hoskins 2010 paper

Upload: wuwpes

Post on 30-May-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    1/31

    Fair play, political obligation, and punishment.

    Zach Hoskins

    DRAFT; Submitted Jan. 22, 2010,

    for the Political Theory Workshop, Washington University in St. Louis

    I. Introduction.

    Since H. L. A. Hart famously distinguished three different questions of legal punishment1

    why should we punish, who may we punish, and how much may we punish responses to

    this disaggregation strategy have been mixed. Some have argued that it is ad hoc, and that Harts

    appeal to consequentialist considerations in answering the first question and retributivist

    considerations in answering the second and third creates a dialectic instability in his view. Others

    have endorsed the disaggregation strategy but have argued that the questions should be

    structured somewhat differently. Hart indicates that the answer to why should we punish, which

    he calls punishments general justifying aim, must be determined first, and that once this aim is

    known, it is then left to decide (based on distinct considerations) who may properly be punished,

    and how severely. Since the publication of Harts account, however, scholars have argued that a

    normatively prior question to punishments general justifying aim is whether the practice itself is

    morally permissible; that is, does the practice of punishmentper se violate the rights of the

    1 Throughout this chapter, I use punishment to refer to the legal institution of punishment. For an interesting

    discussion of nonlegal instances of punishment, and a critique of accounts (such as mine) that focus on legalpunishment, see Leo Zaibert,Punishment and Retribution (Aldershot, U.K.: Ashgate Publishing, 2006).

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    2/31

    criminal wrongdoers who are punished?2 On this view, defenders of punishment must first

    explain why a communitys political authority is justified in treating some of its citizens in

    ways that it would be clearly wrong to treat others.3 I refer to this throughout as the question of

    punishments presumptive permissibility. If punishment is not even presumptively permissible,

    then appeal to whatever positive justifying aims will be insufficient to justify the practice.

    In this paper, I offer a defense of punishments presumptive permissibility. My account is

    a version of the fair play view, according to which, briefly, the permissibility of punishment

    derives from reciprocal obligations shared by members of a political community, here

    understood as a mutually beneficial, cooperative social venture. Mine is a nonstandard fair play

    account, however, in that most fair play accounts aspire to offer unified theories of punishment

    that is, they employ considerations of fair play to ground not only punishments presumptive

    permissibility, but also its positive justification as well as sentencing guidance. By contrast, my

    fair play view is more modest; it seeks only to provide an answer to the presumptive

    permissibility question. I contend that in this context, modesty is a virtue. Because my account

    offers only an answer to the permissibility question, but not to the positive aim question or to

    questions of how we may punish, it avoids certain powerful objections that have been raised

    against standard articulations of the fair play view. Whats more, as I argue below, my focus on

    only the permissibility question is not ad hoc; to the contrary, a closer examination of the fair

    play views evolution from a theory of political obligation to a defense of punishment indicates

    2 C.f., K. G. Armstrong, The Retributivist Hits Back, in H. B. Acton, ed., The Philosophy of Punishment(London:

    Macmillan, 1969), p. 141; and Matt Matravers,Justice and Punishment(Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press,2000). Matravers writes that punishment theory must concern itself with the morality of attaching the threat of

    sanctions to rules (as well [as] the morality of imposing those sanctions on particular people). And whilst it seemsplausible to think that the point of threatening sanctions must have something to do with preventing offending ,

    that is not the same as arguing that preventing offending through the threat and imposing of sanctions is morally

    permissible p. 7. Note also the distinction between the moral permissibility question and the who may we

    punish? question: The answer to the latter question might be, e.g., only those culpable for criminal wrongdoing,

    but this answer would, in itself, say nothing about whypunishment, i.e., the infliction of intentional harm, is a

    morally permissible response to criminal wrongdoing.3 David Boonin, The Problem of Punishment(New York City: Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 29.

    2

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    3/31

    that there are good reasons to expect that it is suitable as an answer only to the presumptive

    permissibility question. That is, there are good reasons to expect punishments positive

    justification and the constraints on how it is administered in particular cases to be based on

    distinct considerations.

    In what follows, I first lay out in more detail the standard articulation of the fair play

    view. I consider how the view, first offered as an account of political obligation, has been

    extended to justify punishment, and why this justification ultimately fails. Next, I develop my

    alternative version of the fair play view, on which the defense of punishments presumptive

    permissibility follows more straightforwardly from fair plays answer to the political obligation

    question. I contend that my version of the view fares better than standard articulations on a

    number of counts. Finally, I address certain objections to my view, one of which aims at my

    attempt to use the resources of political obligation in my defense of punishment, and others that

    aim at the fair play account of political obligation itself and thus threaten my defense of

    punishment as well.

    II. The standard fair play account and its drawbacks.

    According to the fair play account, a political community can be understood as a

    cooperative venture in which each member benefits when there is general compliance with the

    rules governing the venture. The fact that each member benefits from the compliance of other

    members generates an obligation to reciprocate by similarly complying. Thus Hart wrote:

    [W]hen a number of persons conduct any joint enterprise

    according to rules and thus restrict their liberty, those who havesubmitted to these restrictions when required have a right to a

    3

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    4/31

    similar submission from those who have benefited by their

    submission.4

    Similarly, Rawls elaborated the view this way:

    Suppose there is a mutually beneficial and just scheme of socialcooperation, and that the advantages it yields can only be obtained

    if everyone, or nearly everyone, cooperates. Suppose further thatcooperation requires a certain sacrifice from each person, or at

    least involves a certain restriction of his liberty. Suppose finally

    that the benefits produced by cooperation are, up to a certain point,free: that is, the scheme of cooperation is unstable in the sense that

    if any one person knows that all (or nearly all) of the others will

    continue to do their part, he will still be able to share a gain fromthe scheme even if he does not do his part. Under these conditions

    a person who has accepted the benefits of the scheme is bound by a

    duty of fair play to do his part and not to take advantage of the freebenefits by not cooperating.5

    As espoused by Hart and Rawls, the fair play view grounded a reciprocal obligation to

    comply with the rules of a mutually beneficial political community. It said nothing about what

    would be a justified response to those who failed to meet this obligation. Several theorists of

    punishment, however, have used the principle of fair play espoused by Hart and Rawls as their

    foundation in developing a defense of the practice of punishment. The crucial claim for

    extending the fair play view to justify punishment is that when a member of the community

    chooses not to comply with the communitys laws, she takes an unfair advantage relative to her

    fellow community members. That is, she unfairly benefits twice: Like everyone, she reaps the

    benefits that general compliance with the law makes possible, but she additionally benefits in

    that she, unlike her fellow community members, doesnt constrain her behavior in compliance.

    Typically, then, on fair play accounts the offender is portrayed as a free rider, and punishment is

    defended as a means of removing the offenders unfair advantage by imposing a burden on the

    4 H. L. A. Hart, Are There Any Natural Rights? The Philosophical Review 64:4 (April 1955): 175-91, reprinted in

    Jeremy Waldron, ed., Theories of Rights (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 1984), on p. 85.5 John Rawls, Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play, in S. Hook, ed.,Law and Philosophy: A Symposium

    (New York City: New York University Press, 1964), pp. 9-10.

