creativity in mathematics - noah litvin

Upload: noah-litvin

Post on 06-Apr-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    1/26

    Creativity in Mathematics

    Noah Litvin

    St. John's College, Annapolis MD

    February 4th, 2012

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    2/26

    1

    I. Introduction

    Mathematicians are creative. We find ourselves surprised by proofs, baffled by

    conjectures, and amazed by algorithms. But this is not the only perspective from which we

    consider mathematicians. Since the Pythagoreans, philosophers have held up mathematics as a

    paradigm of certainty. Mathematicians appear to be discovering a set of laws that govern the

    universe. We are certain of these laws despite the varying accuracy of our application of them to

    the physical world through the sciences. From this latter perspective, the former requires further

    scrutiny. In what sense can mathematicians be creative?

    This question becomes more pressing when considering mathematicians move to create

    a fully formal mathematics in the twentieth century. The possibility of generating all

    mathematical truths through an algorithm did not invalidate the idea of a creative mathematician

    but put it in a tenuous position. The mathematician could be creative in choosing which chain of

    valid logical deductions to follow but is not creating anything new.

    In hisRemarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Wittgenstein offers an alternative

    perspective. For him, the mathematician is an inventor, not a discoverer (168).1 Their

    inventions can be understood in two non-exclusive categories: some offer a new ability and some

    provide a new psychological aspect. Additionally, Wittgensteins conception of mathematics

    dissolves the metaphysical and ontological questions that surround mathematics.

    II. Mathematical Formalism

    In the twentieth century, many mathematicians attempted to uncover the foundations of

    mathematics. Since EuclidsElements, it was implicit in the presentation of mathematical works

    1Ludwig Wittgenstein,Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, ed. G. H. von

    Wright, R. Rhees, G. E. M. Anscombe, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983). Further citations will refer to this work

    unless otherwise noted.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    3/26

    2

    that mathematicians should always begin with basic principles and, from them, deduce other

    valid propositions. Yet geometers in particular found themselves unsatisfied with the basic

    principles they were working from. Euclids definitions, common notions, and postulates lacked

    rigor. That is, Euclid and many of the mathematicians that followed him were making

    assumptions that were not made explicit. Hilbert sought to fix these oversights by choosing a

    simple and complete set ofindependentaxioms (Foundations of Geometry, Introduction).2

    To most mathematicians, this task could seem entirely superfluous. Mathematicians may

    very well have been assuming as an axiom, for instance, that if two planes , have a point A in

    common, then they have at least a second point B in common (Foundations of Geometry, I, 6).

    Making this particular axiom explicit is inconsequential to the development of mathematics. But

    ifevery axiom of mathematics were listed and the task of fully formalizing mathematics were

    achieved, an interesting possibility would arise. It would seem that if one were to establish a

    complete set of axioms and rules of inference, an algorithm could be developed which could

    generate all mathematical truths. This appeared to be a feasible task until the publication of

    GdelsIncompleteness Theorem which demonstrated that it could not be realized; some

    undecidable propositions will exist in a consistent system capable of expressing just the basic

    propositions of arithmetic. But even without the development of Gdels theorem, the task of

    generating a complete set of axioms and laws of inference could still seem questionable. The

    criterion by which one is to decide which propositions deserve the status ofaxiom is unclear.

    Hilberts three criteria supply only a general idea. If one were to come into dispute over the

    simplicity of a given axiom (or its worthiness for inclusion in general), it is not clear how this

    matter could be settled.

    2David Hilbert, Foundations of Geometry, trans. E. J. Townsend, (Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publising, LLC, 2010).

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    4/26

    3

    One can temporarily put these difficulties associated with the choosing of axioms aside.

    Even without complete certainty regarding the validity of ones axioms, one can still be

    confident that the laws of inference will generate truepropositions if ones axioms are true.

    Wittgenstein suggests that this is indicative of a mindset of one for whom reality is something

    very abstract, very general, and very rigid. Logic is a kind of ultra-physics, the description of the

    logical structure of the world, which we perceive through a kind ultra-experience (with the

    understanding e.g.) (8).

    From this perspective, mathematics would allow for creativity, but in a limited sense. The

    mathematician would be akin to an explorer, traversing this logical structure of the world. He

    could be creative insofar as he could choose which path he would like to follow, but he could not

    forge his own path (as this would be to defy the laws of inference). Turing summarizes this well:

    When working with a formal logic ingenuity will then determine which steps are the most

    profitable for the purpose of proving a particular proposition (Systems of Logic Based on

    Ordinals, p. 208).

