ch10 douglass bailey

Upload: pamant2

Post on 14-Apr-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    1/8

    Douglass Bailey90

    10. Beyond the meaning of Neolithic houses:specific objects and serial repetition

    Douglass Bailey

    In doing this, I wish to imply neither metaphor nor analogy

    (Bochner 1967).

    What do we know about Neolithic houses?

    As archaeologists we have become very good at studying

    Neolithic houses. We have perfected the application and

    extrapolation of geophysical methods to the point where

    we can locate Neolithic buildings beneath the soil and

    accurately predict their sizes and depths. We can uncover

    these structures with precise excavation, pick them apart,

    peeling back extra-ordinarily thin layers and fragmentary

    traces of activities, rubbish, debris and fragments of floors,

    ceilings, ovens and hearths. We can produce excavation

    records and floor-plans to millimetric precision and we

    can reconstruct highly intricate and often truncated

    patterns of long extinct human behaviour. We can rebuild

    structures on paper (and at full size on land) and

    manipulate complex stratigraphic matrices, inventories

    of artifacts and refuse, positions of grinding stones, storage

    bins, and looms in order to produce authoritative

    reconstructions of household living in 8000 year old

    houses. As material scientists we can recreate the recipes

    with which house walls and roofs were made; we can

    determine the relative proportions of each constituentelement of plaster or paint. We can identify the season in

    which the grass, clay and mud daub was mixed. We can

    reveal the method by which a particular tree was split and

    from what distance the wood had to be transported before

    it was placed in the foundation trench that had been dug

    for it. We can reconstruct the processes and order in

    which these foundation trenches and post-holes were dug,

    infilled, redug, shored up and covered over through series

    of repairs and reconstructions. We can identify and count

    sequences of wall and floor replasterings and create

    genealogies for buildings long dead. We can measure

    soils, sediments and patterns of artifact fragmentation

    and erosion in order to reconstruct alterations in building

    usage from human to animal and back to human. We can

    track subtle sequences of construction, extension and

    abandonment of buildings and building complexes. As

    forensic experts we can recreate the sequences, causes

    and consequences of house destruction and decay. We are

    very good at using the evidence of Neolithic architecture,

    floorplans, investments of labour, patterns of construction,

    reconstruction, destruction and neglect as proxies for social

    structures, hierarchies, conflicts and intra-community

    political dynamics. We speak with confidence of unequal

    access to private space as well as of the social value of

    shared, communal, open space. We recreate household

    units and their ceremonies of membership, incorporation

    and exclusion. We use floor-plans and intra-mural spatial

    organization in order to extrapolate entire structures of

    community relations and metaphors for living. We are

    terribly confident about our progress in improving

    archaeological techniques and experience, our strategies

    of fieldwork, our interpretive inspiration and philosophic

    complexity.

    But is this enough? Are these the right sorts of tools

    and methods? Are these the right kinds of knowledge we

    should be eager to accumulate? Does any of it really get

    at the meaning of Neolithic buildings?

    What dont we know about Neolithic houses?

    On the one hand then, we are very good at the archaeology

    of houses from the Neolithic of south-eastern and central

    Europe. We have become experts in taming the house as

    an archaeological beast, in controlling it, in domesticating

    these buildings within our settled, shared world-view of

    an understandable, interpreted Neolithic. Despite our

    accumulated knowledge, technological expertise and

    intellectual sophistication, however, we are very bad at

    understanding what buildings from the Neolithic mean

    today to us and what they meant to the Neolithic observer.

    We have been particularly unsuccessful, negligent even,

    at understanding two of the most obvious patterns that

    we have been so diligent in reconstructing.

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    2/8

    Beyond the meaning of Neolithic houses 91

    Morphological similarityFirst, we do not competently understand the morph-

    ological similarities among Neolithic buildings, whether

    they are curvilinear pit-features of many early, and

    significantly, later, Neolithic landscapes or whether they

    are the rectangular surface-level structures of settlement

    tells and flat, extended sites (Fig. 10.1). What does it

    mean that there was so little variation in form of

    individual units of Europes earliest built environments?

    Why are pit-features so similar in shape? Why are the

    forms and sizes of buildings in tell villages repeated with

    such similarity?

    The explanations to date do not satisfy. Least sufficient

    are culture historical attempts that see building form,

    like other elements of a society, as essential constituents

    that define a community: similarity of building morph-

    ology as just another example of shared material culture.