    4

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    5/31

    offender proportionate to the additional benefit she unfairly gained through her crime. As

    Herbert Morris writes, Justice that is, punishing such individuals restores the equilibrium

    of benefits and burdens by taking from the individual what he owes, that is, exacting the debt.6

    The standard articulation of the fair play view of punishment is inadequate in two key

    respects: The first is that the fair play view misconstrues, at least in many cases, what makes a

    criminal act worthy of punishment, or as Antony Duff writes, it offers a distorted picture of the

    punishment-deserving character of crime.7 That is, we tend to think that a person who has, for

    instance, tortured someone should be punished not because she has gained an unfair advantage

    over other members of the community generally, but rather because of the heinous moral wrong

    she has committed against her victim. In other words, we do not typically think of serious mala

    in se crimes such as torture, murder, or rape as primarily matters of free riding.

    The second deficiency of standard fair play accounts involves the specification of the

    offenders unfair benefit. The challenge for advocates of this view has been to determine exactly

    what added benefit, what unfair advantage, the criminal gains through commission of the crime,

    and then how punishment can be seen to remove this benefit. In what follows, I consider three

    prominent candidates for the benefit an offender unfairly gains. Each option ultimately fails,

    either directly, because it is implausible in its own right, or indirectly, because it implies

    counterintuitive conclusions regarding appropriate sentencing. The failure of these attempts is

    evidence, as I contend below, that there is no benefit that an offender gains through her crime

    such that punishment is an appropriate means of removing it. Thus if the fair play account of

    6 Herbert Morris, Persons and Punishment,Monist52 (1968): 475-501; on p. 478. For other notable elaborations

    of the fair play view, see Jeffrie Murphy, Three Mistakes about Retributivism,Analysis 31 (1971): 166-9; Michael

    Davis, How to Make the Punishment Fit the Crime,Ethics 93 (1983): 726-52, and Criminal Desert and Unfair

    Advantage: Whats the Connection?Law and Philosophy 12 (1993): 133-56; George Sher,Desert(Princeton, N.J.:

    Princeton University Press, 1989); and Richard Dagger, Playing Fair with Punishment,Ethics 103 (April 1993):

    473-88, and Punishment as Fair Play,Res Publica 14 (2008): 259-75.7 R. A. Duff,Punishment, Communication, and Community (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 22.

    5

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    6/31

    political obligation is to ground a defense of punishment, it must do so in some different way.

    Developing such an alternative account is my task in the section III.

    Before considering the three candidate benefits, however, its worth distinguishing two

    types of benefits that are notintended by any of the fair play advocates. First, the benefit gained

    by an offender is not characterized as a moral benefit. M. Margaret Falls criticizes the fair play

    view as being incompatible with the tradition that says willing the moral good is the highest

    human good and therefore doing evil harms the evildoer.8 I think its fair to say, however, that

    the fair play view operates within a tradition that recognizes a distinction between moral and

    prudential benefit, which believes that the latter does not necessarily collapse into the former,

    and which holds that an offender gains someprudentialbenefit through her crime.9 Second, the

    benefit gained by the criminal is explicitly not characterized as the material spoils of her crime.

    Thus, the relevant benefit unfairly gained by, say, the burglar is not the actual money or property

    that she steals, nor is the tax evaders relevant benefit the tax money she doesnt pay. If the

    benefit were characterized as the material gain from the crime, then removing this benefit would

    seem to be a matter merely ofcompensatingthe victim(s); punishment, understood as the

    intentional imposition of hard treatment, would not seem necessary. For fair play defenders of

    punishment, therefore, it is crucial that the unfairly gained benefit is something distinct from the

    ill-gotten material gains.

    How, then, should we understand this unfairly gained benefit, or advantage, of the

    criminal? Typically, the benefit is characterized as some measure of freedom; specifically, most

    8 M. Margaret Falls, Retribution, Reciprocity, and Respect for Persons,Law and Philosophy 6:1 (1987): 25-51, on

    p. 31.9 Of course, ifits true that what is prudentially good for us reduces to what is morally good for us, or even if any

    ostensible prudential benefit a criminal gains would be outweighed by the moral harm so that the criminal should be

    understood as harming herself all things considered, this will only support my conclusion below: that the fair play

    view cannot demonstrate an advantage that the criminal unfairly gains over others that is appropriately removed by

    punishment.

    6

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    7/31

    fair play accounts hold that the offender gains freedom from the burden of self-constraint that

    others accept in complying with the law. This burden could be fleshed out in two distinct ways:

    First, it could be the burden others accept in complying with the particular law that the offender

    violates. Second, it could be the burden others accept in complying with the law in general. Both

    have generated objections. According to the first option, the offender gains the unfair advantage

    of not having to constrain herself to comply with the particular law at issue. But many critics

    have noted that compliance with the law is in many cases no significant burden, and perhaps no

    burden at all, for most citizens. In fact, compliance appears to be least burdensome to most of us

    in cases where the law prohibits the most egregious offenses (e.g., murder, rape, armed robbery,

    etc.). This is because most of us are not tempted to commit such offenses anyway, and so

    compliance with the laws prohibiting such offenses does not require some sort of burdensome

    self-constraint. On the other hand, because many of us may feel comparatively more tempted, on

    occasion, to cheat on our taxes, jaywalk, drive in excess of the speed limit, etc., we will therefore

    tend to regard compliance with prohibitions of these less serious violations as comparatively

    more burdensome. Notice, then, that if punishment is permissible as a means of removing the

    unfair advantage the offender gains in freeing herself from the burden of compliance, it appears

    that the relatively more severe punishments will be permissible in response to the relatively less

    serious violations, given that most of us will tend to find compliance with these lesser

    prohibitions more burdensome than compliance with the more serious ones. The notion that tax

    evasion, or even jaywalking, might merit a more severe punishment than murder is obviously

    deeply counterintuitive. Thus it appears that the offenders unfairly gained benefit, if there is

    one, is not freedom from the burden of complying with the particular law that she violates.

