how judges think

Upload: harvard-university-press

Post on 30-May-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    1/24

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    2/24

    How Judges Think

    Richard A. Posner

    HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS

    Cambridge, Massachusetts

    London, England

    2008

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    3/24

    Copyright 2008 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College

    All rights reserved

    Printed in the United States of America

    A Caravan book. For more information, visit www.caravanbooks.org

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Posner, Richard A.

    How judges think / Richard A. Posner.

    p. cm.

    Includes index.

    ISBN-13: 978-0-674-02820-3 (alk. paper)1. Judicial process. 2. Judicial processUnited States. I. Title.

    K2300.P67 2008

    347.012dc22 2007037826

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    4/24

    Contents

    Introduction 1

    PART ONE THE BASIC MODEL

    1 Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior 192 The Judge as Labor-Market Participant 57

    3 The Judge as Occasional Legislator 78

    4 The Mind of the Legislating Judge 93

    PART TWO THE MODEL ELABORATED

    5 The Judicial Environment:

    External Constraints on Judging 125

    6 Altering the Environment: Tenure and Salary Issues 158

    7 Judicial Method: Internal Constraints on Judging 174

    8 Judges Are Not Law Professors 2049 Is Pragmatic Adjudication Inescapable? 230

    PART THREE JUSTICES

    10 The Supreme Court Is a Political Court 269

    11 Comprehensive Constitutional Theories 324

    12 Judicial Cosmopolitanism 347

    Conclusion 369

    Acknowledgments 379

    Index 381

    http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/http://0.0.0.0/
  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    5/24

    Introduction

    In my youthful, scornful way, I recognized four kinds of judgments;first the cogitative, of and by reflection and logomancy; second,aleatory, of and by the dice; third, intuitive, of and by feeling orhunching; and fourth, asinine, of and by an ass; and in that sameyouthful, scornful way I regarded the last three as only variants of each

    other, the results of processes all alien to good judges. 1

    Ivan Karamazov said that if God does not exist everything is permitted,

    and traditional legal thinkers are likely to say that if legalism (legal for-

    malism, orthodox legal reasoning, a government of laws not men, the

    rule of law as celebrated in the loftiest Law Day rhetoric, and so forth)

    does not exist everything is permitted to judgesso watch out! Legal-

    ism does exist, and so noteverythingis permitted. But its kingdom has

    shrunk and grayed to the point where today it is largely limited to rou-

    tine cases, and so a great dealis permitted to judges. Just how much is

    permitted and how they use their freedom are the principal concerns of

    this book. These concerns have been made especially timely by the star-

    tling (to the nave) right turn by the Supreme Court in its latest term

    (ending in June 2007).2 The turn resulted from the replacement of a

    moderately conservative Justice (OConnor) by an extremely conserva-

    tive one (Alito), and so underscores the question of the personal and po-

    litical elements in judging and thus of the sense in which the nation is

    ruled by judges rather than by law. If changing judges changes law, it is

    not even clear what law is.

    1

    1. Joseph C. Hutcheson, Jr., The Judgment Intuitive: The Function of the Hunch in Judi-

    cial Decision, 14Cornell Law Quarterly274, 275276 (1929).2. Linda Greenhouse, In Steps Big and Small, Supreme Court Moved Right: A 54 Dy-

    namic, with Kennedy as Linchpin, New York Times,July 1, 2007, 1, p. 1.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    6/24

    I feel a certain awkwardness in talking about judges, especially appel-late judges (my main concern), because I am one. Biographies are more

    reliable than autobiographies, and cats are not consulted on the princi-

    ples of feline psychology. At the same time, I am struck by how unreal-

    istic are the conceptions of the judge held by most people, including

    practicing lawyers and eminent law professors, who have never been

    judges3and even by some judges. This unrealism is due to a variety of

    things, including the different perspectives of the different branches of

    the legal professionincluding also a certain want of imagination. It is

    also due to the fact that most judges are cagey, even coy, in discussing

    what they do. They tend to parrot an official line about the judicial pro-

    cess (how rule-bound it is), and often to believe it, though it does not

    describe their actual practices.4

    There is also the sense that judging re-ally is a different profession from practicing or teaching law, and if youre

    not in it you cant understand it. I remember when I was appointed re-

    ceiving a note from a court of appeals judge in another circuit with

    whom I was acquainted, welcoming me to the club. This book parts

    the curtains a bit.

