ethington et al placing the past

Upload: bosnabosna

Post on 07-Aug-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    1/66

    Rethinking History

    Volume 11, Number 4, December 2007

    Contents

    In This Issue463   David Harlan

    Article465 Placing the Past: ‘Groundwork’ for a Spatial Theory of History 

    Philip J. Ethington

    Commentaries495 Theory, Experience, and the Motion of History 

    Thomas Bender 

    501 Commentary on ‘Placing the Past: ‘‘Groundwork’’ for a Spatial

    Theory of History’

    David Carr 

    507 Boundary, Place, and Event in the Spatiality of History 

    Edward S. Casey 

    513 The Limits to Emplacement: A Reply to Philip Ethington

    Edward Dimendberg 

    517 Presenting and/or Re-Presenting the Past

     Alun Munslow 

    Reply525   Philip J. Ethington

    Forum: Robert Rosenstone,  History on Film/Film

    on History 531 Rosenstone on Film, Rosenstone on History: An African Perspective

    Vivian Bickford-Smith

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    2/66

    547 The Balcony of History 

    Robert Burgoyne

    555 Back to the Future, Ahead to the Past. Film and History: A StatusQuaestionis

    Leen Engelen

    565 Film and History: Robert A. Rosenstone and History on

    Film/Film on History 

     Alun Munslow 

    577 Critical Approaches to the History Film—A Field in Search of a

    Methodology Guy Westwell 

    Reply589 A Historian in Spite of Myself 

    Robert A. Rosenstone

    Forum: Alison Landsberg,  Prosthetic Memory:

    The Transformation of American Remembrancein the Age of Mass Culture597 Which Prosthetic? Mass Media, Narrative, Empathy, and

    Progressive Politics

     James Berger 

    613 Why Should Historians Write about the Nature of History (Rather

    Than Just Do it)?

     Alun Munslow 

    Response627   Alison Landsberg 

    Notes on Contributors631

    Index of Volume 11, 2007635

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    3/66

    ARTICLE

    Placing the Past: ‘Groundwork’ fora Spatial Theory of History

    Philip J. Ethington

    This essay presents an argument that the past is the set of all places made by 

    human action. The past cannot exist in time: only in space. Histories

    representing the past represent the places ( topoi) of human action. Knowledge

    of the past, therefore, is literally cartographic: a mapping of the places of 

    history indexed to the coordinates of spacetime. The author’s reply to published 

    commentary emphasizes the multi-perspectival framework of his theory and 

    the non-narrative potential of visual representation of the past.

    Keywords: Historical Theory; Mapping; Past; Place; Space; Time

    Précis

    All human action takes and  makes place. The past is the set of places made

    by human action. History is a map of these places.

    Introduction

    The past cannot exist ‘in’ time, because time cannot be any sort of frame

    within which anything can exist. By western definitions, time is something

    other  than space, and yet it is incessantly portrayed as something spatial: as

    a line, a frame, a background, a landscape, and as having orientation. In

    common usage, the past is behind us and the future is ahead. We speak of the distant past and the gulf of time that separates us from the ancients.

    These spatial metaphors for time are ubiquitous because they are grounded

    metaphors, arising from the spatial experience of time. In nature, time—by 

    Rethinking History Vol. 11, No. 4, December 2007, pp. 465 – 493

    ISSN 1364-2529 (print)/ISSN 1470-1154 (online)  ª  2007 Taylor & FrancisDOI: 10.1080/13642520701645487

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    4/66

    itself —has no being whatsoever. It is a mere measurement of spatial

    motion. But human, or lived  time is another matter. Experiential, memorial

    time is very real because it takes place. The past cannot exist in time: only  in

    space. Histories representing the past represent the places (topoi) of humanaction. History is not an account of ‘change over time,’ as the cliché goes,

    but rather, change through space. Knowledge of the past, therefore, is

    literally cartographic: a mapping of the places of history indexed to the

    coordinates of spacetime.

    If historical knowledge can mean anything that is distinct from other

    forms of knowledge, it must mean something about the temporal

    dimension of human experience in the world. What precisely is this

    temporal dimension? The experience of memory, common sense, and

    material evidence all around us strongly indicates that the past did  exist.What can we add, other than rendering the verb ‘to be’ in its past tense? It

    is circular to say, ‘the past was.’ What is the signified of ‘the past ,’ and does

    it have more than a semiotic existence?

    Historians have extensively addressed the question, ‘what is history?’ and

    how best to study the past. This essay begins with a far simpler question:

    what is the past, that we could seek to know or represent it in any way? That

    question depends unavoidably on a larger question: what is time? The

    process of answering these questions leads to a robust account of experience, as action inscribing the places of the past in spacetime. It also

    leads to a reconception of historical interpretation as the act of reading

    places, or  topoi.

    This essay attempts to make a contribution to current discussions about

    historical knowledge and even to knowledge in general. I advocate a new 

    materialism that incorporates, in good faith, two generations of 

    postpositivist, poststructural, postmodern, and postcolonial critique, and

     yet moves beyond these negations into a practice that can, in principle,

    achieve cumulative knowledge through intercultural dialogue on thecourses and meanings of the global past. Emplacing historical knowledge

    entails a radical rethinking of many basic terms that have become nebulous

    through shorthand use and critical neglect.

    Placing the past will also help historians to navigate the most recent

    ‘turn’ in the human sciences, the ‘spatial turn,’ as instigated by such

    thinkers as Henri Lefebvre, Michel Foucault, Yi-Fu Tuan, David Harvey,

    Edward Soja, and Edward Casey. Bookshelves groan under the weight of 

    recent discussions of place and space among geographers, anthropologists,and sociologists (Agnew & Duncan 1989; Feld & Basso 1996; Gieryn 2000;

    Low & Laurence-Zúñiga 2003; Cresswell 2004; Hubbard   et al . 2004).

    Amazingly, in the face of all this, almost nothing has been written in the last

    466   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    5/66

    three generations by historians directly on the concept of time. I have come

    to realize that historians cannot merely borrow new ideas about place and

    space without first conducting a searching examination of their own

    discipline’s home dimension of  temporality . Just beginning this necessary and long-overdue task may lead to some exciting new possibilities for

    historical knowledge that can overcome the fragmentations of perspectival

    contingency.

    Before the spatial turn even joined the list of ‘turns’ in the late 1980s,

    philosophers, critical theorists, intellectual historians, and others had

    developed a very advanced debate about the possibilities of producing

    knowledge of society. This was not  a debate between some naive believers in

    objective, scientistic value-neutral knowledge on one hand, and relativistic

    poststructuralists, on the other, as in Peter Novick’s (1988) misleadingaccount (Kloppenberg 1989). Instead, it has been a debate among those

    who all  agree   that we are in a post-foundational age, aware that linguistic

    construction, cultural difference, and historical contingency have elimi-

    nated the possibility of appealing to timeless, underlying truths, impartial

    epistemological methods, and the positive accumulation of uncontested

    knowledge.

    Concerned primarily with the possibilities of knowing the past, I shall

    build my case by remapping the past of knowing. My starting point is therise of the pragmatic-hermeneutic tradition inaugurated by Wilhelm

    Dilthey in Germany and William James in the United States, in the closing

    decades of the 19th century. In that tradition, knowledge of the past lost its

    atemporal universality and the foundations of universal truth began to

    crumble. In temporality and historicity, the contingency of knowledge

    became inescapable. The linguistic turn further separated knowing from the

    past by adding the semiotic critique of representation to those of historicity 

    and contingency. These traditions branched into several intellectual

    pathways. Dilthey’s historicism was recast by Heidegger, who radicalizedHusserl’s phenomenology into a temporalization of human being, and then

    by Derrida, who added semiotics to produce a radical deconstruction of 

    knowledge. James’ and John Dewey’s closely related pragmatism branched

    into reconstructive and radically skeptical positions on the possibilities

    of knowledge, represented by Jürgen Habermas and Richard Rorty,

    respectively.

    I shall argue that a cornerstone of the pragmatic tradition: temporality  as

    construed by fin-de-siècle hermeneutics—is in need of reconstruction now that the spatial  turn has been added to the linguistic  and  cultural  turns. My 

    interrogation of ‘time’ will lead back into space and place, through

    historical regions yet unexplored by the current state of the spatial turn.

    Rethinking History    467

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    6/66

    From Timeless Historians to an Account of Time

    If anything is obvious about the practice of historical research and writing,

    it is that ‘time’ is the discipline’s most defining feature. For historians, thequestion ‘what is time?’ is so basic and essential to our craft that it should

    be a cause for wonder that historians have evaded it almost completely and

    for so long. History has been as active as any other discipline in probing its

    most profound issues of theory and method. The major essayists on the

    historian’s craft, from Carl Becker ([1931] 1966) and Marc Bloch (1953) to

    E. H. Carr (1961), Fernand Braudel (1980), Siegfried Kracauer (1969),

    David Hackett Fischer (1970), David Lowenthal (1985), Joan Wallach Scott

    (1988), Pierre Nora (1996), Joyce Appleby, Lynn Hunt, and Margaret Jacob

    (1994), Alun Munslow (2000), and most recently, John Lewis Gaddis(2002), show us the necessary limits and also the open possibilities for

    interpreting and representing the past. I can neither summarize these

    important works, nor improve on them. Rather, I wish to show that by 

    exposing the ontologic status of time, the questions that all of these works

    address will take on a new light.