    7

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    8/31

    A second option is that the offender gains freedom from the burden of compliance, not

    with the particular law violated but rather with the law in general. Thus a murderer rejects a

    burden of self-constraint that others accept, but the burden is not compliance with the law

    prohibiting murder (most of us do not feel constrained by such compliance) but rather

    compliance with the law generally. This general compliance, Richard Dagger writes, is a genuine

    burden: there are times for almost all of us when we would like to have the best of both worlds

    that is, the freedom we enjoy under the rule of law plus freedom from the burden of obeying

    laws.10This route, however, appears to lead to the objection that all offenses become, for the

    purposes of punishment, the same offense. That is, a murderers punishable offense and a tax

    cheats punishable offense appear the same: Each has failed to comply with the rule of law

    generally while benefiting from the general compliance of others. If the punishable offense is the

    same, however, then the two cases appear to warrant equal punishments, and as before, this will

    strike most of us as counterintuitive.11 That the general-compliance account generates such

    counterintuitive conclusions is strong evidence that the unfair advantage gained by the offender,

    the advantage to be removed via punishment, is not freedom from the burden of compliance with

    the law in general.12

    A third possibility for characterizing what the offender unfairly gains from her crime is

    offered by George Sher. On Shers account, the offender gains an extra measure of freedom, not

    from the burden of self-constraint, but rather from the demands of the prohibition he violates. 13

    He continues:

    Because others take that prohibition seriously, they lack a similar

    liberty. And as the strength of the prohibition increases, so too

    10 Dagger, Playing Fair with Punishment, p. 483.11 This objection is pressed by Boonin, The Problem of Punishment, pp. 125-6.12 Dagger offers a fuller defense of his view in a more recent paper, Punishment as Fair Play, which I discuss at

    length below.13 Sher,Desert, p. 82.

    8

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    9/31

    does the freedom from it which its violation entails. Thus even if

    the murderer and the tax evader do succumb to equally strong

    impulses, their gains in freedom are far from equal.14

    Shers account, unlike the particular- and general-compliance views discussed above,

    does not depend on the claim that compliance with laws typically represents a burden. It thus

    avoids the counterintuitive sentencing implications that appear to beset the other two views. But

    this account faces its own problems specifically, its not clear on his account in what sense the

    offender, through his commission of the crime,gains freedom from the moral prohibition. As

    David Dolinko points out, the criminal does not so muchgain freedom from the prohibition as

    exhibita freedom that he already had he must have been free from the prohibition even

    before his lawless act (or he could not have committed it!), and presumably, many law-abiding

    citizens are equally free (in this sense) to violate the prohibition.15 It thus appears that

    whatever benefit the offender may gain through her crime, if any, it is not freedom from the

    moral prohibition she violates.

    If the relevant benefit that an offender unfairly gains is not any of these types of freedom

    freedom from the burden of complying with the particular law, or from the burden of

    complying with the law in general, or from the demands of the moral prohibition then what

    else might constitute her unfair advantage? There certainly may be other things that an offender

    gains through her commission of a crime. For instance, Jean Hamptons expressive retributivism

    holds that wrongful acts convey and work to effect the wrongdoers superior importance

    relative to the victim understood as an individual or as a class of individuals.16 Thus we might

    follow Hampton in regarding the offender as gaining a sense of, and perhaps a realization of,

    14 Ibid.15 David Dolinko, Some Thoughts about Retributivism,Ethics 101:3 (April 1991): 537-59, on p. 547.16 Jean Hampton, The Intrinsic Worth of Persons: Contractarianism in Moral and Political Philosophy, ed. Daniel

    Farnham (New York City: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 131. See also Hampton, A New Theory of

    Retribution, inLiability and Responsibility, eds. C. Morris and R. Frey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

    1991), pp. 377-414.

    9

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    10/31

    relative superiority. Hamptons account is explicitly not a fair play account, however, as this

    ostensible benefit to the offender, the superiority that the wrongful act expresses and seeks to

    manifest, is a superiority to the particular victim(s), not to other, law abiding community

    members generally. For purposes of the fair play account, the punishable benefit must be

    something that the offender gains relative to the community in general, as a result of others

    compliance and her own noncompliance; that is, the benefit must be a result of her free riding.

    And insofar as punishment is justified as a means of removing the unfair advantage, this

    advantage must either be commensurate with the gravity of the crime or else risk running afoul

    of our deeply held intuitions regarding proportionality of punishment. Unfortunately for

    advocates of the standard fair play account, there just doesnt appear to be any unfair advantage

    that all criminals gain, in proportion to the seriousness of their crimes, over other, law abiding

    community members.

    Dagger has rearticulated, and further developed, his view in a recent article titled

    Punishment and Fair Play.17Here he maintains that all crimes are indeed crimes of unfairness,

    but he contends that they may be unfair not only in the sense of yielding unfair benefits, but also

    in undermining the political order. If we conceive of a political community as a fair cooperative

    practice whose members have equal standing, Dagger contends, then considerations of

    unfairness can also justify the conclusion that some offenses are more serious violations of equal

    standing and fair play than others.18 For instance, he writes:

    The tax evader takes advantage of many people millions ofthem in many cases but her offense typically does not make it

    difficult for them to continue doing their part in the cooperative

    practice. With the rapist, the murderer, and the batterer, however,the offender has done something that makes it difficult or even

    impossible for his victim to contribute further to the ongoing

    17 Supra note 6.18 Ibid., p. 270.

    10

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    11/31

    cooperation. He has offended against the interests and integrity of

    his victim, to be sure, but he has also offended against the

    requirements of a society based on fair play, and his offense is thusa more serious crime of unfairness than the tax evaders.19

    There are, I believe, two significant problems with this argument. First, its not clear that

    the rapist does make it more difficult for his victim than the tax evader makes it for her victims

    to contribute further to the ongoing cooperation. As Dagger has (rightly) characterized it, the

    relevant sense of cooperation here is cooperation in complying with the law in general. When

    others exercise general compliance with the law, and when I benefit from their compliance, then

    I have an obligation similarly to participate in the cooperative venture (i.e., to reciprocate) by

    complying with the law. But although rape clearly is a more egregious violation than tax evasion,

    its not clear that one way in which it is more egregious is that the rape victims ability to

    further the ongoing cooperation by accepting the burden of compliance with the law is

    especially diminished.

    Second, even if the more serious crime does more severely threaten its victims ability to

    contribute to the fair cooperative venture, this does not demonstrate that such a crime is a more

    serious crime of unfairness than the less serious crime. Put more simply, an act may undermine

    fairness without itself being unfair. Consider, by analogy, a community founded on the value of

    truth-telling. Suppose I, a member of this community, issue a threat to other community

    members that every time I hear them utter a true statement, I will inflict serious harm on them or

    their loved ones (or have my henchmen do it). Then suppose I begin to carry out this threat, and

    that over time my fellow community members, fearing that my henchmen or I may be listening,

    increasingly lie to each other. In this case, it seems that I have undermined truthfulness in my

    community without ever being untruthful myself. I suggest that fairness is analogous to truth in

    19 Ibid.

    11

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    12/31

    this respect, and thus that crimes that more seriously undermine the fair political order are not

    necessarily more unfair.20

    In my view, Daggers recent account asks fair play to do too much; that is, he seeks to

    offer an integrated account in which fair play grounds not only punishments permissibility but

    also its positive justification, as well as generating plausible sentencing guidance. On the

    standard fair play views characterization, however, as articulated by Hart and Rawls, crimes are

    unfair in the sense of free riding. Offenders accept the benefits made possible by the general

    compliance of others with the law, and then they choose to reject the burden of reciprocal

    compliance. Its just not clear, however, that by more seriously undermining the fair political

    order, an offender has therefore been more of a free rider. In fact, given that the offender (like

    everyone) benefits from the cooperative venture, then to the extent that she offends against the

    cooperative venture (by undermining the victims ability to contribute to it), she is actually more

    likely to harm rather than benefit herself. Free riders can only ride freely when the practice from

    which they draw benefits, but to which they do not contribute, thrives. Thus its unclear how, by

    more seriously offending against the cooperative venture, the offender would more egregiously

    free-ride than in cases in which she less seriously offended against the cooperative venture.

