did euclid's circles have two kinds of radius?

4
Historia Mathematica 26 (1999), 361–364 Article ID hmat.1999.2254, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Did Euclid’s Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius? David Fowler Mathematics Institute, University of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL, United Kingdom and Chr. Marinus Taisbak 51 Troeroedvej, DK 2950 Vedbaek, Denmark It is often asserted that Euclid had no single word for “radius,” but rather used the description “the line drawn from the center.” We examine the linguistic practice of Euclid, Archimedes, and Apollonius and find that it is more subtle than that. C 1999 Academic Press Il est souvent dit qu’Euclide n’avait pas de mot pour “rayon,” et qu’` a sa place il se servait de la description “la ligne trac´ ee ` a partir du centre.” Nous examinons ici la pratique linguistique d’Euclide, Archim` ede, et Apollonius, pour montrer que celle-ci est plus subtile que cela. C 1999 Academic Press MSC 1991 subject classification: 01A20. Key Words: Euclid; Elements; Data; circle; radius; ruler and compass. In this note we propose that the Greek noun diastˆ ema in the dative form , the only form found in the Elements, should be understood as a special technical term in Euclid’s geometry. Although “the radius of a circle” is regularly called “the line from the center,” , he always uses diastˆ ema when he is having a circle described; the word undoubtedly does service for “radius,” and this is the only use of this word in the Elements. 1 The first such instance is in Postulate 3: [and (let it be postulated) to have a circle described with any center and radius]. [2, 1 : 5] In most discussions of the postulates it is claimed that Euclidean constructions are based on straightedge and compass. 2 It is often said that postulates 1 and 2 (“let it be postulated to produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line”) assert that a straightedge may be used to draw a line between two points or to extend a given line, while Postulate 3 says that one can use a compass to describe a circle centered at any given point with any given radius. But if that is true, how can it be that the words for straightedge ( ) and compass ( ) do not occur at all in the Elements nor, for that matter, in what has been transmitted from Archimedes and Apollonius? 1 A complete list of the 30 places where it occurs is: Postulate 3, I 1 (twice), 2 (twice), 3, 12, 22 (twice); II 14; III 17, 25, 33 (three times); IV 1, 4 (twice), 5 (twice), 8 (twice), 9, 10, 13 (twice), 14, 15; X1 1; XII 17. 2 Vitrac [3, 1 : 171-2] is an exception to this, expressing deep reservations about the standard view. 361 0315-0860/99 $30.00 Copyright C 1999 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

Upload: david-fowler

Post on 15-Jun-2016

218 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Did Euclid's Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius?

Historia Mathematica26 (1999), 361–364Article ID hmat.1999.2254, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on

Did Euclid’s Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius?

David Fowler

Mathematics Institute, University of Warwick, Coventry CV4 7AL, United Kingdom

and

Chr. Marinus Taisbak

51 Troeroedvej, DK 2950 Vedbaek, Denmark

It is often asserted that Euclid had no single word for “radius,” but rather used the description “theline drawn from the center.” We examine the linguistic practice of Euclid, Archimedes, and Apolloniusand find that it is more subtle than that.C© 1999 Academic Press

Il est souvent dit qu’Euclide n’avait pas de mot pour “rayon,” et qu’`a sa place il se servait de ladescription “la ligne trac´eea partir du centre.” Nous examinons ici la pratique linguistique d’Euclide,Archimede, et Apollonius, pour montrer que celle-ci est plus subtile que cela.C© 1999 Academic Press

MSC 1991 subject classification: 01A20.Key Words: Euclid;Elements; Data; circle; radius; ruler and compass.

In this note we propose that the Greek noundiastemain the dative form ,the only form found in theElements, should be understood as a special technical term inEuclid’s geometry. Although “the radius of a circle” is regularly called “the line from thecenter,” , he always usesdiastemawhen he is having a circle described;the word undoubtedly does service for “radius,” and this is the only use of this word in theElements.1 The first such instance is in Postulate 3:

[and (let it be postulated) to have a circle described with any center and radius]. [2, 1 : 5]

In most discussions of the postulates it is claimed that Euclidean constructions are basedon straightedge and compass.2 It is often said that postulates 1 and 2 (“let it be postulatedto produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight line”) assert that a straightedgemay be used to draw a line between two points or to extend a given line, while Postulate 3says that one can use a compass to describe a circle centered at any given point with anygiven radius. But if that is true, how can it be that the words for straightedge ( ) andcompass ( ) do not occur at all in theElementsnor, for that matter, in what hasbeen transmitted from Archimedes and Apollonius?