    Fernand Braudel’s influential scheme of three time scales went farther

    than most attempts by historians to define the time of the past. In  The

     Mediterranean   and elsewhere, Braudel argued that human history iscomposed of three types of time, each ‘one aspect of the whole.’ In the

    conclusion to  The Mediterranean, he wrote of 

    an attempt to write a new kind of history, total history, written in threedifferent registers, on three different levels, perhaps best described asthree different conceptions of time, the writer’s aim being to bringtogether in all their multiplicity the different measures of time past, toacquaint the reader with their coexistence, their conflicts and contra-dictions, and the richness of experience they hold. (Braudel 1972, II,

    p. 1238)

    The first of these three Braudelian conceptions is the  Longue durée: ‘a

    history whose passage is almost imperceptible,1 that of man in his

    relationship to the environment, a history in which all change is slow,

    a history of constant repetition, ever-recurring cycles.’ The second type of 

    time is also a long time span, but less daunting. This conjunctural history:

    ‘histoire conjuncturelle,’ as Braudel came to call it, is a time of ‘slow but

    perceptible rhythms . . . one could call it social history, the history of groups and groupings’ (1972, I, p. 20, italics in original). The third type, a

    ‘histoire événémentielle,’ deals with the ‘short time span, proportionate to

    individuals, to daily life, to our illusions, to our hasty awareness—above

    468   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    7/66

    all the time of the chronicle and the journalist . . .’ (1980, p. 28). ‘But the

    worst of it,’ Braudel added,

    is that there are not merely two or three measures of time, there aredozens, each of them attached to a particular history. Only the sum of these measures, brought together by the human sciences (turnedretrospectively to account on the historian’s behalf) can give us that totalhistory whose image it is so difficult to reconstitute in its entirety. (1972,II, p. 1238)

    Braudel’s brilliant pluralization of time scales emerged from his

    attempt to see the history of a place, which his training under Lucien

    Febvre had taught him to see geographically and led to his ‘homage to those

    timeless realities whose images recur throughout the whole book’ (1972, II,p. 1239).

    The thesis that the time of the past must have multiple scales and

    simultaneous, yet inharmonious, rhythms, was also developed by the art

    historians Henri Focillon ([1934] 1992) and George Kubler (1962), and

    further elaborated by Siegfried Kracauer (1969). Neither Braudel nor

    Kracauer, however, went further than to subdivide ‘time’ into multiple

    registers. Left whole as a single timeline, stratified into three or twelve layers

    by Braudel’s ‘depth metaphor’ (Megill 1989) or separated into differentrhythms, time has remained unquestionably necessary as a frame or

    background for historians to situate ‘the past.’

    The most recent, and most suggestive, case of portraying the past as a

    background is John Lewis Gaddis’ recent Oxford lectures (2002),

    comparing the past to a landscape, as a   simile   or   analogy . Gaddis

    convincingly shows that the production of historical knowledge is very 

    much ‘like’ that of a cartographer: the need to operate at different scales, to

    contextualize, to generalize and particularize simultaneously, to skip time

    periods and to portray non-adjacent places. But, when Gaddis freely admitsthat he is only  offering a simile, he begs the question of what the object of 

    that simile is: if the past is only   like  a landscape, then what   is   it?

    To be sure, historians have studied the social and intellectual history of 

    time as perceived, conceived, and lived by past societies (Kern 1983; Pocock 

    1989; Haraven 1991; Landes 2000), but amazingly, even these historians

    have left the entire question of   time   as such—the time that makes it

    meaningful for  them  to say anything at all about ‘the past’—unexamined.

    To historicize anything, including time, requires some assumptions aboutthe nature of time to the historicizing historian. The mother of all

    assumptions has been that ‘time’ is a static background, transcendent in its

    universality. For all their vast differences, the philosophers Kant, Husserl

    Rethinking History    469

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    8/66

    and Heidegger took the stand that time is transcendent a priori (Dostal

    1993), so historians can hardly be blamed for doing so.

    Most commonly, historians simply confuse time with chronology and

    chronometry—the ‘time’ of calendars and clocks. No one seriously debateswhether the 18th century came before the 20th, nor that Denis Diderot

    lived before Jean-Paul Sartre, so this framework called ‘time’ remains

    reassuringly stable, unproblematic, and consensual. But this convenient

    evasion tells us nothing about what time actually is, and without knowing

    that, we cannot ask: what is the past, or history, to time? An excellent

    starting point is Paul Ricoeur’s (1984 – 1988) distinction between cosmic  or

    natural   time—that which seems to occur throughout the universe,

    independent of humanity; and   human   or   lived   time: time as conceived,

    perceived, and experienced by individuals and their societies, as forexample in the studies of ‘collective memory’ (Halbwachs 1992; Nora 1996;

    Confino 1997; Klein 2000; Kansteiner 2002). As my argument proceeds, I

    hope to make it clear that these two types of time actually converge by 

    intersecting in places (topoi).

    Natural Time

    To physicists, cosmic or natural time is only part of relativistic ‘spacetime,’a large-scale structure postulated by Hermann Minkowski and Albert

    Einstein. Since humans do not yet travel at speeds nearing that of light,

    historians can be forgiven for not worrying too much about the behavior of 

    time under conditions other than the plodding Newtonian rotations and

    orbits of the Earth, which tick off the days and years. Even less do they 

    need, on a daily basis, to ponder the bizarre issues of space and time at the

    quantum level. The commonplace lesson drawn from relativity theory is

    that there is no privileged perspective or frame for ‘time,’ and therefore,

    that time cannot be absolute. The speed of light provides the only parameter. Quantum mechanics holds that a particle can be in two different

    locations at the same time, a possibility that may have no relevance to

    human affairs, but one which further confounds reassuring notions of some

    standard background called ‘time’ against which history happens (Sklar

    1974).

    Time in nature ‘is no more than an arbitrary parameter that is used to

    describe dynamics, or the mechanics of motion.’ This arbitrary parameter

    has proven very difficult to standardize precisely. The basic unit used by scientists and engineers to describe these motions and to coordinate the

    increasingly complex technology of society is the   second , fixed in 1956

    under the Système Internationale des Unités (SI) as ‘1/31,556,925.9747th of 

    470   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    9/66

    the orbital period of the Earth about the Sun.’ But alas, the Earth’s orbital

    period actually fluctuates slightly, so that  standard was replaced in 1968 by 

    Resolution #1 of the 13th Conférence Générale des Poids et Mesures

    (CGPM), to be, rather, ‘9,192,631,770 cycles of the ground-state hyperfinesplitting of the unperturbed cesium atom’ (Diddams  et al . 2004, p. 1318).

    Paired with the basic unit of time is the basic unit of space, the SI meter,

    today defined as ‘the path length traveled by light in a vacuum during the

    time interval of 1/299,792,458 of a second’ (Diddams et al . 2004, p. 1318).2

    The original meter was born in the French Revolution as a neat subdivision

    of the circumference of the Earth (to supplant earlier measures such as the

    ‘hand’ and the ‘foot’). Humans will calibrate motion with such arbitrary 

    units until the end of the world, never measuring time itself.

    We never  observe time isolated by itself in nature; only motion and thetraces of motions. Those traces are the innumerably various inscriptions by 

    natural events and by purposive beings onto their environments. Because

    collective action is coordinated by cyclical repetitive motions in nature, as

    in the Earth’s solar orbit or the Moon’s terrestrial orbit, it should be no

    surprise that these motions and their periodicity became central to human

    consciousness of time. Classified into units that vary widely by varying

    conceptions of time (linear, circular, discontinuous, etc.), ‘time’ is nothing

    in itself , but rather a culturally specific reading of the dynamicenvironment.

    That said, natural scientists and philosophers of science have come to

    agree that in the physical universe, ‘time’ (enclosed in quotes because what

    follows is actually about the energies and motions of things, and not about

    time as something independent) is   asymmetrical : it only ‘flows’ in one

    direction, and cannot be run backward as a movie can (Feynman 1965;

    Savitt 1990). Hans Reichenbach (1956) demonstrated why this is so. The

    argument is simply that thermodynamic processes have an infinitely higher

    probability of running from low to high states of entropy (from organizedto disorganized) than from high to low states of entropy. Sugar cubes

    dissolve into hot coffee, but sugar in solution with coffee is extremely 

    unlikely to form itself into a cube and rise to the surface. Hence, ‘the

    direction in which most thermodynamical processes in isolated processes

    occur is the direction of positive time’ (Reichenbach 1956, p. 127). Here

    again, however, time is defined as the interval between one entropic state

    and another. It is the behavior of matter and energy that is observed, not

    that of time.It is easy to see, from the ‘asymmetry of time,’ that time travel is

    impossible because there is no time   in which  to travel. Understanding the

    being of the past actually depends on an understanding of why this is so.

    Rethinking History    471

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    10/66

    The spatial field of human experience is an immense, aggregate complex of 

    subatomic and molecular motion. To go ‘back in time’ cannot mean

    anything less than forcing all of the particles in our bodies and the world

    around us into the negative performance of all the motions that they had just completed. This necessarily includes the molecules of the entire planet,

    because adjacent energies cannot be separated. No individual could break 

    free of the network of energy and matter to visit an earlier state of that

    network. Either the entire planet goes backward, or nobody does. And even

    if we could run the entire planet backward, it wouldn’t make a difference to

    anyone, because no one would remember the difference. Memories—stored

    in the neurobiological complex of the brain—would be   unmade   as time

    went backwards, and   remade   as time went forward again. A different

    ‘present’ might result, but no one would be able to remember the original‘present.’ This kind of time travel means that the entire world must always

    experience each ‘time’ for the first time. Natural or cosmic ‘time’ cannot be

    a container or background of any spatial sort, in which to travel. Time   is

    travel.