    I conclude, then, that the fair play view is unable to provide a plausible, univocal account

    of punishment that grounds not only its presumptive permissibility but also its positive

    justification and sentencing guidance in particular cases. Traditional fair play articulations

    provide the wrong answer, at least in many cases, to the question why should we punish this

    crime? and they are unable plausibly to specify any benefit that an offender unfairly gains

    through her crime. And although I believe Daggers recent fair play defense is a significant

    20 Similarly, Philip Pettit points out two distinct ways in which we may respond to whatever we value: We may

    promote it, and we may honor it. As Pettit notes, whether we promote the value implies nothing regarding whether

    we honor it, and vice versa. Pettit, Consequentialism, in Consequentialism, ed. Stephen Darwall (Malden, Mass.:

    Blackwell Publishing, 2003), pp. 95-107, esp. p. 97.

    12

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    13/31

    improvement over traditional accounts, it is not ultimately an integrated account. Rather, it

    implicitly appeals both to the traditional, deontological conception of fair play as well as the

    consequentialist aim of preserving a fair political order. As will become clear in the next section,

    however, I do not regard fair plays inability to answer all the questions of punishment (i.e., its

    inability to ground a unified account) as a liability. Rather, on the account I propose, there is

    good reason to expect that the fair play view will ground only the presumptive permissibility of

    punishment, and that punishments positive justification and guidance regarding appropriate

    sentencing will require appeal to distinct considerations.

    III. An alternative fair play account.

    Although I have argued against prominent fair play accounts of punishment, I

    nevertheless find something intuitively appealing about the fair play account of political

    obligation espoused by Hart and Rawls. In beginning to set out my own fair play account of

    punishment, then, I believe Harts concise statement of the fair play principle bears repeating:

    [W]hen a number of persons conduct any joint enterpriseaccording to rules and thus restrict their liberty, those who have

    submitted to these restrictions when required have a right to a

    similar submission from those who have benefited by theirsubmission.21

    So, as a member of a cooperative enterprise, if I benefit from others playing by the rules,

    then I should play by the rules as well. But which rules? The rules most frequently appealed to

    by fair play accounts of political obligation and of punishment are the political communitys

    criminal statutes, the laws prohibiting, say, murder, theft, tax evasion, drug trafficking, etc. Hart,

    in his The Concept of Law, cited criminal laws as paradigm cases of what he called primary rules

    21 Supra. note 4.

    13

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    14/31

    rules that impose duties or obligations.22 In addition to primary rules, however, Hart pointed

    out that a legal system is composed also of secondary rules, which are rules about the primary

    rules. Secondary rules, he writes, specify the ways in which the primary rules may be

    conclusively ascertained, introduced, eliminated, varied, and the fact of their violation

    conclusively determined.23 Examples of secondary rules are rules of recognition, which

    provide some criteria for determining whether purported primary rules are in fact primary rules,

    i.e., which are legally valid; rules of change, which govern the process whereby primary rules

    may be enacted or repealed; and rules of adjudication, which govern the determinations of

    whether, in particular cases, primary rules have been violated.

    24

    In addition, Hart briefly noted another class of secondary rules that pertain specifically to

    the punishment of violations. These are the rules governing what punishments are appropriate

    (rules specifying or at least limiting the penalties for violation) in particular cases, and also the

    rules granting the legal system the exclusive power to administer punishments.25 I suggest that

    among these rules regarding the punishment of violations, though not cited here by Hart, are also

    the rules establishing punishmentper se as the appropriate response to a crime. Such rules are

    conceptually prior to the rules governing what punishments are appropriate in particular cases;

    that is, determining the appropriate punishment in a given case implies that punishment itself is

    the appropriate response to the criminal wrongdoing. There is nothing in the conception of a

    criminal law that entails that the law must be backed by punishment. 26 Indeed, other forms of

    22 H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law 2d ed. (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 1994), esp. pp. 79-99.23

    Ibid., p. 94.24 Ibid., pp. 94-7.25 Ibid., pp. 97-8.26 Hart appears to have disagreed on this point, as he indicates in various passages that, as a conceptual matter,

    criminal laws must be backed by physical sanctions, i.e., punishment (see, e.g., ibid., pp. 34-5, 86). If this is right, so

    that criminal laws without punishment are not really criminal laws, then those who would endorse the abolition of

    punishment will face the unenviable task of also defending the abolition of criminal laws altogether. As I have

    indicated, however, I reject the view that criminal law entails punishment. Thus on my view, even if criminal

    statutes are themselves justified, the proposition that punishment is an appropriate mode of response to violations of

    these statutes nevertheless requires its own defense. I am grateful to Larry May for raising this point to me.

    14

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    15/31

    response to the violation of such laws have been suggested: public (nonpunitive) censure, or

    restitution, for example. Thus if punishment is to be the response to violations of criminal

    statutes, this will be because it has been designated as the appropriate response by some

    secondary rule(s) of the political community.

    As I indicated above, the fair play account of political obligation aims to ground an

    obligation to play by the rules of ones political community (understood as a mutually beneficial,

    cooperative enterprise). One relevant question, then, is whether this obligation applies only with

    respect to the primary rules of the system (in particular, the criminal statutes), or whether,

    instead, the scope of the obligation extends more broadly. Notably, does the obligation extend to

    the rule(s) establishing that punishment is an appropriate response to crimes? In my view, what is

    relevant in determining whether some rule falls within the scope of a fair play obligation to

    comply is (a) whether the rule is the sort with which we actually can comply, and (b) whether

    general compliance with this rule yields significant benefits to community members. Regarding

    (a), I contend that the rule instituting punishment as a response to crimes is one with which we

    can comply (or fail to comply). One way to comply would be to constrain ones behavior so as to

    avoid being liable to punishment; another way to comply would be, if one has been found guilty

    of a criminal offense, to accept the prescribed punishment.27 Conversely, one could fail to

    comply with this rule by committing a crime and attempting to evade apprehension (and

    27 Acceptance of ones punishment may take various forms. In the paradigmatic case of incarceration, acceptance

    may often be a matter merely of not resisting apprehension and punishment. In other cases, however, accepting

    punishment may require a more active response from the offender. She may be required, for instance, to pay a fine,

    to appear for community service, or to meet with her probation officer. And even with respect to imprisonment,

    courts will in some cases require the convicted person to report to prison on a certain date to serve her term. Thanks

    to Antony Duff for suggesting this point to me.

