ferguson_frances - georg lukacs

Upload: ojero

Post on 03-Apr-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    1/14

    Georg Lukacs

    By Frances Ferguson

    A Tale of Two Cities has many admirers. It was for years the Dickens novel

    most likely to be assigned to high school students, and W.B. Matz noted in 1922 that

    it had recently tied (with David Copperfield) as the favorite work of fiction of women

    freshmen at Radcliffe.Yet for all the admiration the novel has inspired, it has

    prompted an almost equal measure of criticism. Lukacs, in The Historical Novel,

    mentions A Tale of Two Cities only to object that the weaknesses of Dickenss petty

    bourgeois humanism and idealism are more obvious and obtrusive in this novel than

    in those that Lukacs admires and categorizes as the truly social novels. For Lukacs, it

    is a limitation of the novel that Dickens, by giving pre-eminence to the purely moral

    aspects of causes and effects, weakens the connection between the problems of thecharacters lives and the events of the French Revolution. In the novel, he continues,

    the Revolution becomes romantic background and the turbulence of the times is used

    as a pretext for revealing human-moral qualities (243). And John P. Williams, Jr.

    extends Lukacss general view in arguing that Dickens eviscerated politics to defend

    individual morality, writing that Dickens attempted to control the monster of

    revolution by devising a tale in which no political issue is finally pertinent either to

    the assumed certainty of social progress or to the conduct of the truly virtuous man.

    From one perspective the criticism is surprising, because Dickens continually

    speaks of revolution as an inevitable response to abusive social arrangements and

    vividly shows the French Revolution and its animating motives at work in the lives ofotherwise ordinary individuals. Yet at least two features of the novel make the

    criticism telling. The first is that Dickenss reliance on Cartons love for Lucie

    Manette can make his self-sacrifice look like a celebration of the merely personal and

    generally domestic affections. (I say generally here to take into account Hilary

    Schors argument that these happen to be adulterously domestic affections, in that

    Carton manages to intrude himself into the lives of the Darnay family as much as if he

    had actually had an affair with Lucie.) The second is that Dickenss insistence on

    Cartons disguising himself as Darnay deprives him of a public and political voice.

    Carton cannot utter any statement aloud, lest he reveal that he is not Darnay. And he

    thus both appears to see the future and remains sphinx-like as he goes to his death,

    offering personal comfort to the touchingly unprotected young seamstress rather thandenouncing either the Terrorists or those who had so oppressed the French people that

    Revolution came to seem the only imaginable response.

    Indeed, the most compelling feature of Lukacss objections is that they

    ultimately call attention to the ending of the novel and the way in which it does not so

    much deliver historical events as pass judgment on them. Dickens, ventriloquizing

    Cartons thoughts, accords them the authority of last words. And indeed, Cartons

    prophecy seems all the stronger for having gone unuttered. In the far-seeing

    conditional in which Carton enjoys the endorsement of never having spoken and thus

    never having opened himself to possible contradiction, he seems to become the

    spokesperson for History how things will ultimately have turned out. If you thinkparticularly of Dickenss long view of the evil of this time and of the previous time of

    1

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    2/14

    which this is the natural birth, gradually making expiation for itself and wearing out, it

    is easy to hear a biblical sonorousness about the passing of generations and regimes

    that treats politics as mere skirmishing (366). And its not surprising to learn that

    many have heard those words harmonizing with the kind of shibboleths in which

    people clucked with smug self-satisfaction as they spoke of the ultimate failure of

    the French Revolution and opined that it had been doomed from the outset by its ownextremism. In that light, it resonates unfortunately with recent claims that history has

    delivered up a definitive report of the collapse of communism with a footnote on the

    inevitability of this result. Such statements always combine two claims1) that a

    political approach was internally and fatally flawed (brought down by its own hand)

    and 2) that I told you so. Insofar as the novels ending sounds like those statements, it

    arguably feels like a betrayal of the opening chapter with its connections between the

    past Dickens is describing and the present, and between France just prior to the

    Revolution and the England of the same moment--and especially of its sardonic

    assertion that In both countries it was clearer than crystal to the lord of the State

    preserves of loaves and fishes, that things in general were settled for ever (13). And

    we might think of that betrayal as having already begun with the second chapter whenDickens drops his accounts of the likeness of England and France and begins to treat

    London and Paris principally as two locations in which the story of his characters

    personal lives unfold. We certainly might think of that betrayal as fully achieved

    when Dickens next speaks of the Two Cities, only to treat the connection in terms of

    the affectionate grandiosity of family life; the young Lucie Darnay, he says, blended

    the tongues of the Two Cities in her life by growing up speaking both French and

    English.