1 A complete list of the 30 places where it occurs is: Postulate 3, I 1 (twice), 2 (twice), 3, 12, 22 (twice); II 14;III 17, 25, 33 (three times); IV 1, 4 (twice), 5 (twice), 8 (twice), 9, 10, 13 (twice), 14, 15; X1 1; XII 17.

2 Vitrac [3, 1 : 171-2] is an exception to this, expressing deep reservations about the standard view.361

0315-0860/99 $30.00Copyright C© 1999 by Academic Press

All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

Page 2: Did Euclid's Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius?

362 FOWLER AND TAISBAK HMAT 26

A PLATONIC ATTITUDE

Euclid and his followers may have understood these postulates in a Platonic way, aninterpretation founded, among other things, on what can be learned from Euclid’sData: thestage on which mathematics is played out is the Realm of Intelligence. When Euclid wrotein Postulate 1:

˙[Let it be demanded that a straight line be drawn from any point to any point] [2, 1 : 4],

his audience may have understood this it as “Whenever there are two points, there is also astraight line joining them,” and we are permitted to behave accordingly, that is, to conceive apicture of that line. To exhibit it in practice, we would of course need a ruler, but that wouldbe to work in another world than that of the Realm of Intelligence. When Euclid wrote inPostulate 3, “and (let it be postulated) that a circle can be described with any center andradius,” his readers may also have understood this as “and whenever there are a point andan interval (between two given points, an ‘opening’), there is also a circle having the pointfor center and the interval for radius,” and we can also conceive that circle, but to draw it inthe picture would of course require a compass, and that also would be to leave the Realmof Intelligence.

THE HELPING HAND

It may be appropriate here to introduce “The Helping Hand,” a well-known factotumin Greek geometry who takes care that lines are drawn, circles are described, points aretaken, perpendiculars are dropped, etc. The perfect imperative passive is its verbal mask:“Let a circle have been described ( ) with center A and radius AB.” No one whohas studied theElementsin Greek will have missed it, and never do we find any of thecommands or exhortations so familiar from our own classrooms: “Draw the median fromvertex A,” “If we cut the circle by that secant line,” “Let us add those squares together.” TheHelping Hand is always there first to see that things are done and to keep the operations freefrom contamination by our mortal fingers. However there is no magic involved: the HelpingHand can do only such work as is warranted by postulates or propositions. Thus, it canlet circles be described by Postulate 3; it can let equilateral triangles be designed on givenline segments by Proposition I.1; angles can be bisected thanks to I.10; but it cannot trisectan angle for you. Its main effect and interest is to keep us mortals out of the play. Greekgeometry is not about what we can do, but about what can be done. Plato was familiar withThe Helping Hand when (in theRepublicVI 527 a6 ff.) he characterized mathematicians:“Their language is most ludicrous, though they cannot help it, for they speak as if they weredoing something and as if all their words were directed towards action. For all their talk isof squaring and applying and adding and the like...” [6, 2 : 171].

HEATH’S NOTE ON POSTULATE 3

In his influential note on Postulate 3, Sir Thomas Heath asserted that “This word, meaning distance, ... was the regular word used for describing a circle with

a certain radius.... The Greeks had no word corresponding to radius: if they had to ex-press it, they said “(straight lines) drawn from the center” [4, 1 : 199]. He certainly hada point:diastema, or rather its dative formdiastemati is without exception the one word

Page 3: Did Euclid's Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius?

HMAT 26 RADII OF EUCLID’S CIRCLES 363

used when Euclid is having a circle described—but Heath may not have appreciated whythe Greeks used two different expressions for radius. TheData presents many exampleswith the two expressions occurring side by side, e.g., Proposition 31: “... with center Aand radius ( ) AD let the circle EDZ have been described; so the circle EDZis given in position, because its center A is given in position and the line from the center( ) AD is given in magnitude” [2, 6 : 52.22–25].