    15

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    16/31

    subsequent punishment).28Thus I conclude that the rule instituting punishment as a response to

    criminal offenses is one with which we can comply.29

    With respect to (b), there is good reason to believe that the institution of punishment

    yields significant benefits for community members. To deny this claim, one would need to

    demonstrate that the protections afforded to members of the political community by the rule of

    law would not be significantly threatened if the institution of punishment, as a sanction backing

    the various prohibitions, were abolished (perhaps to be replaced by some alternative, such as

    public censure or restitution). Such an argument would need, most obviously, to refute the

    purportedly crucial value of punishment as a general deterrent, but it would also need to

    demonstrate that the institution of punishment is not necessary to providing community members

    with any other significant benefits either e.g., as a means of specific deterrence, retribution,

    incapacitation, or reform/rehabilitation. If general compliance with the rule instituting the

    practice of legal punishment as a response to criminal wrongdoing does provide significant

    benefits to community members, then it appears that this rule falls within the scope of those rules

    to which the fair play account grounds an obligation of compliance.30

    28 In other words, if the rule is stated crudely as the conditional ifyou commit a crime, then you are subject to

    punishment, then I can comply eitherby not committing crimes, so that the antecedent is false (and the conditional

    itself trivially true), orby not attempting to escape punishment, so that the consequent (and thus the conditional) is

    rendered true.29 One might object here that only primary rules are the sort with which we may comply because, in Harts terms,

    only primary rules impose obligations; secondary rules, by contrast, confer powers. Thus, given my argument that

    the rule instituting punishment is the sort with which we can comply, one may argue that this rule cannot be a

    secondary rule in Harts sense. This is a fair point. I characterize the rule here as a secondary rule because, like other

    secondary rules, it is a rule aboutthe primary rules, specifically about how violations of the primary rules may be

    addressed. But for my account, not much hangs on where this rule might fit into Harts taxonomy, i.e., whether it isa secondary rule, a primary rule, or even in somesui generis category that Hart did not anticipate. What is relevant

    for my purposes here is that the rule instituting punishment is one with which we can comply.30 It is beyond the scope of this paper to engage in the important debate about whether in fact punishment does have

    significantly beneficial social effects, e.g., as a general deterrent, etc. If there are no considerable benefits from

    maintaining the institution of punishment, then I believe the fair play account would be unable to ground its

    presumptive moral permissibility. This fits with my own intuition, however, as I believe that punishments yielding

    some significant benefit is a necessary (albeit not sufficient) condition of the institutions moral permissibility. In

    what follows, however, I assume (in keeping with common intuitions) that the institution of punishment does yield

    significant benefits to members of the political community.

    16

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    17/31

    If the rule establishing punishment is among those rules with which, according to the fair

    play account, we are obliged to comply in a mutually beneficial, cooperative social order, then

    the presumptive permissibility of punishment follows straightforwardly. That is, if, according to

    considerations of fair play, or reciprocity, each of us has a moral obligation to comply with the

    rule that says violations of criminal statutes will be punished, then insofar as having a moral

    obligation to X implies not having a moral right not to X none of us has a moral right not to

    comply with this rule. As I claimed above, compliance with the rule can take either of two forms:

    On one hand, I can comply by constraining my behavior to avoid violating the law and thus

    avoid being subject to punishment; on the other hand, if I do violate the law, I can comply by

    accepting punishment as the response. Putting these pieces together, it follows that no one has a

    right not to be punished if she violates some criminal statute. The practice of punishment in

    general, then, is not a violation of criminals rights.

    To briefly sum up my argument to this point: Punishment is presumptively morally

    permissible not because it removes some benefit(s) that an offender unfairly gains in failing to

    meet her obligation to play by the communitys legal rules; rather, it is permissible because

    punishment as a response to crime is itself one of the rules with which the offender, like all those

    who benefit from mutual compliance with the rules, is obliged to comply. My fair play account

    of punishmentjust is the fair play account of political obligation, along with the recognition that

    the rules of punishment are among those rules of the community that, when community members

    generally comply with them, are mutually beneficial. In section IV, I address what I take to be

    the most powerful objections against the fair play view of political obligation. First, however, in

    the remainder of this section, I want to consider a number of advantages to my view in

    comparison with the standard fair play account of punishment.

    17

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    18/31

    Most importantly, my view fares better against the two objections to the traditional fair

    play account of punishment that I discussed earlier. Consider the first objection, that the

    traditional fair play account misconstrues why certain crimes merit punishment; murder, that is,

    does not seem to be centrally, if at all, a crime of free riding on other community members

    generally. My version of the fair play account, by contrast, grounds only punishments

    presumptive permissibility. It does not follow from my account that fair play considerations also

    supply the positive justification of punishment; thus my account does not imply, for instance,

    that the murderer should be punished because she was a free rider on members of the community

    generally. In fact, my account of punishments permissibility is compatible with any number of

    positive justifications of punishment. All that is required, on my account, is that general

    compliance with the practice of punishment provides benefits to community members (where,

    again, compliance may take the form either of constraining ones behavior so as not to violate

    the law or of accepting punishment when one does violate the law). This account is consistent

    with various sorts of benefits. My own view is that the institution of punishments central benefit

    is that, by acting as a general deterrent, it helps to ensure the safety and security of community

    members. Others, however, might argue that the institution of punishment is beneficial to

    community members because it incapacitates or reforms offenders, expresses the communitys

    condemnation of crimes,31 or even because it is intrinsically valuable for wrongdoers to get what

    they deserve.32Whatever benefits are determined to provide a positive justification of

    31 In the context of international crimes especially, the expressive value of punishment is fleshed out not only in

    terms of publicly condemning the crime but also in constructing a shared narrative of the events. In particular, seeMark Drumbl,Atrocity, Punishment, and International Law (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2007),

    esp. pp. 173-9.32 It may seem strange to include retribution among the possible benefits punishment might provide to community

    members. Typically in the literature, retribution is contrasted with consequentialist positive justifications of

    punishment grounded in various societal benefits (e.g., deterrence, incapacitation, reform). One might hold,

    however, that retribution is itself beneficial to community members. If one accepts G. E. Moores claim that the

    state of affairs in which wrongdoers are made to suffer is better on the whole than the state in which they do not

    suffer, then it might follow that community members generally are better off when this superior state of affairs

    prevails. For Moores account of the value of retributive punishment, see hisPrincipia Ethica (Cambridge, U.K.:

    18

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    19/31

    punishment, however, its presumptive permissibility will stem, on the fair play view, from the

    fact that an offender (like everyone else) reaps these benefits as a result of the general

    compliance with the communitys rules regarding punishment thus the offender will have an

    obligation of fairness similarly to comply.