    III. Wittgensteins Conception of Logic

    Wittgenstein offers an alternative perspective on mathematicsone in which

    mathematicians are genuinely creative. For him, the mathematician is an inventor, not a

    discoverer (168), a creator of essences (32). His view is contrary to that of the mathematical

    formalists of the twentieth century. His disagreement rests in his conception of mathematical

    axioms as well as that of logical inference.

    Rather than seeing logic as an ultra-physics which consists of the laws that govern reality,

    Wittgenstein understands logic as a description of what we call thinking (that is, what we call

    thinkingproperly).

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    5/26

    4

    The propositions of logic are laws of thought, because they bring out the

    essence of human thinking to put it more correctly: because they bring out, or shew,

    the essence, the technique, of thinking. They shew what thinking is and also shew kinds

    of thinking.

    Logic, it may be said, shews us what we understand by proposition and bylanguage (133-134).

    Here, Wittgenstein is applying his understanding of words meanings as use, introduced

    in the Philosophical Investigations, to logic. Rather than thinking of words as symbols that refer

    to things (be they physical objects, concepts, etc.), words are akin to tools which have different

    uses in different contexts. This view encourages one to keep in mind how children learn the

    meanings of words as well as the situations in which one uses words.

    For example, one may assert the proposition, Socrates is mortal. That man may assert

    another proposition, IfSocrates is mortal then Socrates will die. Now consider what would

    occur if the man were to state Socrates will not die with utter confidence. One would likely say

    that this man could not possibly think these three propositions at once, despite the fact that he

    can clearly say aloud all three of these propositions. But, for Wittgenstein, this would merely be

    indicative of the way in which one uses the word thinking. This is to say, it is for us an

    essential part of thinking that in talking, writing, etc.he makes thissort of transition

    (116). So if someone were to say that he could actually think all three of these propositions,

    then a disagreement would arise regarding in which contexts it is proper to use the word

    thinking.

    One may insist that this is not a linguistic issue, but a psychological one. Despite the

    words varying uses among people and contexts, one could study thinking, the mental

    phenomenon, in some sort of laboratory setting to determine scientifically the possibility of

    contradictory thought. But, for Wittgenstein, this is only to push the issue a step back. In

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    6/26

    5

    determining what sort of empirical result would serve as ample evidence, one is making clearer

    what sorts of things one calls thinking. And disagreement could just as well be met at this

    stage.

    One may still take recourse in pointing out that anyone could very well assert that

    Socrates will not die, but it simply would not be true. Use and meaning, one might insist, are

    related but not interchangeable. To better understand Wittgensteins stance, the inquiry should

    now focus on the use of the word true. One need not maintain that truth is some sort of ethereal

    property which is associated with some propositions and not others. Instead, one should consider

    how the word is taught and used in ordinary language. For example, from this perspective, it

    should be clear that the proposition: It is true that this follows from that means simply: this

    follows from that (5). There is, perhaps, an interesting and subtle nuance in meaning between

    the two propositions. And this would come out in thinking about the situations in which one

    would explicitly assert a propositions truth. In this way, one can come to understand the rich

    variety of meanings that the word truth carries.

    So, although logical inference can be thought of as a method which generates new true

    propositions from other true propositions, it may be more appropriate to understand logical

    inference as a transformation of our expression (9). That is, the distinguishing characteristic

    of a proposition which is a logical inference from one that is not is that the former can be

    generated from previously asserted propositions through the use of certain rules. From this

    perspective, the rules themselves should be understood as propositions regarding grammar and

    language. Take, for example, Modus Ponens: (P(PQ))Q. This would appear to be a rule by

    which reality abides. Alternatively, one could see Modus Ponens as part of a definition for the

    word therefore or implies.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    7/26

    6

    One might object that this latter perspective does not take into account the fact that one is

    compelled by logical deductions. Certainly logical deductions compelbut in what sense? In

    ordinary language, it comes out that a proof has compelled someone in the fact that once [one

    has] got it [one goes] ahead in such-and-such a way, and [refuses] any other path (34). If an

    individual who is compelled by a proof is met with disagreement regarding the proofs

    conclusion or legitimacy, the individual would likely insist Dont you see?! without providing

    further argument. Additionally, the sense in which one is compelled by a proof is similar to the

    way in which a man is compelled by another pointing him down a single path (117). That is, if

    the man were to point down two different paths at once (providing two different options), one

    would say the man being directed is not compelled to go down the particular path he eventually

    walks. Similarly, a law of inference compels in the sense that it insists one particular conclusion;

    no choice is offered whether or not one accepts Modus Ponens, for instance, at any particular

    point in the proof.