    All matter is in motion, so all space is dynamic. The only sensible term

    for this environment is ‘spacetime,’ which I shall use from this point on.

    Lived Time

    What then of human, or experienced, time? It may be clear that time is

    illusory in nature, but isn’t our experience of it in daily life, our feeling of it

    passing, our conviction of it as memory, and our collective knowledge of it

    as history, real? Let us now enquire whether there can be a substance to this

    time, and if so, is it possible to speak of a ‘past’ as something real enough

    that we can obtain knowledge of it?

    Despite historians’ indifference, a mountain of philosophical and

    scholarly texts since antiquity are devoted to unraveling the mystery of human and natural time (Grünbaum 1963; Sherover 1975; Carr 1986;

    Flood & Lockwood 1986). Models of time—as linear, circular, eternal,

    fragmentary, discontinuous—are as diverse as the cultures of the globe

    (Aguessy  et al . 1977; Fraser 1981). Limitations of space require me to enter

    this massive background through a single regional tradition: the Euro-

    American beginning of the 20th century.

    In two very different ways, the philosophers J. Allen McTaggart and

    Henri Bergson cast damning doubt on the ‘reality’ of the linear, or spatial,model of time. McTaggart’s influential 1908 essay, ‘The Unreality of Time,’

    established the convention of distinguishing between two very different

    kinds of temporal ‘series.’ In the ‘A series,’ events occur in moments that

    472   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    11/66

    run from the future to the present and then into the past. In the ‘B series,’

    events are either ‘earlier’ or ‘later.’ Considering ‘pastness,’ ‘presentness,’

    and ‘futurity’ to be either relations among or qualities of events, McTaggart

    concluded that the A series is contradictory, because past, present, andfuture are ‘incompatible determinations,’ and yet ‘every event has them all’

    in that each event somehow changes its state (1908, p. 468). The A series

    also clashes with the B series. The event of the death of William Shakespeare

    (1616) occurred before the event of the death of Queen Anne (1714), and

    remains, always, 98 years prior to the latter. Thus, these events must remain

    fixed and yet they are asked to move or change states in the A series from

    being future, to present, to past—to shift down the line, as it were, to make

    room for new events. From this, McTaggart reasoned that time cannot be

    part of reality.But McTaggart neatly dispatched from ‘reality’ only the   abstract   time

    that corresponds to another abstraction—space. Since this time is only read

    from planetary motion with everyday clocks, it cannot function like

    something spatial in itself, much less something with the capacity to ‘move,’

    as when time ‘passes.’ It is not a background or ground of any kind, just the

    interval point-observations of bodies in motion. But neither consciousness

    nor social action is possible without a real sense of time. That kind of time

    was theorized vividly by Henri Bergson.Bergson cut through McTaggart’s Gordian Knot with his famous

    distinction between linear time sequences and ‘duration’ (durée). In a series

    of essays, books, and his immensely popular lectures at the Collège de

    France, Bergson argued that ‘real time’ is essentially a human phenomenon,

    since two ‘moments’ can only meaningfully constitute a temporal relation

    via memory ([1890], [1896], [1907], [1922]). ‘To tell the truth, it is

    impossible to distinguish between the duration, however short it may be,

    that separates two instants and a memory that connects them, because

    duration is essentially a continuation of what no longer exists into whatdoes exist. This is real time, perceived and lived’ ([1922] 2002, p. 208).3 In

    nature then, time in isolation quite definitely cannot exist, but in human

    consciousness it must. We are left with the result that human, subjective,

    psycho-socially constructed ‘time’ is real, while natural, objectively 

    measured ‘time’ is an illusion. Given the typical prioritization of the

    physical over the imaginary, this irony deserves further attention. Indeed,

    since humans are part of nature, the irony may indicate a conceptual flaw 

    in the distinction between human and natural time. I shall return to thispossibility later.

    Certainly, if human experience is real, then the temporality of that

    experience is no less real. But Bergson’s distinction between ‘real’ time and

    Rethinking History    473

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    12/66

    the abstraction of measured time, and his dismissal of the latter’s ‘spatial’

    character, is fundamentally flawed and requires a historical critique.

    The Time of Metaphoric Space

    Bergson’s conception of ‘real time’ as  duration  thematized ‘the present’ as

    the genuine field of human temporality. In this project he had good

    company. United as ‘philosophers of life,’ Wilhelm Dilthey, William James,

    and Henri Bergson successfully raised  presentness   in streams of time as a

    critical feature of consciousness. The temporality of consciousness, in turn,

    was a key feature of the pragmatic-hermeneutic project to establish the

    contingency of knowledge within historic contexts. So far, so good. But I

    want to reinforce these intellectual achievements by exposing the weak metaphoric spatiality deployed by the founding generation of the

    hermeneutic and pragmatic traditions.

    William James, whose enthusiasm for Bergson is well known,

    independently developed the idea of ‘stream of consciousness’ to

    characterize the indivisibility of lived time. Already in his   Principles of 

    Psychology  ([1890] 1983) he concluded his chapter on the ‘Perception of 

    Time’

    by saying that we are constantly conscious of a certain duration—thespecious present—varying in length from a few seconds to probably notmore than a minute, and that this duration (with its content perceivedas having one part earlier and the other part later) is the originalintuition of time. Longer times are conceived by adding, shorter ones by dividing, portions of this vaguely bounded unit, and are habitually thought by us symbolically. ([1890] 1983, p. 603)

    James’ influential account apprehends time in its ‘flow’: the present is

    specious because as soon as we can think of it, it is past, and the duration of this passage has no fixed measure. As in Bergson’s   durée, the specious

    present seems to refute the very logic of measured time, which represents

    moments as points.

    ‘The representations by which we possess the past and the future are

    there only for us as we live in the present,’ writes Wilhelm Dilthey in his

    uncompleted Critique of Historical Reason. ‘The present is always there, and

    nothing is there except what emerges in it.’ ‘Nothing’ is a strong claim.

    How literally can we take it? If the past is part of reality, then according toDilthey, it must exist only ‘in’ the present. ‘The present,’ continues Dilthey,

    ‘is the fullness of a moment of time being filled with reality; it is reality as

    distinct from memory or representations of the future as found in wishes,

    474   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    13/66

    expectations, hopes, fears, and strivings’ (2002, p. 215).  Presenting  the past

    is a cornerstone of Dilthey’s philosophy of history because his goal was to

    situate both the historical subject and the historian, a goal that had deep

    epistemological implications.‘Action everywhere presupposes the understanding of other persons,’

    Dilthey explains, ‘so at the threshold of the human sciences we encounter a

    problem specific to them alone and quite distinct from all conceptual

    knowledge of nature’ (2002, p. 235). Dilthey successfully enshrined

    ‘interpretation’ as the core method of the human sciences and therewith

    erected a formidable barrier between the human and natural sciences. He

    also made it clear that an endless circle would bedevil the interpreter, whose

    own interpretive ‘position’ (a historically situated cultural perspective)

    would also be implicated in the interpretation of others, and vice versa.Thus, Dilthey also founded ‘hermeneutics’ as a branch of philosophy 

    devoted to reflecting on the problems of interpretation, the goal of which is

    to reach intersubjective understanding (Verstehen). Further, Dilthey 

    thoroughly historicized the human sciences: ‘The decisive element in

    Dilthey’s inquiry,’ writes Martin Heidegger, ‘is not the theory of the

    sciences of history but the tendency to bring the reality of the historical into

    view and to make clear from this the manner and possibility of its

    interpretation’ ([1924] 1992, p. 17).But Dilthey’s clarity regarding historical temporality is mitigated by his

    lavish use of spatial metaphors, the irony of which requires serious

    attention. ‘The ship of our life is carried forward on a constantly moving

    stream, as it were, and the present is always wherever we enter these waves

    with whatever we suffer, remember, and hope, that is, whenever we live in

    the fullness of our reality’ (2002, p. 215). The lack of precision in this

    sentence was perhaps intentional; Dilthey’s ‘as it were’ flags the image as

    intended metaphor. But ‘wherever’ is conflated with ‘whenever.’ Through-

    out his direct examination of time, Dilthey never breaks free from a basicspatial metaphorization, which he never stops to examine. ‘When we look 

    back at the past, we are passive; it cannot be changed . . . . But in our attitude

    toward the future we are active and free . . . . thus the lived experience of 

    time determines the content of our lives in all directions’ (2002, p. 215).

    ‘Back,’ ‘toward,’ ‘directions.’ The ‘present,’ Dilthey writes, is ‘there.’ Where? 