We have concentrated on theElements, but a search of the remaining works of Euclid andof Archimedes using theThesaurus Linguae Graecae[9] and a skimming of Apollonius’sConicspoints to the same situation, which can be characterized as follows: whenever acircle is to be described (that is, whenever a form of the verb is around) with acertain interval as radius, the word used isdiastemati, whereas if a circle is assumed to bethere at the outset, or has already been described, its radius is referred to asthe line from thecenter.

SO IS THERE A COMPASS AFTER ALL?

The double vocabulary for radius gave us the idea of the use ofdiastema, that if it is notthe actual term for compass that we miss in the texts, then it might at least have very muchto do with that tool. The word means “standing apart” (from+ ), “separation,”the “opening” (for example of a bottle), and it might well carry the idea of the ‘stride’ orangle of a pair of compasses. So when Euclid allows The Helping Hand to describe a circlewith any center and anydiastema, he may mean “with a given opening of the compass.”This interpretation would explain why the word occurs only when a circle is needed and isabout to be described, and why it is found only in the instrumental dative, “by means of thisseparation of the legs of the compass”—the said “separation” being given by the endpointsof the given line—whereas the locution “the line from the center” is used in contexts wherethe circle is already there.

DISTANCE AND DIMENSION

As Heath commented, the word generally means “distance” and his examples fromAristotle can be supplemented by the passage he quoted [4 : 1, 190] from Proclus as acomment onElementsI, Definition 23 about parallel lines: Proclus [7, 176.6–17; 8, 138]attributed to Posidonius a definition of parallels which implies equal perpendiculars, that is,a constant difference,diastema, between the lines. In space, the word denotes “dimension,”for example when Aristotle discussed “place,”topos, in Physics209a5: “A ‘place’ has threediastemata, length, breadth, and depth” [1, 1 : 282–283]. But never do we find these usagesin Greek geometry.

CONCLUSION

We may conclude that in Greek geometry, whenever a circle is to be described,di-astemaalways means the “opening of a (notional) compass,” that is, its radius conceivedas a separation. In other contexts it means “distance,” though geometrically, as a line, andnever numerically. In hisDictionnaire historique de la terminologie geometrique des grecs,Mugler gave several examples from Greek mathematical works which confirm our thesis;nevertheless he wrote: “La terme est ainsi synonyme de ”[5, 1 : 136]. We have argued that the terms were not synonyms, but were alternative

Page 4: Did Euclid's Circles Have Two Kinds of Radius?

364 FOWLER AND TAISBAK HMAT 26

expressions for “radius” according as the circle was to be created (needing a tool) or wasthere already with its diameters and “lines from the center to the periphery.”

REFERENCES

1. Aristotle,The Physics, ed. and trans. Philip H. Wicksteed, Francis M. Cornford, 2 vols., Loeb Classical Library228, 255, London: Heinemann/Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1969–1970.

2. Euclid,Opera, ed. Johan L. Heiberg and Heinrich Menge, 9 vols., Leipzig: Teubner, 1883–1916; reprint ed.of vols. 1–5 (theElements): Euclid,Elementa, ed. Evangelos S. Stamatis, 5 vols. in 6 parts, Leipzig: Teubner,1969–1977.

3. Euclid,Les Elements, traduction et commentaires par Bernard Vitrac, 4 vols., Paris: Presses Universitaires deFrance, 1990 ff.

4. Thomas L. Heath,The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 2nd. ed., 3 vols., Cambridge, UK: CambridgeUniv. Press, 1926. [Based on [2]]

5. Charles Mugler,Dictionnaire historique de la terminologie geometrique des grecs, 2 vols., Paris: Klincksieck,1958.

6. Plato,The Republic, ed. and trans. Paul Shorey, 2 vols., Loeb Classical Library 237, 276, London: Heine-mann/Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1969–1970.

7. Proclus,In Primum Euclidis Elementorum Librum Commentarii, ed. Gottfried Friedlein, Leipzig: Teubner,1873.

8. Proclus,A Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements, trans. Glenn R. Morrow. With a new forewordby Ian Mueller, Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press, 1970.

9. Thesaurus Linguae Graecae, CD-ROM #D and (yet unpublished) #E. [TheThesaurus Linguae Graecae(TLG) is an electronic data bank of ancient Greek literature from Homer (8th century B.C.) to 600 A.D. withhistoriographical, lexicographical, and scholiastic texts from the period between 600 and 1453 A.D., locatedat the University of California, Irvine <http://www.tlg.uci.edu/∼tlg/>]