    Still one may insist that this explanation is insufficient. This explanation may make it

    seem as if one is not truly compelled. One mustgo a certain way according to the laws of

    inference. No one can break these laws. But this isnt actually the case. As mentioned previously,

    someone could very well assert Socrates will not die after claimingSocrates is mortal and

    If Socrates is mortal then Socrates will die. One might call this individual a madman or insist

    that he cant really think that. Here, again, this latter statement would more accurately be

    interpreted as a remark about what the critic calls thinking. Perhaps one is trying e.g. to say:

    he cant fill it with personal content; he cant really go along with itpersonally, with his

    intelligence (116). And this certainly makes sense. But the limiting factor here is not stemming

    from a law of inference. It is a practical limitation.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    8/26

    7

    From these considerations, it would appear that the laws of inference compel, but in the

    same sense, that is to say, as other laws in human society (116). This becomes clearer when

    one considers a situation in which someone actually draws an inference. In 17, Wittgenstein

    offers an example: A regulation may state that all men taller than five foot, six are to join a

    particular section. A clerk is told that a particular man is five foot, nine. He now attempts to draw

    an inference. All men taller than five foot, six are to join this section; This man is taller than five

    foot, six; Therefore, this man should notjoin this section. Here, the clerk has broken a law of

    inference. For this, the clerk will perhaps suffer certain practical consequencesno more, no

    less.

    One still may insist that though the clerk, in this case, could break a law of inference, the

    law itself is inexorable. Keep in mind that, of course, a law does not apply itself. Rather, in

    calling a law inexorable, Wittgenstein suggests that one is employing an image, a picture of a

    single inexorable judge, and many lax judges (118). This inexorable judge makes no

    exceptions when enforcing the law. Similarly, the laws of inference never allow for

    discrimination (i.e. provide an option) to the person applying them. As with the man pointing

    another down one path rather than many, this is the sense in which a law of inference is

    inexorable.

    So the conception that logic allows one to traverse the facts that constitute reality and, in

    doing so, make discoveries may not be entirely justified. Rather, through a reconsideration of

    meaning in language, it would seem that logical propositions work to describe what we call

    thinking, proposition, and language. The sense in which the laws of inference compel us are no

    different than the sense in which the other laws of our society do. The structure which logic

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    9/26

    8

    provides should not be thought of as foundational. Rather, logic seems to be a system of analysis

    which can be applied to ordinary language and activities.

    IV. Mathematics as Activity

    Regardless of how one conceives of logic, one may still hold on to the basic propositions

    of arithmetic and geometry as undeniable truths. One may think of these propositions as

    fundamental to the constitution of reality, separate from human experience. Wittgenstein, again,

    offers an alternative perspective. For him, the basic propositions of mathematics are best

    understood as describing activities.

    One should begin by considering how to teach the basic propositions of arithmetic. One

    would likely begin by teaching a student the series of cardinal numbers. A teacher would use a

    group of objects to demonstrate different quantities. Once the student had mastered the technique

    of counting, the student could move on to addition. Two apples could be set on a table and

    correctly counted by the student. Two more apples could subsequently be placed on the table.

    Then, the student would count four total apples. With a brief explanation of arithmetic

    vocabulary, it could be said that the student now understands what the proposition Two plus

    two equals four means. Now imagine a strange situation in which this same process is

    conducted, but six apples are counted rather than four. Assuming the student had not made an

    oversight, one must say that apples are no good for teaching sums. It is essential to summation

    that two and two yield four. If all solid bodies were to express the same irregularity the erratic

    apples had, that would be the end of all sums (37).

    So, in the same sense one is compelled to make logical inferences, one is compelled to

    count (and perform all sorts of mathematical operations) the way one does. Counting (and that

    means: counting like this) is a technique that is employed daily in the most various operations of

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    10/26

    9

    our lives (4). One could certainly count however one pleases, but the particular technique of

    counting society employs is not arbitrary. One would very quickly run into practical difficulties

    if one were to count otherwise. Further, mathematical operations are as inexorable as logical

    inference insofar as both leave no ambiguity regarding proper execution. In the series of cardinal

    numbers, for example, three follows two every time. Counting does not admit of a choice on the

    part of the one counting.