    As a painter and physician whose literary creativity rivaled that of his

    novelist brother, William James’ richly visual language for time perception

    delivers a flood of metaphor: ‘The knowledge of some other part of thestream, past or future, near or remote, is always mixed in with our knowledge

    of the present ’ ([1890] 1983, p. 571, italics in original). ‘To think a thing

    past is to think it amongst the objects or in the direction of objects which at

    Rethinking History    475

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    14/66

    the present moment appear affected by this quality’ (p. 570). Without

    irony, James quotes the following: ‘Le moment ou je parle est dé jà  loin de

    moi’ (p. 573).4 By the end of his chapter on the ‘Perception of Time,’ James

    is swept away by his own spatial metaphors: ‘In short, the practically cognized present is no knife edge, but a saddle-back’ (p. 574). And finally:

    ‘The same space of time seems shorter as we grow older . . .’ (p. 588). Not

    surprisingly, James’ otherwise compelling chapter on ‘The Perception of 

    Space’ (pp. 776 – 912) has nothing to say about spatial metaphors, much

    less is it marked by temporal metaphors for space.5

    I contend that this metaphoric entanglement with space is filled with

    powerful clues as to the nature of time, and holds profound importance for

    the debate about historical knowledge of the past. In their enthusiastic

    embrace of temporality, the modernists of Dilthey’s generation failed toappreciate the implications of their own metaphors. Spatiality, presumably 

    an indispensable dimension of being, was left behind as these modernists

    entered the flow of time. Dilthey and James left spatiality in the

    unthematized condition of metaphor; while Bergson considered spatializa-

    tion a curse and left it in negation, banishing it from ‘real time.’ Building in

    part on Dilthey’s historical hermeneutics, Martin Heidegger further

    radicalized the implications of  Lebensphilosophie   by constituting human

    temporality as an ontological  question. He also surpassed his predecessors inthe metaphoric evasion of spatiality.

    Being and Time   (Heidegger [1927] 1962) is the limit case of the

    modernist prioritization of time over space. ‘Our provisional aim,’

    Heidegger writes in the Preface to  Being and Time, ‘is the Interpretation

    of  time as the possible horizon for any understanding whatsoever of Being’

    ([1927] 1962, p. 1, italics in original). But the temporality of Heidegger’s

    Dasein is, a priori, a transcendent dimension, as Dostal (1993) shows. Time

    to Heidegger is the mother of all assumptions. It simply is, and everything

    ‘whatsoever’ appears to consciousness against this ‘horizon.’ Heidegger’sopus, it turns out, helps us to confront time only in an oblique way,

    because   Dasein   can only know itself temporally. It is always already 

    temporal and always already being-there: ‘primordially’ ([1927] 1962, p.

    385) engaged with the everyday. Despite his profound conceptualization of 

    being-there, and the presentness of  Dasein, Heidegger is determined to keep

    the spatiality of that being secondary to its temporality. Heidegger

    purchased his achievement through a massive (and evasive) metaphoriza-

    tion of space: Dasein is ‘already alongside’ itself, ‘ahead-of-itself,’ or ‘thrownand falling’ ([1927] 1962, pp. 141, 375, 477, italics in original).

    Heidegger was not neglectful of space in   Being and Time. On the

    contrary, he aggressively pursued a project to temporalize it. In section 70

    he writes of ‘the function of temporality as the   foundation   for   Dasein’s

    476   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    15/66

    spatiality . . .’ ([1927] 1962, p. 421, emphasis added). But an older and wiser

    Heidegger admitted that his temporal existentialism had led him into a

    dead end. In his 1962 essay ‘Time and Being’ (what was originally, in 1927,

    supposed to be the title of the second volume of his  magnum opus), hewrites: ‘The attempt in   Being and Time, section 70, to derive human

    spatiality from temporality is untenable’ (Krell 1995, pp. 43 – 44; Casey 

    1997, pp. 243 – 284; Heidegger 2002, p. 23).

    I propose reading Heidegger backward: disregarding his unsustainably 

    transcendent temporality, literalizing his spatial metaphors, and imagining

    Dasein’s horizon as that of its given spatiality, against which time becomes

    meaningful. Spatiality is the missing keystone of the pragmatic-hermeneu-

    tic edifice, just as temporality is its elusive foundation.

    Etymologies Past and Present

    The unreflective spatial metaphorization of time by the modernists was a

    fateful mistake, but it can be easily explained. Spatial metaphors for time

    are ‘grounded metaphors’ in Lakoff and Johnson’s (1980, 1999)

    terminology. It is not accidental that we use them to talk about time,

    because our experience of time is movement in space. If metaphors form a

    bridge between language and experience, they also open a door to escapethe prisonhouse of language, enabling us to express more than that

    symbolic system can signify (Ricoeur 1981). Metaphor cuts two ways, then.

    Observed historically, it illuminates the intersection of language with

    experience. In communicative action, it transcends experience to enable the

    creative transformation of language in purposive projects.

    The metaphoric conflation of time and space is observable in the  Oxford 

    English Dictionary ’s historical etymology of ‘the present’ and ‘the past’ (Oxford 

    English Dictionary Online, accessed 2003). The OED’s entry for ‘present,  n.’

    provides the following account: ‘Anglo-Norman and Old French, MiddleFrench present  (French présent ) presence (early 13th cent. or earlier in Anglo-

    Norman), thing which or person who is present (c 1225 in Old French), (in

    grammar) present tense (c 1245), present time, period of time now occurring

    (a1278)’ (Oxford English Dictionary Online, accessed 2007). To be present and

    to   be in the   present originally held the same meaning. This conflation is

    evident today in the simple answer to a roll-call: ‘present!’

    We learn the same lesson from the etymology of ‘past.’ As the past

    participle of the verb ‘to pass,’ it gradually evolved a nominal form. Thespelling ‘passed’ was truncated into ‘past’ over the centuries by speakers and

    writers, observable between Chaucer’s ‘The day is short, and it is passed’

    (Franklin’s Tale, 1476) and Charlotte Brontë’s ‘It was past four o’clock, and

    the beclouded afternoon was tending to drear twilight’ ( Jane Eyre, 1847).

    Rethinking History    477

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    16/66

    In both of these examples, time is metaphorically represented as a spatial

    passing. The nominal form of ‘the past,’ expressing ‘a time that has gone by;

    a time, or all of the time, before the present,’ did not appear until about

    1500, but the same spelling continued to signify a strictly spatial passing, asin Shakespeare’s ‘My lord, the enemie is past the marsh’ (Richard III , 1596),

    and today’s ‘just past the next intersection’ (Oxford English Dictionary 

    Online, accessed 2003).

    This brief look at the past of ‘the past’ shows evolution from a verb

    signifying action and motion of bodies in space, to an adjective and adverb

    signifying time by metaphorizing space, to a noun referring to prior times.

    Withal, the temporal meaning of ‘the past’ contains a spatial understanding

    of phenomena in motion: that which had ‘passed’ the observer. ‘Time’

    begins to make sense again as a landscape, but only in a de-metaphorized,spatial sense. We do push off into the future with every move of our bodies,

    but that ‘future’ is nothing more than the next emplacement of the bodies

    of the world, leaving behind the places of the past (passed) with every new 

    configuration of presence. As the later Heidegger explained, even our most

    fundamental verb, to be, evolved from the verb  to dwell  (Heidegger [1951]

    1993).6

    The Social Choreography of Georg Simmel

    Georg Simmel was the   only   modernist in the hermeneutic revolution

    inaugurated by Dilthey to theorize spatiality as integral to the human

    sciences. His formulation is worth examining in detail because he

    developed a method of linking the metaphoric with the non-metaphoric

    senses of space. It provides us with a link to the historicism of Dilthey, and

    thereby a direct path toward the reconstruction of that tradition. It has also

    been completely ignored by the current discourse on spatiality.

    Spatiality as an analytic category finally came into its own in the 1960s and1970s, with the work of Gaston Bachelard [1958], Michel Foucault [1967],

    Henri Lefebvre (1974), and Yi-Fu Tuan (1977). Thanks primarily to the work 

    of Edward Soja (1989, 1996) and David Harvey (1989), a ‘spatial turn’ has

    occurred in many of the human sciences. So successful have Soja and Harvey 

    been in spreading the pathbreaking ideas of Lefebvre that it is no exaggeration

    to call the current discourse on spatiality ‘Lefebvrian’ (Elden 2001).

    Lefebvre’s Production de l’Espace (1974; tr. The Production of Space 1991)

    is justifiably admired as a deep well of insight, reworking many strands of western philosophy to interrogate the category of space from a variety of 

    angles. Lefebvre has contributed permanently to our conceptual tool set

    with his distinction—already widely cited in the human sciences—between

    478   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    17/66

    ‘spatial practice’ (the practical material work carried out spatially in any 

    given society), ‘representations of space’ (the ways that society represents its

    own spatiality), and ‘spaces of representation’ (the arts, architecture, and

    other environmental texts that society deploys in its self-representation).This triad is useful in itself, but Lefebvre encloses it within an unnecessarily 

    convoluted tangle of neo-Hegelian ‘moments,’ comprehending, in Edward

    Dimendberg’s (1998) succinct explication,

    existing social space as a concrete universal containing three terms(spatial practice, representations of space, and spaces of representation),three levels (perceived, conceived, lived), and three forms of space(absolute, historical, abstract) that particularize themselves with specificcontents at different time periods. (1998, p. 29)7

    The current Lefebvrian discourse, however, ignores the pioneering spatial

    thinking of Georg Simmel.8 Limitations of space force me to summarize my 

    much more extensive treatment of Simmel (Ethington 1997, 2005), but it is

    notoriously difficult to summarize Simmel’s thought in any case. Max 

    Weber, Siegfried Kracauer, and Talcott Parsons all abandoned the effort,

    leaving their manuscripts on Simmel unpublished (Frisby 1987, 1990, pp.

    xxvi, 2; Levine 1991). His own contemporaries ‘. . . clearly found it difficult

    to locate Simmel’s work within some readily recognized discipline andtradition’ (Frisby 1990, p. 2). Nevertheless, it is quite clear that his thought

    is a variation on  Lebensphilosophie, despite his failure to acknowledge his

    deep debt to Dilthey.9

    Integral to Simmel’s formal approach was his spatial understanding of 

    intersubjective social interaction. His distinctive treatment of social

    spatiality is evident in one of his best-known essays, ‘The Stranger’

    ([1908] 1971). Simmel constructs ‘the stranger’ as a social form: ‘a form of 

    being together,’ ‘a form of union based on interaction.’ Strangeness is

    ‘create[ed]’ by ‘factors of repulsion and distance’ working together (Simmel[1908] 1971, p. 144). Not mobility itself, but the ‘appearance of this

    mobility within a group occasions that synthesis of nearness and

    remoteness which constitutes the formal position of the stranger’ (p.