    The second objection noted to the traditional articulation of the fair play view is that there

    seems to be no benefit that an offender unfairly gains, relative to other community members

    generally, through her commission of a crime. Because the traditional articulation justifies

    punishment as a means of removing the unfair advantage, the inability to specify such an

    advantage is obviously problematic. And accounts that have specified some advantage appear to

    generate counterintuitive sentencing guidance. Again, my account avoids this general line of

    criticism, as my view does not characterize punishment as removing some unfairly gained

    advantage. Punishment is permissible because the practice is among the rules of the cooperative

    system to which general compliance yields certain benefits benefits that offenders, like

    everyone else, enjoy. Determining the benefits of punishment, and if some measure of

    proportionality in sentencing is necessary (or at least conducive) to realizing these benefits, is a

    separate matter.

    An implication of my account, then, as I have indicated, is that it is appropriate to

    disaggregate various questions of punishment in particular, (why) is punishment

    presumptively morally permissible? what is punishments positive justifying aim? and what

    mode and degree of punishment are permissible in particular cases? and to answer these

    questions by appeal to distinct considerations. Some may criticize this sort of disaggregation

    strategy as ad hoc, but on the fair play view I have suggested, this objection is unpersuasive.

    Cambridge University Press, 1992), chapter 6, esp. sections 128-33; see also Leo Zaiberts discussion in his

    Punishment and Retribution, esp. ch. 7. I do not myself endorse retribution as a positive justification of punishment,

    but the account of punishments presumptive permissibility that I offer here is compatible with such a view.

    19

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    20/31

    Again, my fair play account just is the fair play account of political obligation, with the rules of

    punishment recognized to be among those rules to which the obligation of fairness extends. To

    require this account to ground not only punishments presumptive permissibility but also its

    positive justification and sentencing guidance would be as implausible as requiring it to ground

    specific conclusions about the other rules of the cooperative enterprise. We dont expect that the

    fair play view should tell us, for instance, which acts should be required or forbidden by criminal

    statutes that is, we dont expect the view itself to generate primary rules, to use Harts term.

    Why then, should we expect the same fair play view to generate rules about punishment? Rather

    than its being ad hoc to distinguish the presumptive permissibility question from the other

    questions, on the fair play view we have good reason to expect that the answer to the

    permissibility question will not yield guidance regarding the other two questions.

    As I have discussed, my account avoids what I take to be the two most powerful

    objections to the standard fair play articulation. More generally, however, my account has an

    advantage over any account that defends punishment as a sort of appropriate remediation for

    violations of the fair play obligation to play by the rules of the cooperative venture. Such

    accounts require two substantial defenses: a defense of the fair play account of political

    obligation itself, and a defense of punishment as a permissible remediation for failures to meet

    the obligation defended in the first part. By contrast, once we recognize that the rules of

    punishment are among those rules to which the obligation of compliance extends, then on my

    account only one substantial defense is required: a defense of the fair play view of political

    obligation. My view is in this regard sturdier than standard fair play accounts of punishment,

    insofar as objections that purport to undermine my view will undermine the standard

    20

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    21/31

    articulations as well, whereas not all objections faced by the standard articulations also threaten

    my account.

    Essentially, on my fair play account, whether the institution of punishment is

    presumptively permissible will be determined by whether we have a moral obligation to comply

    with the rules of our political community. Thus, this defense of punishment will stand or fall

    according to whether the fair play account of political obligation is persuasive. In the following

    section, I consider, first, an objection to my defending punishment as a matter of political

    obligation and, second, what I take to be the most powerful objections to the fair play account of

    political obligation itself.

    IV. Objections.

    The first objection I want to consider involves my strategy of deriving the moral

    permissibility of punishment from an account of political obligation. On my account, the rules

    instituting legal punishment are among those with which we are reciprocally obliged to comply

    as members of a political community, here characterized as a mutually beneficial, cooperative

    enterprise. According to the objection, therefore, this strategy implies that punishment would not

    be morally permissible in the absence of such a political community, viz., in the state of nature.

    Insofar as we have intuitions that punishment would be morally permissible in the state of nature,

    then my account appears deficient.33

    I actually have mixed intuitions about whether punishment would be permissible in the

    state of nature. On one hand, Im somewhat inclined to maintain that punishment would not,

    perhaps could not, be permissible in such conditions. Those in a state of nature might retaliate

    against wrongs perpetrated against them, but its not clear that harming in this context, even if

    33 This objection was raised to me by Kit Wellman.

    21

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    22/31

    proportionate to the wrongdoing, would constitute just punishment. Kant, for one, believed that

    just punishment is impossible in the state of nature, because there is no public authority to settle

    disputes.34If we accept the notion that punishment, to be permissible, must be imposed by a

    proper authority with standing to settle disputes between opposing parties, then it appears that

    such punishment is by definition impossible in the state of nature.

    On the other hand, it seems that I might permissibly impose intentional harm on someone

    who has wronged me, even if there is no recognized authority to confirm that punishment in such

    a case is permissible. If this is true, however, I contend that such punishment would be morally

    permissible for roughly the same reasons that it is permissible in a political community. In the

    state of nature, if George steals from Kramer, and Kramer responds not only by retrieving his

    stolen goods but also by inflicting some sort of harm on George, then presumably this will tend

    to deter others who might have otherwise considered stealing from Kramer. Conversely, if

    Kramer didnt respond, others might take this as evidence that they could get away with similar

    behavior as George. Furthermore, when Kramer punishes George, seeing this may lead Elaine to

    think twice not only about stealing from Kramer in the future, but about stealing from anyone.

    This is because Kramers punitive response to Georges stealing may cause Elaine, especially if

    she has witnessed others responding in similar retaliatory ways in similar circumstances, to

    believe that this sort of response is the sort that tends to follow attempts at stealing. All of this is

    just to say that general deterrence would be a significant benefit (arguably the central benefit) of

    punishing wrongdoing in the state of nature. As noted above, the deterrent effect will be

    particularly strong if those in the state of nature see wrongdoing meeting with punitive responses

    with some regularity. That is, if individuals begin to regard it as a sort of informal rule that

    34 C.f., Immanuel Kant, The Doctrine of Right6:312, in the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant,

    Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 456.

    See also Helga Vardens helpful discussion of Kants account in Varden, Kants Non-Voluntarist Conception of

    Political Obligations: Why Justice is Impossible in the State of Nature,Kantian Review 13:2 (2008): 1-45.

    22

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    23/31

    wrongdoing is met with a punitive response, then they may be persuaded to comply with this rule

    by constraining their behavior to avoid the punishment. But if such compliance with this

    informal rule is beneficial to those in the state of nature, then they have an obligation of fair play

    to comply with it as well, either by appropriately constraining their behavior or by accepting the

    punitive response when they do commit a crime.