    Lukacs confines his remarks on A Tale of Two Cities to one paragraph with a

    brief continuation in another, but his observations on how the fate of the characters

    does not grow organically out of the age and its social events may help us to mount adefense of the novel that extends past simply insisting that the novel is, too, great. For

    if Lukacs expresses reservations about Dickenss abstract-moral attitude toward

    concrete social-moral phenomena (243-244) , I think he also helps us to identify

    various key features of the novel that allow us to argue that Dickens was not failing a

    political project but was trying to come to terms with changes in politics even more

    revolutionary than those Lukacs imagined. He was not, I think, sacrificing the

    political to the domestic but was instead wrestling with his newly discovered sense of

    their extraordinary interconnections. Indeed, I want to maintain that he was trying to

    come to terms with the very ideas of terror and terrorism in the political world. For

    while Lukacs particularly values the ways in which class-consciousness can come to

    be a resource for novelistic characters and has an extraordinary ear for moments inwhich characters speak of how they will never be able to take us for granted again,

    Dickens seems to me to be addressing a different issue. His question, briefly stated, is

    How do we conceive of our own actions if we cannot think of our actions as

    expressing either our individual wishes or the interests and wishes of a group with

    whom we identify? And how do we come to terms with the instability of the

    relationships between individuals and the groups in which those individuals

    sometimes have membership?

    In the discussion that follows, I shall be arguing that in A Tale of Two Cities

    Dickens develops an account of how abstractions come to occupy concrete social-

    moral phenomena in modern morality. Lukacs takes Dickens to separate out what hecalls the purely human and the purely moral from their social basis and laments that

    2

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    3/14

    this tendency is not corrected by reality itself, by its impact upon the writers

    openness and receptivity as he see it to be in his best novels on the present. (244). Yet

    while Lukacs plausibly values social concreteness, Dickens is, I think, concerned to

    make the novel tackle the abstractness that a host of writers most notably Burke in the

    Reflections on the Revolution in France had associated with French thought generally

    and with French revolutionary thought in particular. The more I have ponderedLukacss list of all thats missing from the novel--full characterization of key figures

    under social pressure, dialogue that would continually yield the sense of characters in

    confrontation the more I have thought that hes right to think that theyre missing but

    wrong to think that the novel would have been improved if it had had them. For if

    Lukacs is interested in depicting persons aware of their own social agency, Dickens is,

    I think, committed to examining how all our notions of both political and moral

    agency must be recast. The French Revolution and the Terror of September 1793

    through July of 1794 thus come to look less like events than like an intensification of

    a logic of agency that pre-existed them and post-dates them. For if it is easy to believe

    that the Columbia Encyclopedia is correct in saying that Terrorism reaches back to

    ancient Greece and has occurred throughout history and that it is a tactic and not anideology, it seems to me that Dickens was grappling in A Tale of Two Cities with the

    extent to which the modern deployment of the political tactic of terrorism escaped

    individuals and ideologies in a way that couldnt be addressed merely by invoking the

    standard rules of moral and political engagement.

    Ive already used the words terror and terrorism, but I must now begin to say

    something about what they entail that does not rely on you to supply the notions with

    content.

    We know all too much about terrorism. We know that it combines actual

    attacks and the threat of attacks. We know that it is often directed against the civilian

    population--people at work in office towers, people riding the commuter train to theirjobs. We know that it distributes fear very widely as people go from checking to be

    sure their own limbs are still intact, to congratulating themselves on not having been

    at the wrong place at the wrong time, to thinking of how they or a friend or relative

    might well have been at that wrong place at that wrong time, to feeling that all places

    and times suddenly harbor the possibility of being at that wrong place and that wrong

    time. The aspect of terrorism that would particularly have interested Dickens that I

    believe particularly did interest Dickens is that terrorism alters the world we tend to

    think of as a moral world. Even as world leaders and journalists denounce terrorism as

    pure evil and speak of the cowardliness and thuggishness of terrorists, it is hard not to

    hear their words as just so much preaching to the choir about how bad actions areauthored by bad people.

    That understanding of morality to put the best face on it--continues to find its

    most powerful expression in Kants categorical imperative, with its statement of the

    principle that humans must seek to avoid harming other people as a simple reflex of

    their respect for themselves (and its implicit claim that they can and often do behave

    well on the basis of this self-respect when extraindividual reasons go wanting).. That

    version of morality finds a corollary in the notion that people should not seek to keep

    their consciences clean either by doing nothing or by casuistically controlling their

    knowledge of the effects of their actions. (Think of Miltons denunciations of

    cloistered virtue or George Eliots depiction of drunkenness not merely as oblivion

    but as obliviousness to ones own actions and their consequences.) It is a conceptionthat is persuasive both positively and negatively positively, in that our most basic

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    4/14

    ideas of conscience involve imagining that we accuse ourselves even when other

    people dont know that we should be accused; and, negatively, in that it is easy to see

    that no amount of force or eloquent reasonableness can make anyone behave better

    than they are willing to behave. Yet these quite plausible accounts of the centrality of

    individuality to moral action begin to take on a more sinister tinge if we recast them

    only slightly and bring out the element of self-policing that Foucault (and Schillerbefore him) found in the Kantian moral view, if we move from George Eliots sense

    that moral concerns are the greatest spur to knowledge to a question about the

    desirability of our trying to be the most scrupulous of moral accountants, continually

    developing ever more exacting standards and employing our so-called autonomy in

    the service of our own enslavement.