    While there may be something to the building similaritywithin one settlement or, even across one coherent region,

    it is a less sustainable explanation when one recognizes

    that morphological similarity crosses the borders of

    established culture groups. Why are there similarly

    shaped multi-roomed rectilinear buildings in northern

    Greece as well as in southern Romania? While it is true

    that variation at greater distance is apparent (Linear-

    bandkeramik longhouses are not Kodzhaderman-

    Gumelnia-Karanovo VI tell houses), there are significant

    repetitions of formal building similarity within andbetween individual LBK sites that themselves are

    separated by substantial geographic distances. Equally

    insufficient are the functional suggestions put forward,

    for example by me (Bailey 1999; 2000) following the

    lead of others such as Kent Flannery (1972; 2002), in

    which building morphology follows the most efficient

    use, division and extension of built space: that rectilinear

    structures are more suited to sub-division and extension;

    oval and round structures to less anchored concentrations

    of activities.

    None of these attempts at explanation really deals with

    the repetition of building form across space and throughtime. None of them touches the conceptual core that sits

    beneath the formal similarity in architecture. How does

    similarity of structures work? Why should it happen? Is

    it mere coincidence? Or is there something that we, as

    Figure 10.1 Selection of house plans from tells Ovcharovo, Polyanitsa, Radingrad and Turgovishte, northeasternBulgaria (after Todorova 1982).

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    3/8

    Douglass Bailey92

    expert house archaeologists, are missing in our hyper-

    detailed, millimetrically precise, explicit research

    strategies? We are left not understanding what the

    similarity of Neolithic buildings meant to Neolithic

    people and what it means to us.

    Building aggregation

    Second, we do not understand the aggregation of

    Neolithic buildings into the communities that we call

    villages or, for the pit-features, camps. Why did people

    construct these similarly-formed buildings in such tight

    congregations? Indeed why does the village emerge as a

    tectomorphic (and political) institution in the Neolithic

    of south-eastern and central Europe? Is it enough to

    recognize that the phenomenon that we choose to

    recognize as the Neolithic in south-eastern and central

    Europe has precedents in the Near East and in Anatolia

    where there also occur aggregations of buildings withrectilinear floorplans? Are these (eastern or western)

    aggregations merely other facets of being a community of

    a particular economic sort, literally another consequence

    of a groups culture history and functional dynamics?

    Are these aggregations a requisite of early agricultural

    life, if indeed such a concept ever existed? Older traditions

    of archaeological interpretation found satisfaction in an

    essential need for defensive buildings and for safety in

    numbers, as well as in some hard-wired stimulus to

    shelter, work, share, store, and live together. None of

    these answers satisfy. Though explanations may service

    particular approaches to the subject (the culture historical,

    the economic), they do not get into the meaning of villageaggregation in the south-east European Neolithic.

    Questions

    Despite the advances of our growing skills and inter-

    pretive enthusiasms, two fundamental questions have

    gone unasked: why are the south-east European Neolithic

    buildings similar in appearance; and why do these

    buildings occur in aggregations? We have failed to answer

    these questions, indeed many of us have failed even to

    ask these questions, because we have been studying the

    wrong things in the wrong way. Critically, we have been

    looking at Neolithic architecture from the wrong per-spective. We have been looking at building and settlement

    composition, at the material and political interiors, of

    Neolithic sites. We have sought understanding in the

    increasingly fine-grained and minute internal details of

    Neolithic houses and villages: we have sought answers in

    the precise patterns of artifacts, residues, traces and social

    contexts. Two propositions push us in a different

    direction, towards a radically altered understanding of

    the structural similarity and spatial arrangement of

    Neolithic architecture; it is also a direction in which lies

    a more dynamic meaning of Neolithic buildings.

    First, what if none of what we have discovered about

    Neolithic houses matters? What if it is unimportant what

    happened inside Neolithic houses? What if it is un-

    important how a Neolithic house was built, abandoned or

    destroyed? What if it is unimportant if a Neolithic house

    represents a social unit such as a household?

    Second, what if building morphology and aggregation

    are interesting only when we see them as uninteresting?

    What if Neolithic buildings are of interest only when westep away from the accepted questions and methods that

    seek compositional interpretation or explanation? What

    if Neolithic architecture becomes interesting only when

    we stop focusing on the building itself and on its internal

    components? What if Neolithic buildings are only of

    interest when we start to think about them in terms of

    external relations: more specifically, when we start to

    think about them from the eyes of the spectator?