    On the view I have developed here, considerations of fair play could ground the

    presumptive permissibility of punishment even in the absence of a formal cooperative scheme,

    such as a political community. Whether it actually did ground punishments permissibility would

    be a matter of whether (a) individuals came to regard it as a sort of informal rule that wrongdoing

    is met with punishment, (b) recognition of the rule led to general compliance with it (with

    compliance here taking the form of choosing not to engage in wrongdoing so as to avoid

    punishment), and (c) general compliance with the rule yielded significant benefits for

    individuals. Although I have argued that each of these requirements might hold in the state of

    nature, notice that the existence of a political community governed by the rule of law makes each

    of them much more likely. In such a political community, the rules of punishment are not merely

    regularities of behavior that may come to be seen as informal rules; rather, they are set out

    formally, so that everyone can clearly recognize them as rules of the community. The more

    clearly individuals recognize the rules, the more likely they will be to comply. The greater the

    general level of compliance, the greater will be the benefit i.e., general deterrence to

    community members. Finally, the greater the benefit community members enjoy from the

    compliance of others, the greater their (fair play) obligation is similarly to comply.

    So to sum up my response to this first objection, punishment may be presumptively

    permissible in the state of nature, but if so it will be because of the same considerations of

    23

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    24/31

    fairness that ground its permissibility in a political community. The fair play obligation to

    comply with the rules of punishment will be significantly stronger, however, in a political

    community than in the state of nature, because the benefits yielded by punishment will be

    comparatively greater in a political community than in the state of nature.

    The second objection I want to consider attacks the fair play view of political obligation

    directly. It has been commonly pointed out that my merely receivingbenefits from others

    compliance with the rules of a cooperative enterprise is not itself enough to generate obligations

    on me to reciprocate.35Rather, as A. John Simmons has written, what is required is that I accept

    these benefits.

    36

    With respect to certain kinds of benefits, which Simmons calls readily available,

    determining whether we accept them is fairly straightforward if we seek them out and obtain

    them, then we have accepted them. For instance, if I request and receive specialprotection by

    the police, if I fear for my life, say, or if I need my house to be watched while Im away, this

    would constitute my acceptance of a readily available benefit.37 By contrast, many benefits of

    membership in a political community are not the sort that we seek out; rather, they are open

    benefits, which we cannot avoid, except perhaps at great inconvenience.38 Examples of open

    benefits include police protection, national security from external threats, assurance of air- and

    water-quality standards, etc.

    35 Robert Nozick notably made the point that mere receipt of benefits is not sufficient to confer obligations by way

    of this example: Imagine you live in a neighborhood in which a group of your neighbors buys a public address

    system and decides to start a public entertainment program for the neighborhood (which happens to comprise 365

    neighbors). Each neighbor is assigned one day per year in which she is responsible for running the PA system.After 138 days on which each person has done his part, your day arrives. Are you obligated to take your turn? You

    have benefited from it, occasionally opening your window to listen, enjoying some music or chuckling at someonesfunny story. The other people have put themselves out. But must you answer the call when it is your turn to do so?

    As it stands, surely not. Nozick,Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York City: Basic Books, 1974), p. 93.36 See A. John Simmons, The Principle of Fair Play,Philosophy & Public Affairs 8:4 (1979), reprinted in Robert

    M. Stewart, ed.,Readings in Social & Political Philosophy (New York City: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 66-

    81.37 Ibid., p. 77.38 Ibid., p. 76.

    24

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    25/31

    On Simmons account, acceptance of an open benefit normally involves taking the

    benefit willingly and knowingly, where this requires, at least, (a) regarding the benefit as

    flowing from a cooperative scheme rather than seeing it as free for the taking, and (b)

    thinking that the benefit is worth the price we must pay for [it], so that given a choice of taking

    the benefit and accepting the concurrent burdens or rejecting the benefit, we would take it.39

    These are fairly steep requirements on what counts as acceptance of a benefit. Not surprisingly,

    he concludes that many, perhaps most, citizens do not meet these criteria for acceptance of

    benefits. Many do not notice or think much about the benefits they receive from the political

    order, and many of those who do think about these benefits mistakenly undervalue them relative

    to the corresponding burdens thus for Simmons they cannot be said to have accepted the open

    benefits in the sense necessary to confer political obligation.

    George Klosko has provided what I take to be a persuasive response to this objection.

    Essentially, Klosko contends that acceptance, of the sort Simmons has in mind, is not necessary

    in some cases for open benefits to confer fair play obligations. Klosko contends that in situations

    where you benefit from our compliance with the rules of a cooperative venture but do not

    yourself comply (i.e., in free-rider situations), fairness demands either(a) that you no longer

    benefit, (b) that we (i.e., the rest of us) be similarly freed from the burden of compliance, or (c)

    that you start to comply.40 Open benefits, by definition, benefit everyone they cannot be

    provided generally but withheld from certain members of the community. Thus with respect to

    open benefits, (a) is not an option. Klosko argues that (b) also is not an option for certain open

    benefits, specifically those that are indispensable to the welfare of all community members.41

    National defense, for instance, is essential to the well-being ofXand all its members,

    39 Ibid., pp. 77 and 80.40 C.f., Klosko, The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers,

    Inc., 1992), p. 35.41 Ibid., pp. 39-54, esp. p. 43.

    25

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    26/31

    [therefore] it mustbe provided. The consequences of nonprovision would be catastrophic for all

    concerned42 to the free rider herself as well as everyone else. Thus to allow that no one has

    the burden of compliance (and thus to sacrifice the corresponding benefits) is not a practically

    viable option. With (a) and (b) unavailable as options, only (c) remains the free rider is

    obliged to comply. Klosko writes:

    It is difficult to imagine what Pickerel could say to the members of

    X, who have provided him with national defense, in order to justify

    his unwillingness to cooperate. Because the benefits areindispensable, he could not say that he does not want them. Nor

    could he distinguish himself from the otherX-ites because he has

    not sought the benefits out. Because of the nature of national

    defense, none of the X-ites have pursued them. The X-ites can bepresumed to differ from Pickerel in their willing acceptance of the

    schemes burdens. But Pickerels unwillingness to participate isdifficult to defend. Unless there is some morally relevant

    difference between Pickerel and the members ofX, his refusal to

    cooperate must be interpreted simply as a desire to profit fromtheir labor without doing his fair share, and so as a clear instance

    of free riding.43

    Klosko thus concludes that we may be obliged to comply with rules that provide us with

    open, indispensable benefits even if we have not accepted these benefits in the sense Simmons

    requires. Note, however, that on this account, fair play only grounds obligations to comply with

    the rules that provide open and indispensable benefits.44 The relevant question for present

    purposes, then, is whether the benefits provided by the institution of punishment are open and

    indispensable. I contend that they are both. As I indicated earlier, I believe the central benefit of

    the institution of punishment is that it gives genuine bindingness to the rule of law by providing

    significant incentives not to violate legal rules (i.e., through general deterrence). In this way, the

    institution of punishment plays a crucial role in ensuring the security of community members. If

    42 Ibid., p. 43.43 Ibid., p. 42.44 Klosko has argued elsewhere that we nevertheless have political obligations with respect to other rules, and that

    these obligations are grounded in distinct principles. See hisPolitical Obligations (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University

    Press, 2005), esp. chapter 5. Analyzing Kloskos broader account is beyond the scope of this essay.