    Yet the critique of the Kantian account of the autonomy of individual moral

    action did not wait for Foucault. It was, I think, already present in work that had been

    written before Kants moral writings and that had an honored place among the French

    revolutionaries that of Rousseau. Robespierre, as Gregory Dart has told us, carried

    Rousseaus writings at his breast. And if that information accords with things we longthought we knew about Rousseaus influence on the French Revolutionaries, the

    surprising element is that Robespierre always carried and read Rousseaus

    Confessions rather than the writings with overtly political titles. That choice was,

    moreover, part and parcel of a new account of the interpenetration of the personal and

    the political. The Revolutionaries may have developed legislation that erased the

    distinction between public and private life, but Rousseau had made the distinction

    appear untenable.

    Rousseaus contribution to moral thought, I want to suggest, was to have

    discredited individual moral authority and to have shown the difficulties of seeing

    individual conscience as the ultimate arbiter of moral conduct. Thus, he was

    constantly able to portray himself as a good man indeed, a very good man-- who hadhappened to do things that might look evil. Indeed, the Confessions insists upon some

    version of this formulation almost to the point of monotony. If for some two

    centuries, commentators have denounced Rousseaus hypocrisy in the Confessions

    and have charged him with particular moral fecklessness, they have been right about

    the information he gave them and prematurely judgmental in their assessment. It was,

    indeed, strange of Rousseau to describe giving up all of the children his mistress

    Therese Levasseur bore him as if that action were reasonable especially when

    admission to a foundling hospital very nearly amounted to a death sentence. Indeed, it

    could be said to be deceptive or self-deceptive of Rousseau to have imagined that he

    was really confessing anything at all, since he so regularly ended every confessionalepisode by explaining that he had been misinformed. His intentions were good, he

    regularly said, but his friends had misled him; he had acted on mistaken information.

    Yet if we stop with the observation of Rousseaus hypocrisy, we blind

    ourselves to the question of whether we usually know enough to make moral

    decisions. Rousseau makes us reconsider our failures of knowledge and the gaps in

    our information and enables us to see the extent to which we constitute ourselves as

    moral agents not just by having an impact for good or ill upon other people but also

    by being constituted by the perceptions of other people. This process obviously and

    inevitably operated with a double logicor, at least, a double standard. Thus, he

    notoriously insisted that women needed to be extremely modest, because they were, in

    his view, responsible not only for their actions but for their reputations. Women, thatis, deserved even their reputations, and were responsible for them even when they

    4

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    5/14

    bore no relation to the actions that those women had actually performed. On the one

    hand, Rousseaus self-castigation always ended in self-exoneration (on Rousseaus

    part); on the other hand, women were said to be accountable for anything that might

    be thought of them so that it was hard to imagine that they could ever be exonerated

    of anything. It may be that Rousseau was merely making a shrewd empirical

    observation about the way in which blame travels towards servants, towards women.But I think that we can take the measure of this second peculiar account of misaligned

    accusation only by compounding the offense and seeing how far Rousseau was

    casting moral action into the orbit of what might seem like social and political

    considerations outside the control of individuals conceived as individuals. He saw the

    importance, that is, of conceiving of moral action not merely as transcendental in

    relation to its objects but as reflexively transcendental in relation to its authors. Thus,

    while Todorov stresses Rousseaus perception that moral agents must see their

    obligations as determined generally rather than particularly by which he means that

    you must want to do right by strangers and not just by the significant others in your

    life-- I think Rousseau lays out that aspect of a transcendental view and then

    supplements it with an understanding of how our capacities to deliver on that sense ofobligation are themselves been transcendentally constructed (in a view that accords

    with Bernard Williamss account of moral luck). While we often conceive of morality

    as individual and indeed conceive of it as solitary in our accounts of individuals who

    held their moral course despite opposition, Rousseau saw that morality in modernity

    was no longer a matter of individual decision. All of his whining about the goodness

    of his motives and the faultiness of his execution of them amounted to a recognition

    that our capacities to form those motives and to execute them are fundamentally

    affected by our social existence.