    From this perspective, the privileged epistemological status of mathematics begins to

    fade. It cant be said of the series of natural numbers any more than of our languagethat it is

    true, but: that it is usable, and above all, it is used (4). It is undeniable that there is a great

    quantity of men across various cultures who assent to the basic propositions of mathematics. But

    it remains that basic mathematical propositions are not qualitatively different than others in

    regards to their truth. They are just as much rooted in experiment as the sciences . In the usual

    presentation of mathematics, this is obscured.

    One could insist that the practical applications of mathematics and the consensus of the

    mathematical community are only consequences of apropositions validity. This validity stands

    apart from human activity and relies solely on the propositions proof. But, for Wittgenstein, all

    symbols (including those used in mathematical proofs) carry meaning only insofar as they are

    used. For instance, even this simple arrow, , could be understood as pointing left with the stem

    springing out of the head in the direction one is supposed to understand it (if one were taught to

    interpret it in this way). The arrow points only in the application that a living creature makes of

    it (Philosophical Investigations, 454).3 This applies to proofs and even very simple diagrams

    which may serve as proof.

    3Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker, Joachim Schulte,

    ed. P. M. S. Hacker, Joachim Schulte, (Chichester, West Sussex, U.K., 2009).

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    11/26

    10

    Wittgenstein most succinctly demonstrates this in 38:

    Figure A Figure B

    One might suggest that Figure A proves that 2 + 2 = 4. But one could just as well use

    Figure B to prove that 2 + 2 + 2 = 4. This example draws out how, even in this seemingly simple

    example, there is an implicit procedure and set of rules which lead to certain outcomes. In this

    case, one is to draw four Xs. One must then circle them in groups of two. It is crucial during this

    step that the circles do not overlap. One must also trust that no single X will be left outside of a

    circle. Add 2 for each circle. This should yield the same result as the total number of Xs one

    counts. This description should make clear how this example could be better understood as a

    picture of an experiment (36) rather than a demonstration of an undeniable intuition of space.

    One can also consider this from the perspective of a mathematician devising a proof. A

    mathematician may conjecture that all hexagons consist of six equilateral triangles (c.f. Euclids

    Elements, IV.15). He may become convinced of this through the use of triangular shaped pieces

    or perhaps through the drawing of various examples with a compass and ruler. He could then

    translate what he is accepting as proof into mathematical language. That is, he would not write,

    Take a hexagon and overlay six triangles with sides equal to a side of the hexagon. Rather, the

    proof would likely begin, Let there be a Hexagon ABCDEF. The latter form of expression

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    12/26

    11

    hides the temporal, active nature of what the mathematician is discussing. Because of this shift in

    language, one is inclined to say that the latter expresses a mathematical truth which stands apart

    from human activity. Yet, it would seem that the former account is more honest to what the

    mathematician has really done.

    This former mode of expression would seem entirely unacceptable for valid mathematical

    proof. But it is not far from Euclids use of superposition and coincidence in his proof of

    Proposition I.4 in The Elements. This proof has caused discomfort among mathematicians

    because it points out the temporal and experimental origins from which many basic mathematical

    proofs arise. Hilbert was able to avoid using coincidence as a method in the proof of this

    proposition in his Foundations of Geometry. Yet, that this was possible changes nothing.

    Euclidean geometry would have progressed all the same if it were not possible (or without

    Hilberts publication) as it had for millennia.

    Calculus employs motion in its fundamental proofs as well. In Lemma 6 of Newtons

    Principia, the two points A and B approach each other. Although now there has been a shift

    away from Newtons vocabulary in favor ofone of limits, it has been just that: a shift in

    vocabulary. It is indicative of mathematicians distaste for their use of physical experience and

    intuitions. After all, both a Newtonian proof and a more modern proof should be equally

    persuasive if their basic principles are accepted and their steps are fully understood.

    Wittgenstein uses a simple example to draw out the implicit activity in geometric proof

    and the subsequent adjustment of language in 25:

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    13/26

    12

    Figure C Figure D

    The pattern of lines depicted in Figure C is ascertained to be like-numbered with a

    particular pattern of angles, Figure D, through a process of correlation. An image of this

    correlation is offered in Figure E:

    Figure E

    If Figure E were supplied without this context dictating how one is to interpret this

    diagram, it could just as well be a star with threadlike appendages (25). But the reader is

    given a context. The lines which connect our initial lines to the angles were drawn in an effort to

    discover whether or not they were like-numbered. The outcome was unknown. It may be

    tempting to say that this is not the case, but this is only for the fact that the patterns each consist

    of so few elements. If there were a large number of lines in Figure C and a very irregular figure

    in place of Figure D, as in 27, the outcome of a one-to-one correspondence is more obviously

    unknown at first glance. Once one has established that there is a like number of angles and lines

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    14/26

    13

    in 25, one can further extrapolate that, if one were to have men standing in the pattern depicted

    by Figure D and wands arranged on a wall as in Figure C, each man could have one wand. In this

    way, the diagram is a schematicpicture of[ones] giving the five men a wand (26).