    145). Simmel expands this treatment of the near/far synthesis to claim that

    in the stranger he has identified a feature of ‘every human relationship’:

    In the case of the stranger, the union of closeness and remotenessinvolved in every human relationship is patterned in a way that may be

    succinctly formulated as follows: the distance within this relationindicates that one who is close by is remote, but his strangeness indicatesthat one who is remote is near. The state of being a stranger is of coursea completely positive relation; it is a specific form of interaction. (p. 143)

    Rethinking History    479

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    18/66

    Simmel makes space work in two distinct senses in this passage: as

    metaphor   for intersubjective intimacy and as non-metaphoric   geometric 

    space. ‘Closeness’ and ‘remoteness’ are at first unspecified, but after the

    colon, ‘close by’ and ‘near’ are meant geometrically, while ‘remote’ is meantintersubjectively.

    Simmel’s signal achievement is the fusion of metaphoric and geometric

    spatiality in a single conceptual framework, one that successfully resists

    hypostatizing or abstracting ‘space’ in the ways Lefebvre (1991, pp. 229 –

    292) complains of. Crucial to Simmelian space is the ineluctable quality of 

    the ‘boundary,’ a social form that is common to both consciousness and to

    society. Simmel also outlined, but did not fully flesh out, the idea that social

    interactions are spatial configurations for the same reasons that

    consciousness is organized (as he took from Kant) by a series of categoricalboundaries. ‘The boundary is not a spatial fact with sociological

    consequences, but a sociological fact that forms itself spatially’ (Simmel

    1997, p. 143). The boundary is perhaps the most suggestive aspect of 

    Simmelian spatiality, reflecting the indeterminate position of the subject:

    ‘By virtue of the fact that we have boundaries everywhere and always,’

    Simmel writes, ‘so accordingly we  are  boundaries’ (Simmel 1971, p. 353,

    italics in original).

    Simmel’s ‘boundary’ is both geometrically and metaphorically spatial. Itis the intersection of these two types of spatiality, a parallel to the

    pragmatists’ denial of the mind/body dualism. The spatiality of experience

    complements its temporality in ways that the pragmatic-hermeneutic

    tradition has not fully appreciated (in large part because Simmel’s sociology 

    was largely a-historic). Historians, ever indebted to Dilthey’s construction

    of the human sciences, have carried forward his incomplete account of 

    experience, which is historical but placeless. By emplacing experience,

    Simmel’s theoretically compatible handiwork repairs Diltheyan epistemol-

    ogy by accounting for experience   as form, with both geometric andmetaphoric spatiality.

    Placing the Critique of Space

    The world comes bedecked in places. It is a place-world to begin with.(Casey 1996, p. 43)

    Simmel’s insistence that all social forms are in a perpetual state of dynamism through sites of interaction; his location of those forms in the

    embodied self as intersection and boundary; and his refusal to reduce

    contingency and plurality to system and abstraction, well suit the spirit

    480   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    19/66

    of today’s post-foundational world. It is no accident that two of his

    students, Walter Benjamin and Sigfried Kracauer, have returned to

    prominence with such force (Frisby 1986; Schwartz 2001). Among many 

    other qualities, Simmel’s work makes visible the suppressed spatiality of Dilthey’s historicism. Simmel’s achievements, however, are hard to

    appreciate in part because most of what he calls ‘space’ is now 

    understood as place, and this distinction is of major importance in

    current debates.

    Two very different approaches to the space – place distinction will now 

    be explored: Henri Lefebvre’s neo-Marxian approach and Edward Casey’s

    much more radical phenomenological approach. While simplistic, it is not

    misleading to say that in the current discourse, ‘place’ is good and ‘space’ is

    bad. ‘Place is an organized world of meaning,’ Tuan writes (1977, p. 179).Places are experiential, memorial, emotive, subjective, even poetic

    (Bachelard [1958] 1964). Spaces are objective, abstract, measurable,

    ‘scientific’ and universal. Space in this framework is the alienating and

    exploitative handiwork of the capitalist bourgeoisie, bearing the same

    relation to place as exchange value does to use value in the Marxian account

    of commodities.

    Henri Lefebvre’s ‘history’ of the entire period from the Italian

    quattrocento  through the 20th century is one long rise of the bourgeoisieand its alienating gaze: ‘The outcome has been a brutal and authoritarian

    spatial practice, whether Haussmann’s or the later, codified versions of the

    Bauhaus or Le Corbusier; what is involved in all cases is the effective

    application of the analytic spirit in and through dispersion, division and

    segregation’ (1991, p. 308). Lefebvre’s broad brush smears the diverse work 

    of the Bauhaus (which in the hands of Walter Gropius was deeply social-

    democratic) by association with Hausmann’s destruction of Paris and Le

    Corbusier’s ill-conceived sterile spaces.

    Lefebvre’s thesis of panoptic and authoritarian implications of abstractspace have been echoed in the neo-Marxian writings of David Harvey, and

    by a wide range of postcolonial thinkers who trace the abstraction of space

    and time to European imperialism (Blaut 1993). The development of 

    precision clocks and reliable latitude and longitude measurements for

    navigation during the 16th and 17th centuries was conducted by imperial,

    authoritarian regimes, and by the cultures that invented the racial

    categories and generated the brutal boundaries of colonial exploitation.

    But the abstract grid of ‘space’ is ultimately a neutral frame, mereinstrumental  rationality, not to be confused with the  value  rationality of a

    particular instance of deploying it—to use Max Weber’s important

    distinction.

    Rethinking History    481

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    20/66

    Technically, flat maps of the globe are not panoptic but orthogonal:

    every point is seen from its own perpendicular, so they can be instruments

    of subaltern perspectives and multicultural dialogue as substantially as

    anything else. Besides, the grid of global spacetime has now becomeinstitutionalized among all cultures, so it is more important to understand

    its relation to place, and that task has been accomplished by a thinker

    whose intellectual history of the space/place split has now made Lefebvre’s

    ideas on abstract space seem obsolete.

    In The Fate of Place: A Philosophical History  (1997), Edward Casey shows

    that place long reigned as the ‘supreme term’ in western thought, but that

    ‘by the end of the eighteenth century, it vanished altogether from serious

    theoretical discourse in physics and philosophy,’ demoted during the rise of 

    modern science into mere   position. Modern natural and social scientificmethod relegates places to mere instances or points in space. In the

    Newtonian model infinite space is the foundation and frame that gives

    meaning to any given position. All local cases are but variant particularities

    to be combed for common patterns that are the golden nuggets extracted

    by scientific methods. But Casey convincingly dismantles this denigration

    of place by asking: ‘What if things are the other way around? What if the

    very idea of spaces is posterior to that of place? . . . . Could place be general

    and ‘‘space’’ particular?’ (1996, p. 17). Casey’s starting point is ‘our ownlived body,’ always already emplaced. ‘The body,’ he writes, ‘is the specific

    medium for experiencing the place-world’ (p. 24). Bodies, moreover, are

    bilateral, with left, right, forward, and backward orientation. In structure

    and function, bodies orient, and so all (always embodied) perception and

    consciousness is already emplaced. ‘We are never anywhere, anywhen,’

    Casey writes, ‘but in place’ (p. 39).

    What then is place? ‘A place is more an   event   than a   thing   to be

    assimilated to known categories,’ Casey writes; it is not ‘a mere patch of 

    ground, a bare stretch of earth, a sedentary set of stones’ (1996, p. 26).Most usefully, Casey explains that ‘places gather’: ‘Being in a place is

    being in a configurative complex of things.’ Furthermore, ‘places also

    gather experiences and histories, even languages and thoughts’ (pp. 24 –

    25). Places ‘hold’ and ‘keep’ in Casey’s terminology. Memories ‘belong as

    much to the place as to my brain or body’ (p. 25). They are, therefore,

    collective phenomena, transformed by the sentient bodies that inhabit,

    know, or recognize them. Places are the condition of possibility for

    human culture itself: ‘To be cultural, to have a culture, is to inhabit aplace sufficiently intensively to cultivate it . . . . Culture is carried

    into places by bodies. To be encultured is to be embodied to begin

    with’ (p. 34).