    To put the matter this way is to begin to understand how fully socialized we

    are even as moral agents. By comparison even with a view like Bernard Williamssthat pleads the case of particular individual circumstances against abstract moral

    transcendentalism and wonders what sort of people we would have to be to decide

    that we couldnt save members of our families before we saved strangers or

    acquaintances, Rousseau concerns himself with what strangers can do to our moral

    capacities. His contribution to moral philosophy was, as I see it, to have come to

    recognize that our dilemma is to try to achieve particular moral effects as agents who

    are only virtual actors, composites of the persons they really are and the persons

    whom others treat them as being. (Think of the difference in degrees of legal and,

    implicitly, moral--obligation that tort law imposes on the deep-pocketed and the

    indigent.) From Rousseaus perspective, even Williamss position retains too

    individualistic a focus, in that it begins with a moral individual and extrapolates setsof commitments. Rousseaus position, instead, includes a reciprocal concern with the

    ways in which we are known by and to other people.

    This is as much as to say that both Rousseau and the French Revolutionaries

    saw that the personal was the political and the political the personal in ways that

    extended well past the passage of particular laws governing families and education.

    For if Rousseau took the realist position that we would have no individual examples

    without benefit of concepts that precede them and made them recognizable (no

    individual oaks without the concept of the oak, as he puts it in the Essay on the

    Origins of Inequality), he took a similarly realist view of moral action.

    In other words, instead of simply insisting that each man must treat other menas an example of man in the most extensive and abstract sense, Rousseau also tracked

    5

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    6/14

    the importance of the fact that we are each treated as men or women or white or black

    or rich or poor. Our very ability to treat other people as man is affected by the degree

    to which we are ourselves treated as man.

    Rousseaus philosophical realism his emphasis on the priority of the general

    concept over the particular instance did not itself cause the Revolution and the Terror,

    but it did create an opening for defining virtue as the capacity to be undistracted by

    particular examples. Thus, Robespierre could tell the National Convention in 1794

    that Terror is nought but prompt, severe, inflexible justice; it is therefore an emanation

    of virtue; it is less a particular principle than a consequence of the general principle of

    democracy applied to the most pressing needs of the fatherland. It was justice that did

    not simply confine itself to acts that persons had committed. Rather, it addressed the

    distribution of the very ability to act. The notion of the people required stripping away

    the category of aristocrat and that of peasant, those whose words had been taken as

    commands and those whose words had been essentially unutterable even when

    voiced. For actions to be just, Robespierre thought, they should get past the project of

    being just to individuals and should treat justice as a fully transcendental principle.The capacity for individual action should be redistributed by and through society, not

    situated and explained by multiplying descriptions of individual circumstances. For

    Robespierre, that is, the individual aspect of morality should be stripped away,

    rescuing Rousseaus solitary from the contradiction between his conscience and the

    way his actions must look to other people. Robespierre carried the Confessions at his

    breast because he took it to resolve the individual into the transcendental, to make it

    possible for individuals to make claims that did not rest on their individuality.

    In claiming this particular line of influence for Rousseau, I mean to call

    attention to the restrictive effect that his account and that of figures like Robespierre

    had on the conception of character. For if Lukacs stresses the importance of the

    historical novel with its representation of dialogue, its understanding of classconsciousness, and its ability to introduce historical personages while saying and you

    are there, Dickenss novel understands historical consciousness differently. Against a

    history that hurts, he sets a history that causes pain by rendering its principal

    characters ineffectual. The pattern is apparent in what can seem the most bourgeois

    aspects of the novel its attention to the wastefulness of having a trained physician like

    Alexandre Manette compulsively make shoes to no apparent purpose, its registration

    that Darnays repudiation of his fathers and uncles deeds counts for nothing. Most

    interestingly, Dickens shows that understanding action under the sign of futility is by

    no means an exclusively Revolutionary propensity. The depiction of ostentatiously

    ineffectual action developed in Manettes imprisonment under the old regime, and itwas launched in rather milder circumstances in the original trial scene in England, in

    which Dickens brings out a basic feature of the legal systemthat the law elicits from

    witnesses statements that they do not intend to make. In the cases of Cly and Barsad,

    spies and witnesses for hire, poetic justice so closely approximates the description of

    the mechanics of justice that we scarcely notice this feature of the law. It seems

    entirely right that they should not be able to deliver on their intention to frame Darnay

    as a spy against England. But Dickens also captures the negative side of the process in

    which individual speech is subjected to the transcendentalizing pressure of the law,

    with its constant directives that one speak its language and put the words the prisoner

    in the mouth of someone wanting to identify Darnay as the gentleman. Lucie Manette,

    with her forehead ... strikingly expressive of an engrossing terror and compassion thatsaw nothing but the peril of the accused (72) gives every evidence of wishing to

    6

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    7/14

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    8/14

    crucial for helping to explain the difference between Lukacss understanding of the

    historical novel and Dickenss. It is central to Lukacss understanding of the historical

    novel that it developed alongside modern armies that specifically designated certain

    individuals to do the fighting and absorb the blows on behalf of their societies (and

    also that the members of those armies continually had to come into contact with alien

    societies because of the armies need for constant provisioning). Indeed, Lukacssunderstanding of the social and political participates in the Enlightenment rationalism

    of Marxist thought, which imagines that the conception of classes can continually

    ground its immateriality in economic justification. For Dickens, on the other hand,

    terrorism involves eroding the distinction between soldier and civilian, seeing that

    individuals are continually being absorbed into classes and class-based families that

    are not just families but races.