    There is an alternative conception of this diagram:

    I can however conceive figure [E] as a mathematical proof. Let us give names to

    the shapes of the patterns [C] and [D]: let [C]be called a hand, H, and [D] a pentacle,

    P. I have proved that H has as many strokes as P has angles. And this is once more non-

    temporal (27).

    One would be tempted to take this latter conception as primary. That is, one could say that our

    mathematical proof has revealed an essence of hands and pentacles (namely, that their lines and

    angles are same in number). And it is for this reason that the one-to-one correlation process is

    successful between these two figures. From this perspective, one must insist that it is impossible

    for a hands lines and a pentacles angles to be different in number.

    But, as was the case with logical inference, one could imagine a man coming up with this

    impossible result. There are two ways in which one could address a man who asserted that the

    lines of a hand and the angles of a pentacle are not same in number. One would first assume that

    this man had made an error in the process of drawing correlative lines. Perhaps, one would

    assume that he omitted a line or he miscounted the correctly drawn lines. Or one might say that

    this man must not have understood what it means to correlate these figures. But if there were no

    problem in this mans act of correlation, then one would conclude that the subjects of his

    correlation were not, in fact, a hand and a pentacle. In other words, it is necessary for a figure to

    be called a hand or a pentacle that it has the same number of lines or angles as the other.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    15/26

    14

    The proof doesnt explore the essence of the two figures, but it does express

    what I am going to count as belonging to the essence of the figures from now on.Ideposit what belongs to the essences among the paradigms of language.

    The mathematician creates essences (32).

    One might insist that this is still a discovery, as one is now entirely certain that this like-

    numbered property always will be and always has been the case. Undoubtedly in an enormous

    majority of cases [one] will always get same result, and, if [one] did not get it, [we] would think

    that something had put [one] out (31). But what is the motivation behind asserting that this

    result has uncovered something that was, in some sense, already there? One may imagine that if

    men were standing in a pentacle and wands were arranged in a hand, each man would be able to

    receive one and only one wand. Alternatively, one could imagine drawing Figure C and Figure D

    on a sheet of paper and then connecting each line and angle with one and only one line. Neither

    of these examples is contingent on a particular time period. There is no reason to think either of

    these activities, when executed correctly, would yield a different result today, tomorrow, or

    yesterday. This should make clear that the atemporal sense of this proposition is predicated on

    the expectation of certain results of various human activities.

    V. Surprise in Mathematics

    Wittgensteins perspective may draw into question how surprise could be possible in

    mathematics. If mathematicians are not making discoveries (but, rather, inventing), it is not

    immediately apparent what could cause surprise. It would seem that someone should not be

    surprised by ones own creation. Wittgenstein identifies two different roles surprise plays in

    mathematics.

    Many would say that the results of mathematical proof are surprising because the results

    show the depths to which mathematical investigation penetrates; - as we might measure the

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    16/26

    15

    value of telescope by its shewing us things that wed have had no inkling of without this

    instrument (Appendix II, 1). This role, which is dominant at the present day (Appendix II,

    1), is illegitimate. The results of any chain of inferences are not like those of an experiment.

    That is, if a proof is fully understood, no surprise should be had at any particular step, including

    the final one.

    The other role of surprise in mathematics that Wittgenstein describes is often experienced

    when one comes to a proof of a proposition or finds the solution to a mathematical puzzle. This

    is a pleasant surprise; and it is of psychological interest, for it shows a phenomenon of failure to

    command a clear view and of the change of aspect of a seen complex (Appendix II, 2). In the

    case of a mathematical puzzle, this change of aspect is a shift from a failure to see the solution to

    success. The result itself does not surprise, but that one did not think to try the solution surprises.

    Similarly, in mathematical proof, this surprise is not at the result itself, for once the result is

    obtained, the mathematician is no longer surprised at the result of his proof, say, upon reading it

    later on.