    482   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    21/66

    Casey’s interpretation trumps Lefebvre’s critique of abstract space by 

    demonstrating the dependence of the abstract time/space binarism on the

    primacy of place:

    Not only do imperial space and time require recourse to lowly places intheir very definition (rather than conversely), but also the status of spaceand time as equal but opposite terms is put into question by theircommon emplacement. The binarist dogma stretching from Newtonand Leibniz to Kant and Schopenhauer is undone by the basicperception that we experience space and time together in place—inthe locus of a continuous ‘space-time’ that is proclaimed alike intwentieth-century physics, philosophy and anthropology. (1996, p. 37)

    Casey’s placeful phenomenology beautifully compliments Simmel’sformal sociology. Through both, we can see how social forms take place,

    how they are always   in statu nascendi, and why we can find   all human

     phenomena originally arising in and from places. It is time to recognize that

    history must be about those places if it aspires to recount the past.

    The  Topoi of the Past

    We are now ready to understand the relationship between the past, time,and history. Every past is a place (emphatically in the present tense

    because the past is always present). All action and experience  takes place,

    in the sense that it requires place as a prerequisite, and  makes place, in the

    sense of inscription. Casey draws from Aristotle the observation that it is

    impossible to think of a phenomenon or event without thinking of it in

    some place. Even a void is a place of nothingness. Places are prior

    necessities of all phenomena: place ‘takes precedence of all other things’

    (Aristotle,   Physics, quoted in Casey 1997, p. 51). Events are places and

    vice versa.I propose that we refer to the places of the past as topoi. The noun topos

    (place) began its long career in western discourse in the fields of rhetoric

    and logic. Our everyday term for any subject of study or concern, ‘topic,’

    originates in  topos. In Aristotle’s  Topics, the first western treatise on logic,

    topoi   are the logical stratagems for defending or refuting propositions.10

    Although Aristotle never explicitly defines the term, it was most likely 

    borrowed from the widely practiced mnemonic system of using geographic

    locations (familiar sites along a road, or rooms within one’s own house) toanchor memories. Thus, the ‘argument form’ necessary for a given

    refutation could be quickly retrieved in debate (Slomkowski 1997, pp. 43 –

    68; Smith 1997, pp. xxiv – xxx). ‘Each   topos  serves as a location at which

    Rethinking History    483

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    22/66

    many arguments may be found by appropriate substitutions in the relevant

    form’ (Smith 1997, p. xxvii).

    Ernst Robert Curtius (1948) and Leo Spitzer (1948) simultaneously 

    recast topoi from the classical and neoclassical traditions into a central toolof 20th-century literary criticism. Their basic idea is that the vast field of 

    world literature recycles recognizable ‘commonplaces’: the same ‘analogies,

    the same bits of doctrine . . . the same modes or lines of proof, the same

    myths,’ such as ‘the reference of values to the ambiguous norm of Nature;

    the antitheses of nature and art, the simple and the complex, the regular

    and the irregular, the uniform and the diverse; the notions of progress,

    decline, and cyclical change . . .’ (Crane 1954, pp. 74 – 75). R. S. Crane’s

    lucid explication of these recurrent concepts as ‘topoi’ constitutes a

    cartographic method that I wish to retain in my usage: ‘. . . Wherever they occur, they represent not so much what the writers in whose treatises,

    essays, poems, or novels we find them are thinking  about  as much as what

    they are thinking with.’ Thus, ‘the more broadly learned we are, indeed, the

    more correspondences of this kind, linking together parts or brief passages

    in writings of the most diverse sorts, we shall be likely to note in the

    margins of our books . . .’ (p. 75).

    Topoi   are recognizable because we can map them within a general

    topology of the known or familiar. All action, whether building pyramids,making love, writing, or reading, takes and makes place; all individuals are

    the creative authors of their own presence. Reading our environment is a

    holistic endeavor, whether in an everyday mode or with the expert methods

    of the historian. Each element, every sign, is only legible in relation to the

    entire mental map of the world carried within our crania. The cranium also

    serves as a referential point-coordinate (perspective). That which has been

    brought into legible view, such as any aspect of ‘the past’ (however marked

    as such) is by definition something that has been mapped into the network 

    of known or familiar phenomena. Anything that cannot be mapped isbeyond the event horizon of consciousness.

    Topoi   collapse time. I use the term   topoi   to denote the specific places

    of the past because it carries the useful metaphoric Aristotelian and New 

    Criticism traditions, and also the geometric sense of its original usage,

    from which the metaphor was originally drawn. For Aristotle as for me,

    it is sometimes useful to think metaphorically of places, as places of 

    memory.11 That familiar understanding (among many others) that I

    share with this stranger from ancient Greece places us together in atopological relationship. Known pasts (topoi) are mapped onto other

    known   topoi, in a process that constitutes a vast multi-perspectival atlas

    of world history.

    484   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    23/66

    History is the map of the past, but that map is not merely a

    representation.  Topoi   touch the ground in myriad ways. They are not in

    time; they are in space. They can only be discovered, interpreted, and

    debated via the coordinates of spacetime.   Topoi   are not free-floatingsignifiers.

    History is the map of past. Its elemental units are   topoi. In my latest

    vintage of this term, topos signifies the intersection of (lived) place-time and

    (natural) spacetime.

    History as Cartography 

    It matters that history  takes  and makes  place because knowing the  topoi of 

    history is literally to map the human past. I mean to expand the meaning of ‘mapping’ very broadly, but I shall not dilute it into merely a suggestive

    metaphor. Maps represent the relationships among   topoi, be they points,

    lines, polygons, or actions, events, experiences, and ideas. Definitions of the

    noun and verb form of ‘map’ range from ‘the representation of the earth’s

    surface or part of it on a flat surface,’ to the metaphoric ‘conceptualization

    or mental representation of the structure, extent, or layout of an area of 

    experience, field of study, ideology, etc.’ (Oxford English Dictionary Online,

    accessed 2005).I can reach Cambridge from Los Angeles by consulting maps depicting

    the pathways now in use. I can understand the sense of ‘virtue’ current in

    16th-century Cambridge by consulting a range of historical texts that track 

    the discursive pathways both prior to that place and since. Pocock’s

    brilliant   The Machiavellian Moment   (1975) mapped the vast network of 

    texts (traces of communicative action) that made ‘virtue’ a powerful

    keyword in early modern Europe. Cartography refers to the making of 

    maps, of course, but there is no official definition of what a map should

    look like. It can be pictorial, verbal, or mathematical. The only basicrequirement is that a map depict the topological relationships among topoi,

    whether ‘Cambridge’ or ‘virtue.’

    Pictorial maps communicate via vocabularies of shape (points, lines,

    and polygons), color, tone, and iconography. Those vocabularies are

    organized by a syntax comprised of contiguity, scale, paths, distance, area

    (zones, regions, boundaries), volume, and legend. Pictorial maps are

    typically synchronic ‘snapshots,’ but they can be drawn and even

    animated to represent time, motion, and processes. Maps and mappingare today subjected to a critical discourse about the visual representation

    of space and place that is epitomized in the multivolume  The History of 

    Cartography   (1987 – 2007), edited by J. B. Harley and David Woodward,

    Rethinking History    485

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    24/66

    and the work both of these late scholars did to clarify the ideological and

    ideational constructedness of maps. But, as Jane Azevedo (1997) has

    argued, although all maps ‘are constructed with interests in mind’ (p.

    108) their validity is not necessarily undermined by that constructionbecause their use value inheres in enabling us to achieve objectives. Even

    maps of radically different construction must be ‘deeply compatible’

    because ‘a mapping relationship exists between any two maps of the same

    territory’ (pp. 107, 144).

    Cartography is not inherently flawed because of its reinvention during

    the imperial epoch of the European Renaissance. The critique of 

    Eurocentric, scientific space is an instance of perspectivalism: the

    attribution of knowledge or understanding to the social location of the

    subject. Perspectivalism along with related concepts of ‘subject positions’and ‘positionality’ (LaCapra 2004, p. 5) have been deployed extensively in

    the current crisis of knowledge to undermine the possibility of any objective

    or certain knowledge. Postcolonial scholarship has regionalized (Prakash

    1999), even provincialized  (Chakrabarty 2000) western epistemology (Blaut

    1993). Perspective itself now must be subjected to critique of its grounded

    metaphoricality in order to understand subject positions as topoi   that can

    be mapped. Mapping cartography is vital to my proposal to rethink 

    historical interpretation as a form of mapping.We owe to Hayden White (1973, 1985) our map of the ‘tropics’ of 

    historical discourse. White influentially explicated the ways that irony,

    metaphor, metonymy, and synecdoche supply the four basic ‘tropes’ by 

    which historians arrange data about the past. He further claimed that

    historians arbitrarily ‘emplot’ these data as Romance, Tragedy, Comedy,

    and Satire. But we have labored too long under the shadow of White’s

    radical skepticism about the value of the data themselves as sources of 

    historical knowledge. Following the same faulty pathways through the

    linguistic turn as so many modernists and postmodernists, White failed tosee that the past takes place, and that textual narrative is not the only way to

    present the places of the past. I propose that we move from White’s

    ‘metahistorical’ tropics toward a topology  of the past. His tropics, after all,

    are clear cases of  topoi as are his own interventions. Cartography’s infinitely 

    possible figurations cannot be reduced to narrative form. Indeed, a

    cartographic history can escape the narrative   topoi   of White’s historical

    epistemology.