    26

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    27/31

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    28/31

    community members, and the institution of punishment plays a crucial role in ensuring that the

    rule of law genuinely binds.47Thus I conclude that the institution of punishment provides an

    indispensable open benefit. As such, it grounds a fair play obligation of compliance even for

    those who have not met Simmons standards for acceptance of the benefit.

    A third possible objection, again to fair play accounts of political obligation generally,

    centers once more on the idea of the benefit(s) conferred. Here the worry is that, although the

    goods yielded by the cooperative scheme may be generally beneficial, there may be individuals

    for whom the costs of compliance with the rules of the scheme outweigh the corresponding

    benefits. If so, then in such cases considerations of fair play seem ill-suited to ground obligations

    of compliance. In the context of the rule(s) instituting punishment of crimes, one might object

    that many criminals do not, all-things-considered, benefit from the existence of such an

    institution (or, to put it another way, that the costs outweigh the benefits). That is, we might be

    hard pressed to demonstrate that, say, an individual serving an extended prison term is better off

    than she would have been had there been no institution of punishment. In the counterfactual case,

    she might not enjoy the benefits that punishment yields (general deterrence, etc.), but she also

    would not face the hardships associated with the prison term. Thus on balance, one might argue

    that she would be better off if there were no institution of punishment.48

    Whether an individual being punished would be, on balance, better off in a society with

    no institution of punishment is an empirical question. It is not obvious to me that she would be

    47 My claim here rests on two empirical claims, either of which might be challenged. That is, one might contend that

    the security of community members does not depend on the rule of law, or alternatively that the rule of lawsbindingness does not depend on the institution of punishment. Thus even if security is understood to be an

    indispensable benefit, one might argue that punishment is not an indispensable means to achieving that benefit.

    Arguing for these empirical claims is beyond the scope of this paper, but I concede that if it could be shown

    convincingly that the security of community members could be ensured as (or more) effectively by means other than

    a system of laws backed by punishment, then the case I offer here for punishments presumptive permissibility

    would be correspondingly undermined. I am grateful to Antony Duff for pushing me on this point.48 This objection was raised to me by Victor Tadros.

    28

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    29/31

    better off in such circumstances. On one hand, without the prospect of legal punishment to deter

    others from committing crimes, the individuals own safety and security (as well as that of her

    loved ones) might be significantly jeopardized. On the other hand, if the person herself engaged

    in wrongdoing against others, the void filled by the absence of a legal institution of punishment

    might be filled by private vengeance. This vengeance might be much more severe than the legal

    punishment that the offender would face.49More importantly, however, as I noted earlier, the

    rule instituting punishment as the response to crimes is best understood as a conditional: ifyou

    commit a crime, then you will be subject to punishment. The rule thus offers individuals not only

    the benefits of general deterrence (or perhaps special deterrence, incapacitation, retribution, etc.)

    but also the opportunity to constrain their behavior so as to avoid punishment. So to the prisoner

    who claims she has not benefited from the rule instituting punishment, we might reply: Is it

    more beneficial (a) that there be a rule that helps protect you and your loved ones by deterring

    crimes and allows you the opportunity to avoid being punished yourself, or (b) that there be no

    such rule, so that harms to you and your family may go undeterred, and if you wrong others you

    will be subject to their vengeance? If we thus consider the benefits individuals receive from the

    institution of punishment and the choice each person has to avoid punishment herself, then

    punishment does appear, on balance, beneficial.

    This is not to say that the institution of punishment will therefore be permissible no

    matter what punishments it prescribes in particular cases. As I have indicated from the outset, the

    defense I have offered here is only of punishmentspresumptive moral permissibility. That is,

    my argument has been that punishmentper se, that is, the intentional infliction of harm on

    49 The hazards of private vengeance have been noted by, among others, John Locke, Second Treatise of Civil

    Government, ch. 2 para. 13, inReadings in Social & Political Philosophy, ed. Robert M. Stewart (New York:

    Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 15-6; John Hospers, Punishment, Protection, and Retaliation, inJustice and

    Punishment, ed. J. B. Cederblom and William L. Blizek (Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger Publishing Co., 1977), p. 35;

    and Nicola Lacey, State Punishment: Political Principles and Community Values (London: Routledge, 1988), p.

    184.

    29

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    30/31

    criminal wrongdoers, does not in itself constitute a violation of offenders rights. Particular

    instances of punishment, however, may still be morally impermissible all things considered if

    they fail to treat offenders with the respect to which they are entitled as moral persons. Again, I

    take it that my account is similar in this respect to fair play accounts of political obligation

    generally. In other words, if considerations of fair play ground an obligation to comply with

    criminal statutes, this surely is only a presumptive obligation. Such accounts would not ground

    (nor purport to ground) an absolute obligation of compliance irrespective of the content of the

    statutes. In fact, any plausible account of political obligation, be it grounded in considerations of

    fair play, tacit consent, natural duties of justice, or whatever, will allow that in certain cases we

    may be permitted, perhaps even required, to violate unjust laws (perhaps through civil

    disobedience, or in extreme cases, even outright revolution). Nevertheless, there is a presumptive

    moral obligation to comply with a communitys laws and relevant for present purposes, there

    is a presumptive moral obligation to comply with the rule according to which one is subject to

    punishment when one has violated some criminal statute. Thus the institution of punishment is

    presumptively morally permissible.

    V. Conclusion.

    In this paper, I have aimed to provide a more plausible version of the fair play

    justification of punishment, one that follows more straightforwardly from the fair play account of

    political obligation and also avoids the objections typically leveled against fair play defenses of

    punishment. I have acknowledged that the success of my account depends on the plausibility of

    the fair play account of political obligation. Although I did briefly offer a defense of this view of

    political obligation against what I take to be the most powerful objections raised against it, a full

    30

  • 8/14/2019 Hoskins 2010 Paper

    31/31

    defense of this view would take me well beyond the scope of this paper. For others who would

    endorse the fair play account of punishment, however, I suggest that the political obligation

    question should take center stage. If the fair play view of political obligation can be defended,

    then the fair play account of punishment follows straightforwardly. Also, notice that pursuing

    such a strategy leads to the implication that the question of punishments presumptive

    permissibility is distinct from the questions of its positive justification and of how to punish in

    particular cases; answers to these distinct questions will require appeal to distinct moral

    considerations. Rather than regarding this implication as regrettable, however, I suggest that fair

    play theorists should embrace it. As I argued above, doing so is not only defensible in its own

    right, but it also allows the fair play view to avoid a number of unappealing implications.50

    50 I am grateful to Antony Duff, Larry May, Victor Tadros, and Kit Wellman for their helpful comments on earlier

    drafts of this paper.