    One could object that each time someone reads a particular proof, this individual

    continues to be surprised by the result. Wittgenstein suggests that this surprise is often brought

    on by [thinking oneself] into the situation of seeing the result after having expected something

    different (60). For instance, one may be able to imagine that a circle and a right triangle with

    legs equal to the circles circumference and radius do not have the same area, even after reading

    and understanding a proof which demonstrates that their areas are equal. Since this individual

    could imagine the conclusion being otherwise, it is possible for him to be surprised each time he

    reads the proof. If someone were to say that one could not imagine the areas to be different, the

    likelihood of this persons being surprised in reading the proof would be greatly diminished.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    17/26

    16

    Here it could be said: What the proof made me realize thats what can surprise me (69). An

    individual may be surprised by the fact that these two areas are similar after thinking this was not

    the case. He is not surprised by the result itself.

    One could also experience surprise when re-reading a mathematical proof as one does

    when hearing the turn of a theme one is already familiar with. Here, one should consider what

    meaning it would carry for someone to object that it should not be surprising (Appendix II, 3).

    Certainly, one might experience some feeling of surprise each time. And this feeling can

    accompany a discovery. But it doesnt always. This is to draw out that there are two related, but

    different, senses of the word surprise being mixed here: one, a feeling, the other, an experience

    of the unexpected.

    So, rather than thinking of proofs themselves (that is, chains of inferences) as surprising,

    one should rather understand proofs as bringing to light something that surprises us: - because it

    is of great interest, of great importance, to see how such and such a kind of representation of it

    makes a situation surprising, or astonishing, even paradoxical (Appendix II, 1).

    VI. Creativity in Mathematics

    From these considerations, an interesting framework for understanding creativity in

    mathematics emerges. It would seem that creative mathematicians provide a new aspect, a new

    ability, or both. In other words, one can say This mathematical investigation is of great

    psychological interest or of great physical interest (Appendix II, 2).

    The psychological interest that mathematical innovations can provide stems from a

    change in aspect. Wittgenstein addresses aspect change in Part II of the Philosophical

    Investigations. Jastrows duck-rabbit is offered as an example of a picture which, for most

    people, prompts a change of aspect (PIPt. II, 118).

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    18/26

    17

    Jastrows Duck-Rabbit

    One could imagine someone who could only see this picture as a picture of a duck.

    Subsequently, for whatever reason, this person could see this picture as a picture of a rabbit.

    What was formerly the ducks bill is now perceived as a pair of ears and the eye now appears to

    be looking right, rather than left. The image on the page does not change, but this person

    describes the change just as if the object had changed before [ones] eyes (PIPt. II, 129).

    The expression of a change of aspect is an expression of a new perception and, at the same time,

    an expression of an unchanged perception (PIPt. II, 130).

    So it is with the solution to a mathematical puzzle. Wittgenstein introduces a Chinese

    tangram as an example of mathematical puzzle in 42.

    Figure F Figure G

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    19/26

    18

    In a Chinese tangram, one is given a set of puzzle pieces (Figure F) which must be

    arranged to create a given shape (Figure G). After extensive trial and error, one could become

    convinced that the creator of the puzzle must have erred and the pieces of the puzzle cannot be

    arranged to form such a shape. If there were a solution, for the puzzle solver it would seem as if

    a demon has cast a spell round this position and excluded it from our space (45).

    But then the solution to the puzzle is provided:

    Figure H

    Cant we say: the figure which shews you the solution removes a blindness, or again

    changes your geometry? It as it were shews you a new dimension of space (44). Before, in the

    case of 42, one may not have seen a rectangle as a combination of two pairs of congruent right

    triangles. But now one does. This can be understood as a change of aspect, similar to how ones

    perception of the duck-rabbit changes.

    Mathematical proofs can provide a new aspect in a manner similar to that of the solution

    to a mathematical puzzle. For example, someone could consider the geometric proposition, A

    straight line is an infinitely large circle, complete nonsense. It could be said that this person

    does not see straight lines in this way. But after following and understanding the relevant proof

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    20/26

    19

    in GalileosDiscourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Relating to Two New Sciences, this

    person would likely begin to see them in this way.

    The parallel between mathematical puzzles and mathematical proofs extends further. In

    the case of thepuzzle, imagine that one of the pieces is lying so as to be the mirror-image of

    the corresponding part of the pattern (49). The solution, previously impossible, becomes

    available through the employment of a new technique: turning over the piece. Who could

    determine whether turning a piece over should be deemed a valid move in solving this puzzle?