    Moreover, the relation between individuals and their virtual existences need

    never be any more exact or accurate than that between women and their reputations in

    Rousseau. In our own nearly present moment, we can see the workings of randomly

    assigned group identities in the bombings in New York on September 11, 2001, and inMadrid on March 11 ,2004. People at work, people going to work become targets not

    because they are policy makers but because it does not matter that they are not. People

    at work, people going to work become targets as Americans or as Spaniards whether

    or not they are Americans or Spaniards. (And in the process those who had remained

    foreigners effectively do become Americans or Spaniards, awarded a kind of non-

    native and non-naturalized citizenship by the place of their death or injury. As many

    people around the world briefly said after September 11, 2001, we are all Americans.

    As one foreign-born woman who had lived in Spain for years put it to a reporter for

    Madrids El Pais, she and her family were finally virtually naturalized; the rescue

    workers treated us just like Spaniards.)

    The process that I am identifying as terrorism is no respecter of persons andtheir specializations and particular capacities and beliefs. Moreover, I think that

    Dickenss insight into terrorism was at stake when he reported to Forster that he was

    writing A Tale of Two Cities so as to reveal character by the story itself rather than by

    dialogue. For Dickens imagines that the story itself does not just constitute a backdrop

    against which to show what McWilliams calls the truly virtuous man. Rather, he

    shows the story itself radically altering character. Nowhere is this process more

    apparent than in the case of Sydney Carton, who remains a stealth hero for an

    extraordinarily long time, because nothing in his past behavior leads anyone to

    imagine that he will be a force for good. His virtue is awarded to him by the plot--and

    this is true to such an extent that it does not seem a failing in Charles Darnay that hedoesnt often think of Carton or think much of him when he does. If Lucie hears

    Darnays speaking of Sydney Carton as a problem of carelessness and recklessness

    (207)and beseeches him to give Carton more consideration and respect (208),

    Dickens has already underscored the plausibility of thinking of Cartons as a wasted

    life: He spoke of him, in short, not bitterly or meaning to bear hard upon him, but as

    anybody might who saw him as he showed himself (207). And if Darnay accedes to

    Lucies request and still does not think of Carton during his feverish reflections in the

    hours when he thinks of himself as a dedicated sacrifice to the Guillotine, Dickens

    announces that fact only to explain that his mind was so full of the others, that he

    never once thought of him (341).

    Indeed, were it not for the insistence of the plot, Dickenss readers would havescarcely any reason to expect much from Carton. For while Dickens deploys the

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    9/14

    language of Christian sacrifice to describe Cartons action, so little has Carton

    reformed his general behavior that it would be laughable to describe him as a male

    Mary Magdalen. Dickens goes to great lengths to characterize Cartons drinking as

    past anything that we can imagine in modern times, and he underscores Cartons

    alcoholism by noting how exceptional it was for him to be sober in his last hours of

    freedom (For the first time in many years, he had no strong drink, 331.) Moreover,Dickens makes sure that we dont think of Cartons drinking as an expression of

    charming sociability. He may be hard-working (laboring mightily in his water-soaked

    turban in Stryvers legal chambers), but hes also a nasty drunk, one who insists on

    dining and drinking with the man hes just helped to acquit only to announce to his

    face that he doesnt like him.

    I shall have more to say about Sydney Carton later, but for now I would

    merely like to insist on the aptness of Dickenss announcement that the characters of

    A Tale of Two Cities are developed by the story itself rather than by dialogue. For I

    take Dickens here to be insisting on a new way of understanding actions and their

    agents relation to them in the moral universe that he is discovering. If Franco Morettihas argued that attending to more literature and more globally defined literature will

    help us see that the psychological novel is less important than the novel of action, A

    Tale of Two Cities almost makes us want to identify a third sort of novel one with

    precious little psychology or action. Darnay cannot do what he means to do that is,

    fully to renounce his patrimony and to distance himself from both his ancestral

    holdings and his fathers and uncles deeds. Lucie cannot do what she clearly means

    to do to testify in favor of Darnay. And their inability to deliver on their own wishes

    finds extreme expression in Dr. Manettes fugue states. For if Lucie repeatedly faints

    (when Darnays fate is being debated in his English trial and when he is arrested after

    his earlier release from the Bastille), her father is more often and more seriously

    overborne by the world.In Dr. Manettes fugue states, we see the triumph of Dickenss story itself,

    which has deprived Manette of a great deal of meaningful dialogue and set him to

    work with only occasional effectiveness. Lucie may seem to reprise the swoons of

    sentimentalism, but I take Manettes inability to apprehend his circumstances to

    represent something more than just an intensification of sentimentalism that makes

    trauma look like the only available response of a good man to massively evil times.

