainly concernedhere withthe related butdistinct questionof whether com-miseration is ultimately experienced as sweet or irksome.

    28. Cf. Melzer,Natural Goodness of Man, 16-17.

    29. Contrastthe readingof MargaretOgrodnick,Instinctand Intimacy:PoliticalPhilosophy

    and Autobiography in Rousseau(Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press, 1999), 137. If

    my point here is correct, virtually all of what Jacques Derrida has written about the maternal

    metaphor for compassion in Rousseau is wrong.There is little textual evidence in Rousseau to

    suggest that children have a natural affection for their parents that is written into their hearts by

    God. And in the above-cited passages in the Second Discourse, Rousseau makes it clear that

    maternal or familial affection, likeromanticlove, arises onlyby habitor custom. Cf. Derrida, Of

    Grammatology, 173-75.

    30. Althoughher subsequentdiscussionleads ina different direction, thispoint is supported

    by the following observationof ElizabethWingrove: Here the intensity of the spectators reac-

    tion is rooted in itsinability to differentiate itself from other beings.Rousseaus Republican

    Romance, 32.

    31. Consider also Rousseaus example of the pongos,who take pains to cover the bodies oftheirdeadwithbranches orleavesso thattheydonthave tobe confrontedby itspresence.Second

    Discourse, 205n, 208n.

    32. Derrida,Of Grammatology, 190.

    33. Compare the similar point made by Wingrove,Rousseaus Republican Romance, 35.

    34. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. Macpherson (New York: Penguin, 1968), chap. 13,

    pp. 184-85.

    35. Compare Ernst Cassirer,The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, trans. Peter Gay

    (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), 101:

    According to Rousseau, Hobbes had quite rightly recognized that in the pure state of

    nature there was no bond of sympathy binding the single individuals to each other. . . .

    According to Rousseau, the only flaw in Hobbess psychology consisted in putting an

    active egoism in the place of the purely passive egoism which prevails in the state of

    nature.

    See also Jean Starobinski,Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction, trans.Arthur Goldhammer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 298-99.

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 543

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    27/29

  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    28/29

    To accept a gift is to admit ones inferiority; it is to incur an obligation to people whose

    kindness is a way of signaling social distance while insincerely glossing it over. The

    equality[Rousseau] wantsthe reciprocity of freemindsexcludes dependenceof any

    kind, and in the first place the dependence created by the kindness of the benevolent.

    48. Connolly,Identity/Difference, xiv.

    49. Cf. Montaigne, On Cruelty, whose natural sensitivity extends even to plants! Michel

    de Montaigne,The Complete Essays(London: Penguin, 1991), 488.

    50. Rousseaus revelation of the self as an ungrounded and perfectible tabula rasa invites

    dilemmasof difference andrecognitionunknown toearlier thinkers. Oncethe selfhas become in

    Rousseaus hands nothingmore thanthe perfectiblereflectionof conventional differences and

    cultural influences, truerecognitioncan takeplace onlyundertwo equallyunlikelysets ofcondi-

    tions: either between equals in the pure state of nature or within civil society, when two selves

    have been forgedby an identicalset ofsocial influences.Withthe adventof civilsociety, thefirst

    possibility vanishesforever,and withthe continuous process of civilization,the likelihoodof the

    latter diminishes by the day.51. Rousseau looks to be guilty of pursuing what Joan Tronto has criticized as a morality

    first strategy by conceiving of pity as ultimately best confined to private relationshipsbetween

    individualsrather thanconstitutiveofthe politicalbondsbetweencitizens.Tronto,MoralBound-

    aries, 158.

    52. Here,I have inmind certaincommunitariancriticsof liberalism suchas Robert Bellah,

    Amitai Etzioni, Michael Sandel, and Alasdair MacIntyre. Even if they do not explicitly or uni-

    formlycallfor more compassion (ormoredemocracy!)as a remedyfor these ailmentsof liberal-

    ism, they have presented a challenging criticism of the excessive thinness, legalism, neutrality,

    and sentimental inertness of liberal political theory.

    53. Cf. Orwin, Rousseau and the Discovery, esp. 298-99; Plattner,Rousseaus State of

    Nature, 128-32.

    54. By readingRousseauhere as a critic ofliberalismand theprimacy of private property,

    self-interest,and individual rights, I do notmean tosuggest thathis critiquewasnotalso applica-

    ble to aristocratic or courtly society.

    55. Rousseaus stipulation that the sum of our obligations to our fellow citizens consists in

    refraining from causing them undue suffering is compatible with even the least flattering criti-

    cismsof contemporaryliberalsocietyby Bellah,MacIntyre,or Sandel.A market societycharac-

    terized by self-interest, anomie, and atomization may prove the quintessential example of a

    worldwherewe take nospecialpainsto be cruelto others. Emphasizingboththe thin obligations

    of fellowcitizens to oneanother and therelativeunlikelihoodof even theseminimalduties being

    recognized makes Rousseau among the most realistic of political theorists.

    56. Cf. Melzer,Natural Goodness of Man, who suggests that an immanent human expan-

    siveness to identify with others forms the basis of patriotism, political community, and justice

    for Rousseau, esp. 170-71n. Compare Ogrodnick,Instinct and Intimacy, 135-38. Below, I raise

    questions not just about this possibility for Rousseau, but also and more importantly whether

    even this immanent expansiveness can overcome the problem of moral otherness.

    57. Cf.JrgenHabermas,Citizenship andNationalIdentity, inTheorizingCitizenship,ed.

    Ron Beiner (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995). For a characterization of the

    particularistic andaffective dimensionsof Rousseaus thoughtson patriotism, see MarcPlattner,

    Rousseau and the Origins of Nationalism, inThe Legacy of Rousseau, esp. 187-93.

    58. Judith Shklar,Men andCitizens:A Study of RousseausSocial Theory (Cambridge,UK:Cambridge University Press, 1969), 15-17, 21; Ogrodnick,Instinct and Intimacy, 139-45.

    Boyd / ROUSSEAU AND THE LIMITS OF DEMOCRATIC COMPASSION 545

    at CAPES on July 9, 2010ptx.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/http://ptx.sagepub.com/
  • 8/10/2019 BOYD, Richard - Pity's Pathologies Portrayed

    29/29

    59. Tzvetan Todorov,Frail Happiness: An Essay on Rousseau, trans. John T. Scott and

    Robert D. Zaretsky (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2001), 29.

    60. John T. Scott, The Theodicy of theSecond Discourse: The Pure State of Nature and

    Rousseaus Political Thought,American Political Science Review86 (1992): 708.

    61. Tronto,Moral Boundaries, 145.

    62. Ibid., 147.

    63. One problemwithdoingso is compassionstendencyto eclipse civic equality. See espe-

    cially Hannah Arendt,On Revolution(New York: Penguin Books, 1977), 90:

    Measured against the immense sufferings of the immense majority of the people, the

    impartialityof justice andlaw, theapplication ofthe same rules tothosewhosleepin pal-

    aces and those who sleep under the bridges of Paris, was like a mockery.

    64. Tronto,Moral Boundaries, 93.

    65. Arendt,On Revolution. 86-87.

    66. Habermas, Citizenship and National Identity, esp. 503-6; Barber,Strong Democracy,

    esp. chaps. 6 and 8.

    Richard Boyd is an assistant professor of political science at the University of Wisconsin

    Madison. He is the author of various journal articles on seventeenth- and eighteenth-

    century political thought and a forthcoming book titledUncivil Society: The Perils of

    Pluralism and the Making of Modern Liberalism (2004).

    546 POLITICAL THEORY / August 2004