    An anticompositional attitude

    In late April 1966, an installation opened at the JewishGallery in New York. The work gathered at this show,

    which was called Primary Structures: Younger Americanand British Sculpture, had been made by a group of peoplewho shared a common approach to material objects and

    to space.1 The artists were developing a shared philo-

    sophical commitment to the abstract, anti-compositional

    material object: it was a movement that had several names

    (ABC Art, Cool Art, Primary Structures, Rejective Art)

    but which now rests most easily under the title of

    Minimalism. These artists made work, showed it and,

    perhaps most helpfully for us, wrote about it, wrote about

    what they were trying to do, and they wrote about the

    work of others.2

    Primary Structures was full of seminal pieces of theemerging Minimal movement and included especially

    important work by a core of Minimalists: Donald Judd,

    Sol LeWitt, Robert Morris, Tony Smith, Judy Chicago,

    Robert Smithson, Dan Flavin, Carl Andre, Anne Truitt,

    and Robert Bladen. One example will suffice to provide

    a way into their shared way of engaging material and

    space.

    Robert Morris showed two, extravagantly large,

    identical, grey-coloured, right-angled, three-dimensional,

    L-shaped forms (Untitled, 2 L Beams; 196567) (Fig.

    10.2). These were big objects; the arms of each of the Lswere over two metres long and the measurement around

    the girth of the arms was the same dimension. In addition

    to its size (the pieces were taller than most visitors to the

    installation) 2 L-Beams was a strangely stimulating piece.Like much of the work in Primary Structures, peoplereacted to the L-Beams in new and different ways. Morris

    had placed the identical L-shapes in different positions:

    the first sat securely on the floor with one arm running

    with a flat side along the ground and the other arm

    standing up perpendicular to the floor. Morris placed the

    second L-Beam in a very different position, with the

    outside tip of the right-angle pointing upwards and the

    ends of the two arms of the L, pointed down, like legs,

    supporting the shape but almost teetering, with only a

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    4/8

    Beyond the meaning of Neolithic houses 93

    thin edge of each touching the ground. Though identical

    in size, form and colour, the different positionings made

    these objects appear to be different forms; while one Lwas solid and stable, firmly grounded on the floor of the

    gallery, the other was balanced precariously, ready to

    topple over. The visitor to the Jewish Gallery was faced

    with an apparent contradiction: these were objects that

    were the same but did not appear to be so. From this

    contradiction came a tension that bounced between the

    two pieces (same or different; different or same) and

    between the pieces and the gallery visitor (I see the same

    thing but in different ways). The Minimalists were

    especially successful in creating and positioning identical

    three-dimensional objects in particular ways to confront

    the spectator with apparent contradictions: for MorrisLs, it is the same form but it is not the same.

    Environmental objects

    Like much Minimalist work, Morris Primary Structurespiece stimulated the spectator not only through the

    contradiction that came from the repetition of a right-

    angled, chunky, cubic, L-shape, but through the way that

    the size and positioning of the Ls forced spectators to

    consider things and places beyond the pieces displayed.

    In this sense, Morris Ls, like the pieces of many of his

    colleagues, were environmental; they focused the viewers

    eye not on the object itself but on the objects articulation

    of space. Where traditional sculpture was self-contained

    and attracted the viewers gaze towards it and then into

    its component parts, Minimal art pushed the spectator to

    look elsewhere and in doing so activated the space beyond

    and around the piece itself.The environmental engagement of the space beyond

    the work of art took various forms. Some Minimalists,

    such as Donald Judd3 and Robert Morris4 made work that

    occupied space. Morris geometric shapes and Judds

    series of empty wooden or metal boxes physically

    encompassed space. Other Minimalist work conquered

    space. For example, Ronald Bladens The X (1967),shown at the Scale as Context show at the CorcoranGallery dominated the gallery space: the piece was a

    massive three-dimensional X-shape made of wood and

    clad in black covering; the piece filled a large two-storey

    gallery, straddled the centre of the gallery floor, andreached up to the roof. TheXdominated the space to suchan extent that, in order to experience the piece, the viewer

    literally had to walk through the art by moving between

    the legs of the X. Other Minimalists, such as Sol LeWitt5

    and Tony Smith, made work that incorporated space.