    The difficulty outsiders have in understanding judicial behavior is

    due partly to the fact that judges deliberate in secret, though it would be

    more accurate to say that the fact that they do not deliberate (by which I

    mean deliberatecollectively) very much is the real secret.5Judicial delib-

    eration is overrated. English judges traditionally did not deliberate at

    all, as that would have violated the ruling principle of orality, whereby

    everything that judges did had to be done in public so that their behav-

    2 Introduction

    3. A notable example is Harvard law professor Henry Harts time-and-motion study of Su-

    preme Court Justices: Henry M. Hart, Jr., The Supreme Court, 1958 Term: Foreword: The

    Time Chart of the Justices, 73 Harvard Law Review84 (1959), which I discuss in chapter 10.

    4. Robert Keeton, a federal district judge and before that a Harvard Law School professor,

    acknowledged in his treatise on judging that judges make value-laden rulings. Robert E.

    Keeton, Keeton on Judging in the American Legal System 15 (1999). But he did not explore the

    sources of those values. His treatise has no index entry for either politics or ideology.

    5. Though a pretty open one. When I first came on the court [the U.S. Court of Appeals for

    the District of Columbia Circuit], I imagined that conferences [on cases] would be reflective,

    refining, analytical, dynamic. Ordinarily they are none of these. We go around the table and

    each judge, from junior to senior, states his or her bottom line and maybe a brief explanation.

    Even if the panel is divided, the discussion is exceedingly crisp. The conference changes few

    minds. Assignments are made, life goes on. Patricia M. Wald, Some Real-Life Observationsabout Judging, 26Indiana Law Review173, 177 (1992). Chief Justice Rehnquist described Su-

    preme Court conferences similarly. See chapter 10.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    7/24

    ior could be monitored;6

    hence those seriatim opinions that baffle theAmerican law student and perhaps the English one as well. In almost all

    cases a brief discussion among the judges before deciding enables con-

    vergence on a single majority opinion in lieu of a separate opinion by

    each judge.

    The confidentiality of the judicial process would not matter greatly to

    an understanding and evaluation of the legal system if the consequences

    of judicial behavior could be readily determined. If you can determine

    the ripeness of a cantaloupe by squeezing or smelling it, you dont have

    to worry about the produce clerks mental processes. But the conse-

    quences of judicial behavior are often more difficult to determine and

    evaluate than the consequences even of other professional services, such

    as medicine. Many of the decisions that constitute the output of a courtsystem cannot be shown to be either good or bad, whether in terms

    of consequences or of other criteria, so it is natural to ask whether there

    are grounds for confidence in the design of the institution and in the

    competence and integrity of the judges who operate it.

    The secrecy of judicial deliberations is an example of professional

    mystification. Professions such as law and medicine provide essential

    services that are difficult for outsiders to understand and evaluate. Pro-

    fessionals like it that way because it helps them maintain a privileged

    status. But they know they have to overcome the laitys mistrust, and

    they do this in part by developing a mystique that exaggerates not only

    the professionals skills but also his disinterest.7 Judges have been doing

    this for thousands of years and have become quite good at itso good asto have achieved a certain opacity even to their fellow legal profession-

    als, including law professors as well as practicing lawyers. Judges have

    convinced many peopleincluding themselvesthat they use esoteric

    materials and techniques to build selflessly an edifice of doctrines un-

    marred by willfulness, politics, or ignorance.

    There is nevertheless considerable dissatisfaction with our legal sys-

    tem,8 as there is with our system of health care. Like health care, law is

    Introduction 3

    6. Robert J. Martineau, Appellate Justice in England and the United States: A Comparative

    Analysis101103 (1990).

    7. Richard A. Posner,The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory,ch. 3 (1999).

    8. See, for example, Philip K. Howard,The Collapse of the Common Good: How AmericasLawsuit Culture Undermines Our Freedom (2001); Walter K. Olson, The Litigation Explosion:

    What Happened When America Unleashed the Lawsuit(1991).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    8/24

    said to be too expensive (it certainly costs more per capita than the le-gal systems of the nations with which we tend to compare the United

    States), too intrusive into private and commercial life, too prone to error,

    too uncertain, and simply too large (the nation has a million lawyers).