    For Manette is the only one in the novel who seems ever to approach an

    understanding of the way in which his circumstances really cannot be described as

    local. Lucie Manette fille may speak the languages of the two cities that the novel

    features, but only Alexandre Manette seems almost to perceive the experiences of onecity in terms of the other. He hears Darnays story of writings found hidden in the

    Tower of London and seems almost to connect them with the writings that he had left

    in 105 North Tower of the Bastille. He sees the young Charles Darnays face and

    chooses not to know his name, because he seems almost to connect this young man in

    London with a face or faces he has seen in France.

    In putting things this way, I have called attention to matters that we might

    explain away as Dickenss effort to foreshadow the complications that he intends to

    unfold later in the novel. To look more carefully at these episodes is to see that our

    sense that Manette heard of the writings discovered in the London prison and thought

    of his own writings in the Paris prison and that Manette saw Darnay and thought of

    the twin brothers dEvremonde is our own back-formation from the outcome of theplot. In our back-formation, Manette can seem to have known all along how the

    9

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    10/14

    distantly separated elements of his experience fit together, can seem to have actively

    colluded in suppressing his own knowledge. And Charles Darnay himself certainly

    fosters that impression in crediting Manette with having known all along that his

    daughter was marrying the scion of a family whose actions he has completely

    condemned.. Yet the limitations of that eminently plausible line of thought become

    apparent when we encounter Manettes indignant objection to the idea that he has,along with the Defarges, provided testimony against his son-in-law. If we explain the

    problem away by treating Manettes traumatic disconnection as just another instance

    of the insanity ploy in literature, I think, we miss something rather more important

    that Manette is put in the position of being a kind of idiot savant who can register

    certain connections in much the same way that geiger counters, children, and animals

    are said to identify otherwise imperceptible things. Even as we wonder if Manette

    really knew that Charles Darnay was an Evremonde on the basis of his recollection of

    how Charless father and uncle looked two decades earlier, we can see that the

    brilliance of Dickenss decision to make Darnay and Carton resemble one another lies

    here in the depiction of the difficulty of linking morality with claims about accuracy

    of ones perceptions of the world.

    Indeed, though the plot often encourages us to think of Darnay and Carton as

    dead-ringers for one another, Dickens also undercuts the force of that resemblance.

    Carton, drunkenly reporting to Darnay that he doesnt like him, says that he begin[s]

    to think [they] are not much alike in any particular (90) and thus raises the possibility

    that even the observed resemblance is a lawyers ploy. Stryver, as you recall,

    congratulates Carton after Darnays acquittal and particularly asks how in the world

    Carton came up with the idea that he and Darnay resembled one another. (That was a

    rare point, Sydney, that you brought to bear upon the identification. How did you

    come by it? When did it strike you? 94) Carton, in calling attention to the resemblance

    between himself and Darnay, had sought to smash this witness {John Barsad] like acrockery vessel, and shiver his part of the case to useless lumber (82) and to secure his

    and Stryvers clients acquittal by impugning the reliability of the witnesss

    identification. Moreover, Dickens is careful to avoid treating the resemblance as a

    simple perceptual fact. For though not only the witness but everybody present was

    surprised by the likeness when they were thus brought into comparison (81), Dickens

    almost immediately takes pains to blur the resemblance and to suggest that it partially

    resulted from Cartons abilities as an actor. Thus, Carton removes his wig so the

    likeness [becomes] much more remarkable (82). He then resumes expressions more

    characteristic of himself, and the spectators question the resemblance: Something

    especially reckless in his demeanour not only gave him a disreputable look, but so

    diminished the strong resemblance he undoubtedly bore to the prisoner (which hismomentary earnestness, when they were compared together, had strengthened), that

    many of the lookers-on, taking note of him now, said to one another they would

    hardly have thought the two were so alike (83). And even in Cartons final hours of

    freedom, the likeness between him and Evremonde remains a subject of debate.

    Although Madame Defarge starts at the sight of him, taking him for Evremonde, other

    people in the wine shop minimize the resemblance and chalk her perception up to her

    intense anticipation of seeing Evremondes face at the Guillotine.

    Now I obviously dont mean to say that Darnay and Carton dont bear any

    physical resemblance to one another. I mean, instead, to suggest that Dickens treats

    this resemblance as one that waxes and wanes and is more available to some peoplethan to others. And I mean as well to call attention to a certain improbability of

    10

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    11/14

    Cartons having noticed the resemblance and having commented on it. Its improbable

    for Carton to make the identification because it tends to run counter to ways in which

    people recognize themselves; most people, I think, tend to marvel at the various

    likenesses that other people see between them and others. But even if you leave my

    law of experience to the side, the distinctiveness and improbability of Cartons

    perception of himself in another emerges in the fact that other characters arentregularly looking at other people and thinking that they resemble them. (While we

    hear that Lucies mother and Lucie and Lucie fille all merge in a blur of blonde hair,

    we dont encounter a moment in which either Lucie or her daughter talks about their

    resemblance to one another.) Indeed, as I pointed out earlier, most characters in the

    novel even and especially those who have replicated themselves by means of

    pseudonyms and new identities spend a great deal of time trying to separate

    themselves from the people they are said to resemble. Thus, Darnays insistence that

    he is not an emigrant, however much he might be said to resemble one, and that he is

    no longer an Evremonde, however much he might be said to resemble one.