    And on what basis could one make this judgment? If someone asserted that it were not a valid

    move but it would solve the puzzle (and no other method could), it would be difficult to take this

    objection seriously. This situation is similar to the one previously mentioned regarding Euclids

    use of coincidence. Propositions, which formerly could not be proved, now can be proved with a

    new technique. And new techniques in mathematical proof can yield interesting and fruitful

    results.

    Additionally, certain mathematical puzzles we find terribly uninteresting just as we do

    many mathematical proofs. Consider the tangram presented in 70:

    Figure I

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    21/26

    20

    This shows us that a rectangle can be made out of certain non-rectangular shapes, just

    like the puzzle in 45. But this puzzle is boring. One should be able to solve it without much

    difficultly at all. Only in very rare circumstances would someone find this interesting. (For

    instance, a man who owns two separate plots of land shaped like each of the pieces might be

    excited by this puzzle.) Similarly, there are plenty of trivial geometric and algebraic proofs. They

    too are easy to generate and understand but they do not offer a new aspect with which one can

    understand the entities involved.

    One may insist that, in all of these examples, these aspects are revealed (i.e. discovered),

    rather than created or invented by the mathematician. This is not without good reason. When

    experiencing a change of aspect, it certainly seems as if the new aspect were somehow already

    there. When one experiences a change of aspect with the duck-rabbit, for example, the ink on the

    page obviously does not change. And one could imagine experiencing that particular change of

    aspect any time in the past (at least any time after one were made familiar with what rabbits look

    like). But it would be nonsensical to say that the aspect, this perception, was there before it was

    perceived. In the mathematical puzzle in 42, the individual unable to solve the puzzle simply

    did not see the rectangle in such a way. When the solution is demonstrated, The new position

    has as it were come out of nothingness. Where there was nothing, now there suddenly is

    something (46).

    The mathematical formalists of the twentieth century would likely acknowledge that this

    psychological phenomenon occurs, but it would not carry the same significance that it does for

    Wittgenstein. Likewise, practical application is often considered ancillary to the task of

    mathematicians. But, from Wittgensteins perspective (which emphasizes the activity implicit in

    mathematical proof), the use of mathematics should be considered more important. In fact, many

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    22/26

    21

    of the propositions ofEuclidsElements show the reader how to do many things (e.g. Create an

    equilateral triangle with only a compass and straight-edge; find the length of a right triangles

    hypotenuse from the length of its legs; etc.).

    The solution to the mathematical puzzle, for example, does more than provide a new

    aspect. Before, you could not[solve] itand now perhaps you can (47). So it is with the hand

    and pentacle demonstration as well: The proposition proved by [the diagram] now serves as a

    new prescription for ascertaining numerical equality (30). That is, one can now arrange one set

    of objects into a pentacle and another set of objects into a hand and know that they are like

    numbered, without performing any correlation.

    It should be emphasized that proofs do not need to provide a new ability (though they

    often do). There is not one simple motivation underlying all mathematical innovation.

    Wittgenstein suggests a metaphor:

    a mathematician is always inventing new forms of description. Some, stimulated bypractical needs, others, from aesthetic needs, - and yet others in a variety of ways. And

    here imagine a landscape gardener designing paths for the layout of a garden; it may well

    be that he draws them on a drawing-board merely as ornamental strips without the

    slightest thought of someones sometime walking on them (167).

    Note that even the work of mathematical formalists can be understood in these terms. Hilbert, for

    instance, made a series of aesthetic judgments in writing and organizing his Foundations of

    Geometry. He was not necessarily concerned with any practical consequences of his work.

    VII. Example

    Consider thisproposition from EuclidsElements: If in a right-angled triangle a

    perpendicular is drawn from the right angle to the base, then the triangles adjoining the

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    23/26

    22

    perpendicular are similar both to the whole and to one another (EuclidsElements, VI.8). This

    proposition serves to provide both a new ability and a new aspect.

    The proof demonstrates how one can generate two similar right triangles from any given

    right triangle assuming one has the ability to draw a line perpendicular to another from a given

    point. Compared to the innovations made possible by calculus, this ability is not particularly

    exciting. Rather, most find this proposition interesting for the aspect change it provides. As with

    the mathematical puzzle, one may not have thought that this shape could be divided into these

    two other shapes. This process could even be performed indefinitely on newly generated

    triangles. It might be said that, after reading this proposition, one sees all right-angled triangles

    in a new way.