    For these reasons it is contended to be a source of immense indirect

    costs on top of the expenses to the litigants. The accusations may be

    true, though assessing their truth is not the project of this book and is

    especially daunting because it is even harder to estimate the benefits of

    our legal system than its costs. Legal rights are options that may have

    value even if never exercised, but how to value such options? And legal

    duties deter harmful conductbut how effectively is extremely difficult

    to determine too.

    Supposing the criticisms have merit, the question is whom to blame.If all that judges do is apply rules made by legislatures or the framers

    of the Constitution (or follow precedents, made by current or former

    judges, that are promptly changed if they prove maladapted to current

    conditions), then the responsibility for the mess (if it is a mess) must lie

    with the legislators or the Constitutions framers, or with the political

    process more generally. But suppose that most rules laid down by legis-

    lative bodies are all right and the problem is willful judgesjudges who

    make up their own rules, or perhaps ignore rules altogether, instead dis-

    pensing shortsighted justice on the basis of the equities of each case,

    and as a result create enormous legal uncertainty. The policy implica-

    tions and hence the path of reform would depend on which explanation

    was correct (both might be). And what if the basic problem is that thestructure of American government, and the American political culture

    more broadly,compeljudges to make rather than just apply rules of law?

    What looks to the critics of the judiciary like willfulness might actually

    be the good-faith performance of a vital judicial role, and if judges re-

    fused to play it, insisting instead, as some legal thinkers urge (the le-

    galists, of whom more shortly), on limiting themselves to passively ap-

    plying rules made elsewhere, the legal system might be worse than it is.

    The answers are bound up with issues of judicial behavior. To il-

    lustrate, everyone will agree that contracts are vital to the operation of

    markets, and almost everyone will agree that the legal enforcement of

    contracts is important to the efficacy of contracts. Contract law is ad-

    ministered by judges. (Sometimes they are private judgesarbitrators

    4 Introduction

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    9/24

    but the effectiveness of arbitration depends on the enforceability of arbi-trators awards.) Being a part of the common law, it is also created by

    them. The law they create and the way in which they enforce it are delib-

    erate acts, just as business decisions and decisions by legislatures are de-

    liberate acts. Whether judicially made doctrines and decisions are good

    or bad may depend therefore on the judges incentives, which may in

    turn depend on the judges cognition and psychology, on how persons

    are selected (including self-selected) to be judges, and on the terms and

    conditions of judicial employment. Similarly, American antitrust law is

    far more the creation of judicial decisions than of antitrust legislation:

    the most important antitrust laws are as skimpy and vague as most pro-

    visions of the Bill of Rights. We ought therefore to be interested in how

    antitrust law has been shaped by the motivations, constraints, and otherinfluences that play on judges. The Supreme Court has actually called

    the Sherman Act a common-law statute,9 and common law is of course

    made by judges, not legislators.

    The judicial mentality would be of little interest if judges did noth-

    ing more than apply clear rules of law created by legislators, adminis-

    trative agencies, the framers of constitutions, and other extrajudicial

    sources (including commercial custom) to facts that judges and juries

    determined without bias or preconceptions. Then judges would be well

    on the road to being superseded by digitized artificial intelligence pro-

    grams.10 But even legal thinkers who believe passionately that judges

    should be rule appliers and unbiased fact finders and nothing more do

    not believe that thats how all or even most American judges behave allthe time. Our judges have and exercise discretion. Especially if they are

    appellate judges, even intermediate ones, they are occasional legisla-

    tors. To understand their legislative activity, one must understand their

    motivations, capacities, mode of selection, professional norms, and psy-

    chology.