    Smiths Smoke, also in the Scale show at the Corcoran,was also massive; it filled the gallery like a modulated

    canopy of smoke rising up to the ceiling. Again the viewer

    was in amongst the work, walking through it looking up,

    around, behind. The person looking at Smoke shared acommon space with the work itself. Yet other

    Minimalists, like Carl Andre6 and Don Flavin7 made work

    that dispersed space. Andre used bricks and tiles laid out

    in sequences on gallery floors and pushed viewers to

    Figure 10.2 Untitled (L-beams) installed at the Leo Castelli Gallery, New York (1965). (Photograph by RudolphBurckhardt; after Potts 2000)

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    5/8

    Douglass Bailey94

    follow the sequence with their eyes and their feet (Colpitt

    1990, 82; Lippard 1969). In all of these ways, Minimal

    art was environmental. It pushed around the spectator,

    sometimes moving him or her away from the object itself,

    other times drawing them in before twisting them

    sideways and sending them off again. In all of theseways, Minimalist works existed outside of the individual

    pieces themselves; they engaged the spectator, the piece

    and a shared space all at the same time.

    Engaging the spectator

    The consequence of Minimal arts environmental stim-

    ulation and activation of spaces outside of the individual

    works of art was that Minimal art brought the spectator

    and the piece of work into a shared space. Minimalist art

    established important perceptual relationships across and

    within the space that traditionally separated spectator

    and object. The large size of MorrisL-Beams, BladensXand Smiths Smoke and their presence within galleryspaces had unavoidable implications for spectators

    participation in these works. Critically, the meaning, if

    there is to be a meaning, which emerged out of Minimal

    art was not to be found in a formal analysis of the objects

    contents or internal relationships. On the contrary, any

    meaning that could be located was going to come out of

    the experience that each spectator had with each object

    or sets of objects.

    In this sense then, Minimalist art engaged the viewer

    in ways different from those of traditional representational

    art. Sol LeWitt made this point most clearly (LeWitt

    1969), arguing that when spectators look at traditionalrepresentational art (e.g. a sculpture or a painting), they

    have to make a series of rational decisions. Furthermore,

    representational art was made up of series of relations

    that we as spectators need to understand. Once we have

    understood these rational relations, we arrive at the

    meaning of the object we are looking at. For example,

    when I walk through the Main College building of Cardiff

    University, I pass by W Goscombe Johns 1906 sculpture

    of John Viriamu Jones. When I give visitors a tour, we

    stop and look at this statue. Our process of looking involves

    a series of rational decisions. This is a statue of a man

    (and not of a child or a woman). The man is sitting in achair (and not standing). In the mans hand is a sheaf of

    papers (and not a hammer); is this a manuscript, or a

    lecture or a sermon? This man is wearing a suit and collar

    (and not a dress) and over that suit is an academic gown

    (and not a white laboratory coat) which has rabbit fur

    (and not a fox-tail) around the collar, and so-on and so-

    on until we understand the sculpture and it takes on a

    meaning to me and to my visitor. The sculpture stimulates

    us to ask a set of rational questions to which there are

    rational answers that help me (and my visitor) to

    understand who this man is/was and why there is a statue

    of him here. In fact this man was the first Vice-Chancellor

    of the University of Wales and the first Principal of the

    College; he has an MA, a BSc and was an FRS; and he

    is not some other man, such as Dr. William Price. 8

    We are trained to approach Neolithic houses in a

    similar manner to the way we approach the statue of John

    Viriamu Jones: this is a rectilinear, two room-structure

    and not an oval pit. The walls of this house are made of

    wooden posts (of 10cm diameter oak) and not of stone ormudbrick. The walls are covered with 17 layers of

    alternating white and red plaster and not with 54 layers

    of red, brown and white plaster. This structure in the

    corner of the inner room is a grain silo and not an oven;

    the silo is in the inner room and not the outer room. This

    house contains the produce of the physical labour of a

    small group of people and not of the entire community.

    This group lives in this building and not somewhere else.

    This group of people control the grain which they are

    storing for the next sowing season and which they are

    parching in this domed structure. This domed structure

    is an oven. It is not a small oven; it is a large oven. Andso-on, and so-on, until we understand the house and what

    it means to us and to our understanding of the Neolithic.

    In his writing (and in his work), Sol LeWitt suggested

    that there was another way of putting things together and

    thus another way in which an object can engage a

    spectator. This other way does not follow a rational

    sequence of decisions, questions and answers; indeed,

    this other way is not rational at all. It is logical and in a

    logical sequence each part is dependent on the last. The

    sequence already has a logic to it and if a spectator

    engages it, then such engagement does not require

    (indeed removes the necessity of having) any set of

    decisions, questions or answers. The logical, then, is theirrational. In a logical sequence, you do not think; indeed

    it is not even a way of thinking. Logical things just are

    (Colpitt 1990, 58).