    It should be very clear by this point that I am not talking about thetraditional field of historical geography, although that field is certainly not

    irrelevant (Baker 2003). Instead, I am claiming that the incalculable volume

    486   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    25/66

    of historical writing on all subjects should be thought of as a map because

    the past can only be known by placing it, and the way of knowing places is

    to map them. The emplacement of all human action presumes locations in

    spacetime, which materializes each place. The ‘landscape of history,’ toreturn to Gaddis’ phrase, proves to be far more than a useful analogy. By 

    interrogating the temporality of history, we have revealed experience as the

    intersection of place and space, which is also the intersection of human and

    natural time. Recognizing the placefulness of pastness indicates a clear

    pathway around the blockades raised by the linguistic turn.

    Mapping is the form of interpretation that historians practice. Their

    hermeneutic operation is intrinsically cartographic, or possibly choreographic,

    for all life is movement, despite the conceptual utility (as in Benjamin) of 

    freezing it photographically. However daunting may seem the prospect of ‘mapping’ such intangible topoi as love, greed, faith, ambition, racism, justice

    (and all the various forms of cultural cognition that historians must address),

    the task is unavoidable given that all human actions inscribe topoi, and every 

    topos  is simultaneously locatable and meaningful.

    Conclusions

    What does ‘placing the past’ accomplish? How does this formulationamount to more than a clever new phrase, renaming what we already 

    know? First, I hope that by adding the ingredient of spatiality to the

    pragmatic-hermeneutic tradition, grafted back into that tradition by way of 

    its lost relative Georg Simmel, we can strengthen recent postpositivist work 

    in the pragmatic tradition (Bernstein 1983; Appleby   et al  . 1994;

    Kloppenberg 1996; Hacking 1999, 2002).

    Because it pivots on the concept of grounded metaphors, the method

    of placing the past could be called neo-foundational. Placing the past

    recognizes no boundary between natural and human inquiry, because alltopoi   are placeful spacetimes, both meaningful and measurable. The

    knowing subject is the material world reaching back to itself. Placing the

    past does not depend on Cartesian dualisms, like John Searle’s case for

    ‘external reality’ (Searle 1995). I propose that the coordinates of 

    spacetime (using any generally recognized system) are a post-foundational

    universal, not as a natural truth, but much better: as historical institution.

    Placing the past anchors dialogic reason to universal, mappable criteria.

    Placing the past takes ‘the past’ out of time, locates it in materializedtopoi, and asserts that history, in any symbolic system, is the map of these

    topoi.

    Rethinking History    487

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    26/66

    Acknowledgements

    I owe a deep debt of gratitude to the organizers of, and participants in, four

    forums in which I presented the earlier formulations of this essay: JoanNeuberger and David Crew at the University of Texas, Austin (September

    2003); Lourdes Roca and Fernado Aguaya at the Instituto de Investiga-

    ciones Dr José Marı́a Luis Mora (‘El Mora’) in Mexico City (October 2003);

    José  Marı́a Cardesin at the Universidad de La Coruña, Spain (November

    2005); and Kathleen Canning and William Rosenberg at the Institute for

    Historical Studies at the University of Michigan (September 2006). For

    their critical comments on earlier drafts, my thanks also to Richard Fox,

    Jason Glenn, Valerie Kivelson, James Kloppenberg, David Levitus, David

    Lloyd, Carol Mangione, Steve Ross, Vanessa Schwartz, Brooke Selling,Binky Walker, and an anonymous reader. A special thanks to my infinitely 

    patient and encouraging editor, David Harlan.

    Notes

    [1] Siân Reynolds’ translation of this crucial passage is revealing, however. Braudel’s

    1949 original of the italicized phrase reads ‘une histoire quasi-immobile,’ which

    could well have been translated as ‘a history somewhat fixed in place’ (Braudel

    1949, p. xiii).

    [2] The first universal standard established was that in 1889 by the Bureau Inter-

    national des Poids et Mesures, an ‘artifact unit’ prototype of a meter made from

    platinum and iridium and stored under glass in a cool, dry place in Sèvres, France.

    Intolerably subject nonetheless to expansion and contraction, the stately thing was

    replaced in 1960 and again in 1983 by the 11th and 17th Resolutions of the CGPM,

    respectively. See SI Brochure, Section 2.1.1.1, www.bipm.fr/, under ‘metre.’

    [3] Jorge Luis Borges makes a powerful case against ‘time’ in this way, drawing

    explicitly on Bergson (and Berkeley, and himself) in his anguished and evocative

    essay ‘A New Refutation of Time’ ([1944, 1948], 1962).

    [4] Literally, ‘The moment where I speak is already far from me,’ but idiomatically,‘Just as I speak the moment is already far from me.’

    [5] To the asymmetry of time we might add the asymmetry of spatial and temporal

    metaphors: time is metaphorized as space, but never vice versa.

    [6] ‘What then does  ich bin  mean? The old word  bauen, to which the  bin  belongs,

    answers, ich bin, du bist  mean I dwell, you dwell. The way in which you are and I

    am, the manner in which we humans are on the earth, is   buan, dwelling’

    (Heidegger [1951] 1993, p. 349).

    [7] Edward Soja (1996) has added neologism to obscurity by enthusiastically 

    rechristening these triads ‘trialectics.’

    [8] Lefebvre never mentions Simmel in  The Production of Space  (1974); Soja (1989,p. 33) mentions him only in passing.

    [9] On Simmel’s infuriating failure to use footnotes, and his failure to acknowledge

    Dilthey, see Frisby (1992, p. 37).

    488   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    27/66

    [10] The lengthy list of these   topoi   begins in Book 2. W. A. Pickard-Cambridge

    translates   topoi  as ‘commonplace rules’ throughout the translation included by 

    Jonathan Barnes in  The Complete Works of Aristotle   (Aristotle 1984, vol. 1, pp.

    167 – 277).

    [11] ‘Aristotle’ is no longer a man, nor even merely a text. ‘Aristotle’ is a pluralinstitution, a vast array of  topoi  in popular, religious, and expert discourses.

    References

    Agnew, J.A. and Duncan, J.S. (1989)  The Power of Place: Bringing Together Geographical 

    and Sociological Imaginations,  Unwin Hyman, Boston, MA.

    Aguessy, H., Ashish, M., Askin, Y.F., Boubou Hama, Gadamer, H.-G., Gardet, L.,

    Hasnaoui, A., Honderlich, T., Jeannière, A., Karsz, S., Ohe, S., Ricoeur, P.,

    Toynbee, A.J. and Witt-Hansen, J. (1977)   Time and the Philosophies: At theCrossroads of Cultures, UNESCO, Paris.

    Appleby, J., Hunt, L. and Jacob, M. (1994)  Telling the Truth About History,  Norton, New 

    York.

    Aristotle (1984)  The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. J.

    Barnes, 2 vols, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Azevedo, J. (1997) Mapping Reality: An Evolutionary Realist Methodology for the Natural 

    and Social Sciences,  State University of New York Press, Albany, NY.

    Bachelard, G. ([1958] 1964) The Poetics of Space,  trans. M. Jolas, Beacon Press, Boston,

    MA.

    Baker, A.R.H. (2003) Geography and History: Bridging the Divide,  Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.

    Becker, C.L. ([1931] 1966) Everyman His Own Historian: Essays on History and Politics,

    Quadrangle Books, Chicago, IL.

    Bergson, H. ([1890] 1960)  Time and Free Will,   trans. F.L. Pogson, Harper and Row,

    New York.

    Bergson, H. ([1896] 1991) Matter and Memory, trans N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer, Zone

    Books, New York.

    Bergson, H. ([1907] 1983)   Creative Evolution,   trans. A. Mitchell, University Press of 

    America, Lanham, MD.

    Bergson, H. ([1922] 2002)   Duration and Simultaneity, With Reference to Einstein’sTheory,   trans L. Jacobson and M. Lewis, in  Key Writings, eds K.A. Pearson and

    J. Mullarkey, Continuum, New York.

    Bernstein, R.J. (1983)   Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and 

    Praxis, University of Philadelphia Press, Philadelphia, PA.

    Blaut, J.M. (1993)   The Colonizers Model of the World: Geographic Diffusionism and 

    Eurocentric History,  The Gilford Press, New York.

    Bloch, M. (1953)   The Historian’s Craft,  trans. P. Putnam, Vintage Books, New York.

    Borges, J.L. ([1944, 1948] 1962) ‘A new refutation of time’ in Labyrinths: Selected Stories

    and Other Writings,  New Directions Publishing, New York.

    Braudel, F. (1949) La Méditerranée et le Monde Méditerranéen à l’E  ́poque de Philippe II,Librarie Armand Colin, Paris.

    Braudel, F. (1980) On History, trans. S. Matthews, University of Chicago Press, Chicago,

    IL.

    Rethinking History    489

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    28/66

    Braudel, F. (1972)  The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip

    II,  trans. S. Reynolds, Harper and Row, New York.

    Carr, D. (1986)  Time, Narrative, and History,  Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN.

    Carr, E.H. (1961)  What is History?,  Vintage, New York.

    Casey, E.S. (1996) ‘How to get from space to place in a fairly short stretch of time:phenomenological prolegomena’ in  Senses of Place,  eds S. Feld and K.H. Basso,

    School of American Research Press, Santa Fe, NM.

    Casey, E.S. (1997)   The Fate of Place: A Philosophical History,  University of California

    Press, Berkeley, CA.