    Virtual resemblance, in other words, overrides actual resemblance. WhatDarnay comes to learn is that it doesnt matter to his executioners that he doesnt

    subscribe to his fathers and his uncles views and doesnt endorse their behavior. He

    finally fully comprehended that no personal influence [even from his father in-law,

    whom the Revolutionaries revered] could possibly save him, that he was virtually

    sentenced by the millions, and that units could avail him nothing (339) He has been

    condemned on account of what other characters in the novel refer to as the work of a

    bad race. Moreover, if we think back to Evremondes final encounter with his uncle

    (130), we realize that he himself had spoken as if he were implicated in his forebears

    crimes. We [emphasis mine], he says, did a world of wrong (128). The point that I

    would like to emphasize here is that it is not merely Revolutionary Terror and Therese

    Defarge that racialize families and treat them virtually and by the millions. Instead,that tendency has been present from very early in the story in the curse of the young

    man who was, or would have been, Therese Defarges uncle to the last of [that] bad

    race (320) through Darnays use of the plural when he would like to use the singular

    and through his acceptance of the notion of the curse: There is a curse on [this

    property], and on all this land (129).

    What Dickens brings out with this language is that individuals are no longer

    members of families conceived as domestic units. Rather, families are races. And the

    practical consequence of a situation in which individuals are their families and their

    races is that individual identity and individual responsibility are rendered effectively

    indeterminable and irrelevant. If the Jacquerie recognize that it is a political gesture toshow that they are as indistinguishable from one another as the aristocrats have treated

    them to be, the racialization of identity pervades A Tale of Two Cities and makes it

    difficult for individuals to recognize both others and themselves. Anyone who has

    read even a few of Dickenss novels might take this pattern to be merely another

    instance of Dickenss interest in disguised identities yet one more case of someone

    hiding his fortune or having his origins hidden from him. Yet I cannot think of

    another Dickens novel in which individual identities are so frequently and insistently

    obscured. Dr.Manette is discovered under another name ; Darnays identity as

    Evremonde is concealed from most of the characters during most of the action of the

    novel. And these are just two of the many cases that we might instance in support of

    Dickenss early observation in the novel of the wonderful fact to reflect upon, that

    11

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    12/14

    every human creature is constituted to be that profound secret and mystery to every

    other (21).

    The moral challenge of what I earlier identified as the logic of terror and what

    I am now describing as the racialization of action is that individuals are continually in

    the position of wondering Did I do it? Am I responsible for the wrongs I see around

    me? Lukacss reading suggests that Dickens idealizes the bourgeois family as a way

    of establishing a restricted domestic world in which people can know one another and

    themselves and can know that they are doing well by them. And, indeed, Darnays

    uncle advanced his own version of that view when he taunted Darnay with his

    knowledge of his nephews new connections: A Doctor with a daughter. Yes. So

    commences the new philosophy! (130). If the Marquis all but says that substituting

    new families for old ones doesnt sound much like a philosophic innovation, I think

    that Dickens for all his sentiment and sentimentality about families actually agrees

    with that view in A Tale of Two Cities.

    Indeed, I think that we have scarcely begun to take the measure of Dickenss

    effort to come to terms with a new philosophy of moral action in modernity. For asDickens disables family members of families old and new, bad and good and prevents

    them from taking effectual action, he registers the difficulties that individuals have in

    being moral agents in the modern world. Moreover and this is where Lukacs would

    particularly differ from him he appears to reject the idea that recognizing ones

    solidarity with ones class enables one to see ones class as a plausible author of

    actions. Instead, Dickens has recourse to an entirely archaic plot and to an entirely

    modern solution.

    The entirely archaic plot that I think Dickens had in mind is that of Oedipus

    Tyrranos, in which a baby is transported from Thebes to Corinth and then as a man

    transports himself back to Thebes, in which he learns that there is a curse on the landbecause of an unpunished murder, in which he curses the killer, and in which he

    learns that he himself is the polluter of Thebes whom he has cursed because he had

    killed a man whom he now recognizes to be his father. I dont mean to claim that

    Dickens builds the story of Oedipus into his novel in the same way that Fielding

    builds it into Tom Jones, but I want to suggest that key elements of Dickenss novel

    powerfully echoand then adapt--the moral conundra that Sophocless play poses. In

    both Sophocless hands and Dickenss, there is one tale for two cities, and characters

    cannot outrun their actions by changing their locations. In both works, characters only

    understand their own actions and situations after the fact, and, indeed, it seems

    necessary in both to have oracles to alert characters to their personal connection with

    a general problem. (Think of the spiritual revelations and prophecies that Dickensmentions in the third paragraph of the novel.)