    Minimalist art was logical. It offered sequences of

    visual, physical, material stimuli that spectators did not

    have to think about. Indeed if viewers start to think about

    a Minimalist object or sequence in a rational way, then

    they quickly become lost. Worse, once they start asking

    questions, they become increasingly frustrated, because

    when they think that they have located a possible answer,

    they are dispirited to find that there is no way of

    confirming (testing even) whether or not that potentialanswer is correct.

    A good example of the logical aspect of Minimalist art

    is Carl Andres Lever (1966), a sequence of 137 fire-bricks placed in a line along the floor. People who try to

    read this work in a rational way quickly become frus-

    trated: if they try to understand each individual brick,

    asking rational questions about it, seeking answers before

    moving on to the next brick, they become irritated because

    there are no decisions to be made, there are no questions,

    and there are no answers. In fact, people who approach

    Minimalist art expecting a rational experience frequently

    end up asking the ultimate and, in a Minimal logical, the

    most futile questions. Question: what does it mean?

    Answer: I cant see that it means anything. Question:

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    6/8

    Beyond the meaning of Neolithic houses 95

    why cant I understand this work? Answer: Because it

    isnt art.

    Objecthood and specific objects

    To follow LeWitts suggestions about the logical sequence

    of Minimalist art then is to reject the rational referenceand representationality of traditional art that seeks answers

    in internal elements and composition. If we reject the

    importance of internal composition and its series of

    rational decisions then we are forced to focus on the

    object itself and on notions of objecthood. Minimalist

    artists were very concerned with creating objects which

    were non-representational things, objects which offered

    no illusions of rational representation, but which, at the

    same time, were real and palpable, that were present in

    the space that they occupied. For Minimalists, objecthood

    was three-dimensionality with none of the illusion that

    accompanies representation. Minimal art was notimitation; there was no illusion to something else,

    somewhere else. Their work was non-referential.9 The

    critical thing about an object was not what it alluded to;

    the critical thing about a Minimalist object was its shape.

    Indeed, the shape was the object. It was the whole thing.

    There was nothing else. Specific objects were simple,

    single (but also repetitive and modular) shapes that had

    no internal meanings or rational relationships (Judd 1965).

    One of the most successful objects that appeared in

    Minimalist work was the cube. The cube worked as well

    as it did because it was the ultimate, most basic and most

    standard empty shape. It had no referential components

    to catch the attention of the spectator. If you looked insidethere was nothing to be seen but the inside of the cube. If

    you looked on the outside, again there was only the cube.

    There was nothing there. Furthermore, the cube was solid

    and stationary; it wasnt going anywhere and it wasnt

    going to take the spectator anywhere with it. In an

    environmental sense, the cube might push the spectator

    away from the object, but the cube was immobile and was

    not going to accompany the viewer on that voyage. Of all

    three-dimensional shapes it is the most basic, the most

    standard, because the only thing that the cube represents

    iswellthe cube. In this important sense the cube is

    interesting as an object, simply because it is uninteresting.It means nothing but itself.

    The fact that the cube is empty of anything but itself

    has further significance. Because it is hollow and empty

    it directs the spectator outwards and away from itself. If

    there is meaning, then it is somewhere else. It might be

    in the person looking at the cube. It might be in the

    relationship between the position of the cube and the

    spectator. It might be anywhere else but it will not be in

    the cube. More importantly, the cube had the extra-

    ordinary power of making explicit its empty hollowness.

    By surrounding empty space with solid areas, the cube

    created emptiness. A cube surrounds but doesnt fill the

    space within. Because of this, and in a sensationally,

    apparently contradictory, physical fashion, the cube

    creates negative volume, an emptiness that is environ-

    mental, a manifestation of emptiness that pushes the

    spectator away into thinking about anything and every-

    thing except the cube itself.

    With specific objects such as the cube, we become

    interested not in the thing itself, but in the externalarrangements, repetitions and series of the specific objects

    orchestrated by the artist. MorrisL-Beams and AndresLeverare good examples. Morris arranged his beams tocause them to appear to be different forms, although they

    were identical in every physical way. Morris arrange-

    ment of the Ls, especially as identical forms that appeared

    to be unidentical, set up in the viewers mind a tension of

    contradictory visual impressions. Contradiction came

    from the arrangement of identical objects. For Andres

    linear series of bricks on the floor, the interesting thing

    is not the bricks as objects, which are identical. Rather

    the interesting thing is the way that Andre arranged andrepeated the identical units.