    It may be tempting to say that this account does not draw out the importance of the rigor

    in the proof of the proposition. One could gain this new ability and aspect through simply

    looking at its corresponding diagram, but the proposition requires proof. One may very well be

    compelled to assert this proposition by applying laws of inference to the axioms of geometry.

    But this compulsion occurs in the sense discussed before. If one were to stray from this

    conclusion (whether it were presented on the grounds of a rigorous proof or merely a diagram),

    one could run up against various practical difficulties. The rigor of the proof may offer its reader

    greater certainty than just the diagram and enunciation. But it need not necessarily. For instance,

    a layman who is unfamiliar with logical and geometric language would likely become more

    certain of this proposition if given the enunciation with a diagram rather than a rigorous

    geometric proof.

    Regardless of the certainty this proof grants, one may be surprised by this proof. But

    again, it is not that any particular step in the proof is shocking. It is what the proof made [one]

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    24/26

    23

    realize (69) which surprises: before, perhaps one had not expected two similar triangles to fit

    in a large one. Through reading the proof, the unexpected is realized. This is to be contrasted

    with the opinion that this proposition surprises by drawing out the depths to which

    mathematical investigation penetrates (Appendix II, 1), as if this proof has unearthed an

    essence of the right triangle.

    Also after reading through the proof, it may be tempting to say of right triangles , It is as

    if God constructed them like that (72). It is important that one not lose sight of the fact that this

    is a simile. One must consider in what scenario (if any) it would make sense to say that all right

    triangles could be constructed. This is drawn out by imagining someones saying The shape

    is made up of these parts; who made it? You? (72). The sense in which one could speak of

    triangles (and not a particular one) being made or constructed is an interesting one. Because one

    might be able to imagine Euclids proposition being false, it feels as if some sort of decision in a

    process of construction could have made it the case. This is what may have been meant by the

    simile employed in 72.

    When one says: This shape consists of these shapes one is thinking of the shape as a

    fine drawing, a fine frame of this shape, on which, as it were, things which have this shape are

    stretched (71). In the case of this proposition, as mentioned before, one can imagine a right

    triangle-shaped frame. If one were to lay two similar triangles of the appropriate size upon this

    frame, they would fit. This is the sense in which a shape consists of other shapes. One need not

    suppose some sort of metaphysical composition of mathematical entities which has been

    discovered by employing this proof.

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    25/26

    24

    VIII. Conclusion

    This account of mathematician as inventor, rather than discoverer, frees one of the

    metaphysical or ontological concerns which surround mathematics. For example, the question

    What are the essential properties of a straight line? is still interesting, as straight lines are very

    common in our experience of the world and our imagination. But the method of inquiry one

    should employ in addressing this question should consist in considering the various situations in

    which one calls something a straight line. The discussion would become most interesting in

    situations where people may find disagreement (e.g. in non-Euclidean geometry). But in these

    discussions, which have a philosophical character to them, one must keep in mind that the topic

    of discussion is how one uses the term straight lineone is not discussing properties of some

    sort of metaphysical mathematical object, about which there can be verification apart from

    consensus. For Wittgenstein, Philosophy must not interfere in any with the actual use of

    language, so it can in the end only describe it. For it cannot justify it either. It leaves everything

    as it is. It also leaves mathematics as it is (PI, 124).

    As mentioned previously, the mathematics that society accepts and appreciates (for

    practical reasons, aesthetic reasons, or otherwise) is not arbitrary. Experience dictates which

    mathematical propositions prove to be useful or interesting. But, for Wittgenstein, the

    widespread empirical verification of mathematics (e.g. calculation) is not the only reason

    mathematical propositions have the dignity of a rule (165). The success of mathematical

    formalists, such as Russell, in describing basic mathematical propositions in terms of logic draws

    out the close kinship mathematics has to grammar. Somuch is true when its said that

    mathematics is logic: its moves are from rules of our language to other rules of our language.

    And this gives it its peculiar solidity, its unassailable position, set apart (165).

  • 8/3/2019 Creativity in Mathematics - Noah Litvin

    26/26

    So the perspective from which mathematical formalists viewed their task and that of

    other mathematicians may not be quite right. One need not understand mathematicians as

    uncovering the propositions (foundational or otherwise) which constitute reality. Rather, one can

    understand mathematicians as forming new rules, metaphorically building new roads for traffic;

    by extending the network of old ones (166). Mathematicians throughout history have allowed

    us to make groundbreaking achievements in the sciences and to see things in new ways. And for

    this, we should not only commend their great analytic minds, but their creativity as well.