    Chakrabarty, D. (2000)   Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical 

    Difference,  Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Confino, A. (1997) ‘Collective memory and cultural history: problems of method’,

     American Historical Review , December, pp. 1386 – 1403.

    Crane, R.S. (1954) ‘Literature, philosophy, and the history of ideas,’  Modern Philology ,

    vol. 52, no. 2, pp. 73 – 83.Cresswell, T. (2004)  Place: A Short Introduction,  Blackwell Publishers, Malden, MA.

    Curtius, E.R. ([1948] 1953)   European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages,   tr. W.R.

    Trask, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.

    Diddams, S.A., Berquist, J.C., Jefferts, S.R. and Oates, C.W. (2004) Standards of time

    and frequency at the outset of the 21st century,  Science, 306, pp. 1318 – 1324.

    Dilthey, W. (2002)  Selected Works, Vol. 3: The Formation of the Historical World in the

    Human Sciences,   eds R.A. Makkreel and F. Rodi, Princeton University Press,

    Princeton, NJ.

    Dimendberg, E. (1998) ‘Henri Lefebvre on abstract space’ in Philosophy and Geography 

    II: The Production of Public Space,   eds A. Light and J.M. Smith, Rowman andLittlefield, Boston, MA, pp. 17 – 48.

    Dostal, R.J. (1993) ‘Time and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger’ in   The

    Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, ed. C. Guignon, Cambridge University Press,

    New York.

    Elden, S. (2001) ‘Politics, philosophy and geography: Henri Lefebvre in recent Anglo-

    American scholarship’,  Antipode, vol. 33, no. 5, pp. 809 – 825.

    Ethington, P.J. (1997) ‘The intellectual construction of ‘‘social distance’’: toward a

    recovery of Georg Simmel’s social geometry’   Cybergeo,   electronic edition of 

    European Journal of Geography , article 30, Available at: http://www.cybergeo.

    presse.fr/essoct/texte/socdis.htmEthington, P.J. (2005) ‘Georg Simmel y a cuestión de la espacialidad’,   Trayectorias:

    Revista de Ciencias Sociales de la Universidad Autónoma de Nuevo León, vol. 7, no.

    19, pp. 46 – 58.

    Feld, S. and Basso, K.H. (1996)  Senses of Place, School of American Research Press,

    Berkeley, CA.

    Feynman, R.P. (1965)  The Character of Physical Law,  The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Fischer, D.H. (1970) Historians’ Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought,  Harper

    & Row, New York.

    Flood, R. and Lockwood, M. (eds) (1986)  The Nature of Time, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Focillon, H. ([1934] 1992)  The Life of Forms in Art,   trans C.B. Hogan and G. Kubler,Zone Books, New York.

    Foucault, M. (1998) ‘Different spaces’ in  Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology , ed. J.D.

    Faubion, trans. R. Hurley   et al., vol. 2 of Essential Works of Foucault, 1954 –

    1984, ed. P. Rabinow, The New Press, New York, pp. 175 – 186.

    490   P. J. Ethington

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    29/66

    Fraser, J.T. (1981)  The Voices of Time: A Cooperative Survey of Man’s Views of Time as

    Expressed by the Sciences and the Humanities,   2nd edn, University of 

    Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA.

    Frisby, D. (1986)  Fragments of Modernity: Theories of Modernity in the Work of Simmel,

    Kracauer and Benjamin, The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Frisby, D. (1987) ‘The ambiguity of modernity: Georg Simmel and Max Weber’ in  Max 

    Weber and his Contemporaries,  eds W.J. Mommsen and J. Osterhammel, Unwin

    Hyman, London.

    Frisby, D. (ed.) (1990) ‘Preface’ and ‘Introduction’ to Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of 

     Money , trans and eds T. Bottomore and D. Frisby, 2nd edn, Routledge, London.

    Frisby, D. (1992) Simmel and Since: Essays on Georg Simmel’s Social Theory, Routledge,

    London.

    Gaddis, J.L. (2002)   The Landscape of History: How Historians Map the Past,   Oxford

    University Press, New York.

    Gieryn, T.F. (2000) ‘A space for place in sociology’,  Annual Reviews in Sociology , vol. 26,pp. 463 – 496.

    Grünbaum, A. (1963)  Philosophical Problems of Space and Time,  Knopf, New York.

    Guignon, C. (ed.) (1993)   The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger , Cambridge

    University Press, New York.

    Hacking, I. (1999)   The Social Construction of What?,   Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge, MA.

    Hacking, I. (2002)  Historical Ontology,  Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Halbwachs, M. (1992)  On Collective Memory,  trans. L.A. Coser, University of Chicago

    Press, Chicago, IL.

    Haraven, T. (1991) ‘Synchronizing individual time, family time, and historical time’ inChronotypes: The Construction of Time, eds J. Bender and D.E. Wellbery, Stanford

    University Press, Stanford, CA.

    Harley, J.B. and Woodward, D. (eds) (1987 – 2007) The History of Cartography,  vols 1 –

    4, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Harvey, D. (1989)   The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins of 

    Cultural Change,  Blackwell, Oxford.

    Heidegger, M. ([1924] 1992)  Concept of Time, trans. W. McNeill, Blackwell, Cambridge,

    MA.

    Heidegger, M. ([1927] 1962)  Being and Time,   trans J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson,

    Harper and Row, New York.Heidegger, M. ([1951] 1993) ‘Building dwelling thinking’ in   Basic Writings,   ed. D.

    Farrell Krell, HarperCollins, New York.

    Heidegger, M. (2002)  On Time and Being,  trans. J. Stambaugh, University of Chicago

    Press, Chicago, IL.

    Hubbard, P., Kitchen, R. and Valentine, G. (2004)  Key Thinkers of Space and Place, Sage

    Publications, London.

    James, W. ([1890] 1983)   The Principles of Psychology,   Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge, MA.

    Kansteiner, W. (2002) ‘Finding meaning in memory: a methodological critique of 

    collective memory studies’,  History and Theory , vol. 41, May, pp. 179 – 197.Kern, S. (1983)  The Culture of Time and Space, 1880 – 1918, Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge, MA.

    Klein, K. (2000) ‘On the emergence of memory in historical discourse’, Representations,

    no. 69, Winter, pp. 127 – 150.

    Rethinking History    491

  • 8/20/2019 Ethington Et Al Placing the Past

    30/66

    Kloppenberg, J.T. (1989) ‘Objectivity and historicism: a century of American historical

    writing’,  American Historical Review , 94, pp. 1011 – 1030.

    Kloppenberg, J.T. (1996) ‘Pragmatism: an old name for some new ways of thinking?’,

     Journal of American History , vol. 83, no. 1, pp. 100 – 138.

    Kracauer, S. (1969)  History: The Last Things Before the Last. Completed after the deathof the author by P. O. Kristeller, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Krell, D.F. (1995)  Archeticture: Ecstasies of Space, Time, and the Human Body,   State

    University of New York Press, Albany, NY. (NB Krell’s spelling ‘Archeticture’ is

    intentional.)

    Kubler, G. (1962) The Shape of Time: Remarks on the History of Things, Yale University 

    Press, New Haven, CN.

    LaCapra, D. (2004)   History in Transit: Experience, Identity, Critical Theory,   Cornell

    University Press, Ithaca, NY.

    Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1980) Metaphors We Live By,  University of Chicago Press,

    Chicago, IL.Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1999)  Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and its

    Challenge to Western Thought,  Basic Books, New York.

    Landes, D.S. (2000)   Revolution in Time: Clocks and the Making of the Modern World,

    revised and enlarged edition, Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,

    Cambridge, MA.

    Lefebvre, H. (1974)  La Production de l’Espace,  Anthropos, Paris.

    Lefebvre, H. (1991)   The Production of Space,   trans. D. Nicholson-Smith, Blackwell

    Publishing, Cambridge, MA.

    Levine, D.N. (1991) ‘Simmel and Parsons reconsidered’,  American Journal of Sociology ,

    vol. 96, no. 5, pp. 1097 – 1116.Low, S.M. and Lawrence-Zúñiga, D. (2003)   The Anthropology of Space and Place:

    Locating Culture,   Blackwell Publishing, Malden, MA.

    Lowenthal, D. (1985)  The Past is a Foreign Country,  Cambridge University Press, New 

    York.

    McTaggart, J.E. (1908) ‘The unreality of time’,  Mind , vol. 17, no. 68, pp. 457 – 474.

    Megill, A. (1989) ‘Recounting the past: ‘‘description,’’ explanation, and narrative in

    historiography,  American Historical Review , vol. 94, no. 3, pp. 627 – 653.

    Munslow, A. (2000) The Routledge Companion to Historical Studies,  Routledge, London.

    Nora, P. (ed.) (1996) Realms of Memory: Rethinking the French Past. Vol. I: Conflicts and 

    Divisions, trans. A. Goldhammer, Columbia University Press, New York.Novick, P. (1988)   That Noble Dream: The ‘Objectivity Question’ and the American

    Historical Profession,  Cambridge University Press, New York.

    Oxford English Dictionary Online, http://dictionary.oed.com, accessed 2003, 2005, 2007.

    Pocock, J.G.A. (1975)  The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the

     Atlantic Republican Tradition, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Pocock, J.G.A. (1989)   Politics, Language, and Time: Essays on Political Thought and 

    History, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Prakash, G. (1999)