    By arranging identical units in logical series, Morris

    and Andre (as well as many other Minimalists10) imposed

    an order that operated beyond each physical object itself.

    Along with the environment, repetition of form, and

    attention to the specific object, the serial ordering of

    objects was a powerful tool of the Minimal artists:11 the

    placement of a series of bricks, the series of empty cubes

    that Judd attached to gallery walls and floors. The

    imposition of a serial order to the arrangement of specific

    objects was more than a method; the serial order was an

    attitude through which the execution of a work was

    subsumed under the order and the repetition of form(Bochner 1967). The perception of serial work has

    important consequences for spectators. Since internal

    relationships did not exist, since there was no content

    and no set of rational decisions, the Minimal objects

    become easier for the spectator to consume. Minimalist

    art required less perceptual work on the part of the person

    looking at it. Spectators consumed serial pieces in

    radically different ways than they did traditional rational

    representational work. Where rational work had to be

    chewed over, through rational sequences of decisions,

    questions and answers, Minimal work slides right down

    in one logical gulp.12

    However, while the Minimalist work was simpler to

    consume, the simplicity hid an unexpected impact on the

    role that the spectator had to play. Identical forms arranged

    in series may have been more easily taken in, but they did

    not sequentially reveal the object or its meaning. In fact

    they did the opposite, pushing the spectator away to think

    and look elsewhere; they frustrated meaning. In doing

    this, Minimalist work increased the work-load that the

    spectator had to carry: there was no easy visual path to

    deriving understanding or meaning. In fact, there was no

    particular meaning at all, only sets of tensions and the

    stimuli to think. Among these tensions and thoughts was

    the critical realization that individual specific objects13

    were less important than the systems within which those

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    7/8

    Douglass Bailey96

    individual objects existed and were arranged. As important

    was the final level of understanding: the individual objects

    didnt really matter at all. The only important entities

    were the ordered sets of objects. The arrangement became

    the end; the individual form had become nothing more

    than the means.

    In doing this I wish to imply neither metaphor nor

    analogy.

    Neolithic significances

    Thinking about the Minimal art of the 1960s in these

    ways helps us in our investigation of the meaning of

    Neolithic houses, and in our desires to better understand

    the formal similarities of the Neolithic built environment

    and the aggregation of Neolithic buildings into villages.

    We can begin to finish by thinking in different ways

    about what we excavate and what it is that we interpret in

    such precise ways.

    First, we should think about Neolithic buildings as

    anti-compositional and non-referential. Their importance

    lies not only in what they contain or in how each building

    in a village was constructed. If we accept this, then most

    of the explanations and interpretations of Neolithic

    building and building morphology14 have only offered us

    a portion of the meaning of buildings. In fact in the terms

    sketched out in this chapter, our existing schemes and

    attitudes to the Neolithic built environment could be

    rejected as the anti-thesis of meaning. Second, it is useful

    to think of Neolithic buildings as empty spaces, asnegative volumes, and as the manifestations of hollowness

    and empty space. Third, we should think about Neolithic

    buildings as environmental, at least as that term is applied

    to the Minimalist object. Neolithic buildings, thus,

    positioned Neolithic people in space, not simply in the

    sense of architecture directing movement or choreo-

    graphing social relations, but in the sense of buildings as

    objects that push the spectator/villager/visitor away from

    the building and its contents.

    If we think in these ways, then spectators are turned

    away from the individual components of a particular

    architectural design or form and find themselves lookingat, living among, studying and excavating logical series

    where repetition of a common form pushes them to think

    away from the house and its contents. Furthermore, the

    importance of Neolithic buildings is not to be found only

    inside any particular one of them or only through the

    detailed analysis of any one of them. These buildings

    were/are specific objects. They are physical and palpable

    but they are not representational or illusionistic. Their

    shape is their meaning; their shape is the object. They

    are anti-compositional; in this sense they are not rational

    and thus will not repay rational decisions based on

    rational questions seeking rational answers.

    What was a Neolithic building in the Neolithic? In

    addition to the existing understandings, we would be

    well served to consider an additional perspective. From

    this perspective we see a Neolithic building as a specific

    object that forced people to think externally about

    themselves in relations to others, as a specific object that

    slid down without chewing, and as a specific object that

    was accepted without thinking. Likewise, the importanceof aggregations of Neolithic buildings may not be found

    in any particular building but in all of them in a series of

    repeated, almost identical objects: it is this series that we

    have been calling a village or a camp. What is a Neolithic

    village from a Neolithic perspective? It is a serial order

    of specific objects. In fact it is, in itself, a single specific

    object. At yet another remove, it is just one specific object

    within a longer serial order of villages across a landscape,

    up a river valley, across a region and through a sequence

    running for hundreds and sometimes thousands of years.