    The story of Oedipus, dispersed over two cities and over the time from

    Oedipuss birth to his adulthood, finally returns to him as his individual story. His

    actions have had widespread consequences; he has saved Thebes from the Sphinx,

    after all, by solving a notorious riddle (What has one voice and moves on four legs,

    then two, then three). He has also inadvertently brought on a widespread miasma by

    having killed Laius. Yet the breathtaking quality of the tragedy lies in the sudden

    recognition that he was himself the author of all the results that he curses, that he who

    had thought himself a virtuous man now thinks of himself as evil. In that sense,

    Oedipuss story may seem to rehearse and endorse the idea that moral action issupremely individual. The miasma of the city, in other words, comes to look like a

    12

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    13/14

    mistakenly general effect that punishes everyone who seems like a man as we

    recognize men from the Sphinxs various different descriptions. The drama can

    conclude when moral responsibility is properly localized in an individual, and he who

    has recognized man in general is able to recognize his own situation as an individual

    one. Indeed, that reading of the play has regularly funded the psychoanalytic use of

    the Oedipus story that treats it as a matter of individual disavowal and recognition.

    A Dickensian reading of the Oedipus story would, I think, share the tragedys

    account of the generality of miasma, but would offer a strikingly different route to its

    dissipation. Whereas Sophocles hangs the entire play on imagining that all the diffuse

    consequences of Oedipuss actions can be localized in Oedipuss finally recognizing

    himself as the unique author of his and his citys sufferings, Dickens produces a

    remarkably unindividual indeed, almost impersonal account of moral action. The

    crucial moment of recognition for Oedipus comes when he realizes that Jocasta was

    mistaken in comforting him when she had tried to reassure him that he couldnt

    possibly have killed Laius because Laius had been killed by robbers, and one cannot

    be many. But Carton sees that the solution to at least a portion of the curse on the landis to take advantage of a confusion between the individual and the many that has

    become ineluctable. Sidney Carton may be, like Oedipus, a man who solves riddles,

    but it is crucial to A Tale of Two Cities that they should remain other peoples riddles.

    If the Terror treats individuals as families and the past of ones father and uncle as

    ones own present, if Alexandre Manette and Lucie Manette Darnay seem to try to

    reclaim individuals for their current and chosen families, the plot awards its prize

    neither to the generalized terroristic approach nor to the retreat into bourgeois

    domesticity. Rather, Sidney Carton ends the novel heroically because he manages to

    solve the same riddle twice, first in the courtroom in which he recognizes himself in

    another man, then in France when he again recognizes himself in another man and

    chooses that other man over himself.If we might be inclined to describe Cartons willingness to die as a gesture of

    supreme altruism, however, we would leave ourselves very hard pressed to explain his

    and the novels final words: It is a far, far better thing that I do, than I have ever done;

    it is a far, far better rest that I go to than I have ever known (367). These lines, among

    the most frequently quoted in all of English literature, have been disparaged as

    sentimental. Yet sentimental is, I think, precisely what they are not. Sidney Carton

    here speaks the language of what we have come to know as that of the personal best,

    the language in which you can monitor your own performance at running or jumping

    or taking standardized tests and think less about whether you are good or evil than

    about whether you have done better than you did before. It is the language not ofvirtuous character but of reason as befits a man who does not know how to live his

    life well but does know how to reason, calculate, and solve riddles.

    To put the matter in this way is to see the extent to which Sidney Carton

    represents the very type of a character that Dickens had frequently disparaged the

    Benthamite man. He makes choices by calculating the general utility of his actions,

    and morals are for him, as Bentham insisted they should be, a science. He can choose

    against himself because he sees that a life that Lucie loves is more valuable than his.

    He can perform an extraordinarily virtuous action without being a virtuous man

    because his moral project does not involve trying to recover a past to be recognized.

    Rather, his virtue is the virtue of the professional, the man who can help others more

    easily than he can help himself and who is able to unriddle the miasma of historicalwrong not by retracing and redressing it but by developing a course of action where

    13

  • 7/28/2019 Ferguson_Frances - Georg Lukacs

    14/14

    no other character can. The terror of A Tale of Two Cities is the terror of mass society

    in which virtuous individuals seem deprived of the possibility of action because they

    do not know how to make their individual goodness count for anything. The response

    of Sydney Carton is to give himself and other people reasons for goodness and to see

    that virtuous action can take its impetus from reconceiving peoples just deserts

    outside of their own pasts and an infinite project of self-examination and self-discovery.

    14