    The most important significance of invoking these

    concepts for thinking through the meanings of Neolithichouses, through the similarity of their form and through

    the logic of their aggregations is less specific. The

    Minimalist perspective may not be of value because it

    presents new information; indeed I am not suggesting

    that it does. Rather, conceits such as the serial order, the

    specific object, serial repetition and environmental

    engagements between spectator and work, have sig-

    nificances because they push us away from the search for

    a single, closed meaning of the Neolithic built environ-

    ment. This is/not a house. This is/not a household. This

    is/not a place of shelter. This is/not evidence of privacy

    and social inequality. This is/not a village. The challenge

    will be to see if the perspective elaborated in this chaptercan work alongside the current knowledges, methods and

    accumulated understandings of Neolithic buildings and

    villages that we have become so proficient in developing.

    This is the provocation, but so, I suggest, were the houses

    and villages of the Neolithic.

    Notes

    1 For an excellent and detailed discussion of the PrimaryStructures show see Meyer (2001, 1330).

    2 Key essays and discussions are included in Meyer (2000;

    2001), Batchelor (1997), Battcock (1968), and Strickland(2000).

    3 For more on Donald Judd, see his collected writings (Judd

    1975; 1987; 1991), especially Specific objects (Judd 1965)and the main synthetic and summary work (Serota 2003).

    4 For more on Robert Morris, see Tsouti-Schillinger (2001),

    Meyer (2001, 15366) and particularly the series Notes onsculpture (Morris 1966a; 1966b; 1967).

    5 For more on Sol LeWitt, see his Paragraphs on conceptualart(LeWitt 1967), as well as Legg (1978), Garrels (2000),Baume et al. (2001), and Batchelor et al. (2002).

    6 For more on Carl Andre, see Cole (1997).

    7 For more on Dan Flavin, see Govan (1998) and Ragheb

    (1999).

    8 Dr. William Price (1800-93), doctor and eccentric, believed

    himself to be a descendant of the Druids, and at

  • 7/30/2019 Ch10 Douglass Bailey

    8/8

    Beyond the meaning of Neolithic houses 97

    Pontypridds Rocking Stone he held ceremonies which the

    Puritans considered to be Satanic. His home-made costume

    clashed with the normal Victorian idea of sartorial decorum:

    white cloak, green trousers, scarlet waistcoat, and on his

    head a fox fur with legs and tail dangling. This is how he

    stands in bronze in his hometown Llantrisant, with a bushy

    beard, a crescent moon in his hand, and both arms

    outstretched like the Christ of Rio. Dr Price was also a free

    thinker and an advocate of free love, an avid defender of

    the countryside, who gave early warning of the con-

    sequences of industrialization, a supporter of the working

    classes, who took part in the 1839 Chartist uprising in

    Newport. He was a very unusual doctor. He considered the

    wearing of socks to be unhealthy, prescribed a vegetarian

    diet instead of pills, and refused to treat patients unless

    they gave up smoking. He also attracted nationwide

    attention as a pioneer of cremation. On January 13, 1884,

    a Sunday, to the horror of his neighbours, he went to a hill

    near Llantrisant, and there used an oildrum to burn the

    body of his son Iesu Grist (Welsh for Jesus Christ). Thevillage policeman was called for, tipped up the coffin, and

    rolled out the body of the boy. Only his immediate arrest

    prevented the good doctor from himself being cremated by

    the outraged mob. At court in Cardiff he vehemently

    defended the right for people to be cremated instead of

    buried. It was this trial, in which he won his case, which

    led to the legalization of cremation in Britain. Dr. Price

    returned in triumph to Llantrisant, where he lived happily

    ever after with his young housekeeper Gwenllian, became

    a father again at 90, and when at last his strength began to

    ebb away, he lay down on a couch, asked for a glass of

    champagne, and died. His own cremation in 1893 was

    attended by thousands of sightseers, and afterwards the

    pubs ran dry (Sager 1991, 136).

    9 This of course is not completely true as a major stimulus of

    much minimalist art was the particular material used to

    create the objects: non-traditional, industrial materials such

    as concrete, aluminium, Perspex, steel. These materials

    had very particular reference to a non-artistic world which

    was not the one inhabited by traditionally appropriate art

    materials such as marble, clay, plaster and bronze.

    10 Dan Flavin used fluorescent light bulbs as objects to be

    arranged and repeated; Andre also used stacks of blocks of

    wood; Judd used plywood or metal cubes lined up

    horizontally on walls or vertically on the floor (he also

    used identical rectangular boxes in series running from

    floor to ceiling his stacks).11 On seriality, see Bochner (1967) and Meyer (2001, 17883).

    12 Think about this process next time you eat a McDonalds

    BigMac (regardless of the location of the restaurant) or

    stay in a room at a Hilton Hotel (regardless of the city).

    13 And indeed the archaeologists Neolithic house.

    14 My own included (Bailey 1990; 1999; 2000).

    Bibliography

    Bailey, D.W. 1990. The living house: signifying continuity. In

    R. Samson (ed.), The social archaeology of houses,1948.Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Bailey, D.W. 1999. Pit-huts and surface-level structures: the

    built environment in the Balkan Neolithic. DocumentaPraehistorica (Ljubljana) 25, 1530.

    Bailey, D.W. 2000.Balkan prehistory: exclusion, incorporationand identity. London: Routledge.

    Batchelor, D. 1997. Min ima lism. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

    Batchelor, D., Krauss, R. and Elliott, D. 2002. Sol LeWitt:structures 19621993. Oxford: Oxford Museum of ModernArt.

    Battcock, G. (ed.) 1968 Minimal art. A critical anthology.[1995 edition] Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Baume, N., Flatley, J. and Lee, P.M. (eds) 2001. Sol LeWitt:incomplete open cubes. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Bochner, M. 1967. The serial attitude. Artforum 6, 737.Cole, I. (ed.) 1997. Carl Andre and the sculptural imagination.

    Oxford: Museum of Modern Art.

    Colpitt, F. 1990.Minimal art: the critical perspective. Seattle:University of Washington Press.

    Flannery, K.V. 1972. The origins of the village as a settlement

    type in Mesoamerica and the Near East. In P. Ucko, R.

    Tringham and D.W. Dimbleby (eds), Man, settlement and

    urbanism, 2353. London: Duckworth.Flannery, K. 2002. The origins of the village revisited: from

    nuclear to extended households. American Antiquity 67,417.

    Garrels, J. 2000. Sol LeWitt: A retrospective. San Francisco:Museum of Modern Art.

    Govan, M. (ed.) 1998. Dan Flavin. New York: Dia Center.Harrison, C. and Wood, P. (eds) 2003. Art in theory 1900

    2000. Oxford: Blackwell.Judd, D. 1965. Specific objects. Arts Yearbook8, 7482.Judd, D. 1975. Donald Judd complete writings, 19591975.

    New York: New York University.

    Judd, D. 1987. Donald Judd complete writings 19751986.Eindhoven: Stedelijk van Abbemuseum.

    Judd, D. 1991.Donald Judd: crits 19631990. Paris: GalerieLelong.

    Legg, A. (ed.) 1978. Sol LeWitt. New York: MetropolitanMuseum of Art.

    LeWitt, S. 1967. Paragraphs on conceptual art. Artforum 5,7983.

    LeWitt, S. 1969. Sentences on conceptual art.Art-Language 1,1113.

    Lippard, L. 1969. 10 Strukturisten in 20 Abstzen. In E.

    Develing and L.R. Lippard (eds), Minimal Art, 22937.Dsseldorf: Stdtische Kunsthalle.

    Meyer, J. (ed.) 2000. Minimalism. London: Phaidon.Meyer, J. 2001. Minimalism: art, and polemics in the sixities.

    New Haven: Yale University Press.Morris, R. 1966a. Notes on sculpture. Part 1.Artforum 4, 424.Morris, R. 1966b. Notes on sculpture. Part 2.Artforum 5, 203.Morris, R. 1967. Notes on sculpture. Part 3: Notes and

    nonsequiturs.Artforum 5, various pages.Potts, A. 2000. The sculptural imagination. Figurative,

    modernist, minimalist. New Haven, Conn.: Yale UniversityPress.

    Ragheb, J.F. (ed.) 1999. Dan Flavin: the architecture of l ight.New York: Guggenheim Foundation.

    Sager, P. 1991. Wales. London: Pallas Athene.Serota, N. (ed.) 2004. Donald Judd. London: Tate Publishing.Strickland, E. 2000.Minimalism: origins. Bloomington: Indiana

    University Press.

    Tsouti-Schillinger, N. 2001.Robert Morris and angst. London:George Braziller.