    Achieving a sound understanding of judicial behavior is thus of more

    than merely academic interest; it is a key to legal reform. Yet its academic

    interest is also considerable because of the unusual incentives and con-

    straints, so unlike those in most jobs, that shape judicial behavior, espe-

    Introduction 5

    9. Leegin Creative Leather Products, Inc. v. PSKS, Inc., 127 S. Ct. 2705, 2720 (2007).

    10. I do not know why originalists and other legalists are not AI enthusiasts.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    10/24

    cially in the U.S. federal system, and because the analysis of that behav-ior may offer insights into the general subject of managing uncertainty.11

    Uncertainty is as salient a feature of our legal system as expense is of our

    medical system, and decision making under uncertainty is a deservedly

    important topic in economics, organization theory, and other fields.

    Like other writing by judges about judging, this book is heavily influ-

    enced by my own judicial experience, consisting of more than a quarter

    century as a federal court of appeals judge (seven years as chief judge of

    my court), with occasional forays into the district court to preside at tri-

    als, mainly civil jury trials. But the mode of the book is scholarly rather

    than confessional. In this respect it resembles my book on the regulation

    of sexuality, a subject otherwise remote from the study of judicial behav-

    ior. That book was motivated by my belated discovery that judgesknow next to nothing about sex beyond their own personal experience,

    which is limited, and one of my aims was to bring to the attention of

    the legal profession the rich multidisciplinary literature on the sub-

    ject.12 Judges, like other refined people in our society, are reticent

    about talking about sex, but judges are also reticent about talking about

    judging, especially talking frankly about it, whether to their colleagues

    or to a larger professional audience. This reticence makes the scholarly

    study of judicial behavior at once challenging and indispensable.

    The book emphasizes positive rather than normative analysiswhat

    judges do, not what they should dobut I do discuss normative issues

    and propose a few modest reforms, as well as making occasional sugges-

    tions for further research. Positive and normative analysis cannot easilybe separated when one is dealing with peoples deliberate actions, for

    unless they are evil or cynical people, the best explanation for their ac-

    tions is unlikely to be that they are deliberately flouting the norms of

    their society. If it is deeply wrong for a judge to base a decision on the

    flip of a coin, an aleatory theory of judicial behavior is unlikely to be

    sound. The grounds of a judges decisions may be wrong, but they are

    6 Introduction

    11. About which I have written at length in relation to catastrophic risk and also to the re-

    form of the U.S. intelligence system. See my books Catastrophe: Risk and Response(2004);Pre-

    venting Surprise Attacks: Intelligence Reform in the Wake of 9/11 (2005); Uncertain Shield: The

    U.S. Intelligence System in the Throes of Reform (2006); Countering Terrorism: Blurred Focus,

    Halting Steps(2007).

    12. Richard A. Posner,Sex and Reason1, 4 (1992).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    11/24

    unlikely to be outside the ballpark of norms and values prevailing in thesociety.

    The books primary focus is on federal appellate judges, including Su-

    preme Court Justices (the subject of Part Three, though discussed in the

    other parts as well). But there is some discussion of trial judges, state

    court judges, judges in foreign nations similar to the United States,13 and

    arbitrators (private judges).

    I begin with a discussion of the existing theories (attitudinal, strate-

    gic, organizational, economic, psychological, sociological, pragmatic, phe-

    nomenological, and legalist) of judicial behavior and of the evidence for

    and against each. These theories are expounded in a rich literature ig-

    nored by most academic lawyers (though this is changing14) and by vir-

    tually all judges.15

    The theories provide background and support to myown analysis, which draws heavily on labor economics and on the psy-

    chology of cognition and emotion. It is the stress I lay on psychology

    that has led me to entitle the bookHow Judges Thinkrather thanJudicial

    Behavior.

    My analysis and the studies on which it builds find that judges are not

    moral or intellectual giants (alas), prophets, oracles, mouthpieces, or

    calculating machines. They are all-too-human workers, responding as

    other workers do to the conditions of the labor market in which they

    work. American judges, at least, are not formalists, or (the term I prefer,

    as it carries less baggage) legalists. Legalists decide cases by applying

    preexisting rules or, in some versions of legalism, by employing alleg-

    edly distinctive modes of legal reasoning, such as legal reasoning byanalogy. They do not legislate, do not exercise discretion other than in

    ministerial matters (such as scheduling), have no truck with policy, and

    Introduction 7

    13. That is, nations that have an independent judiciary, as many do not. See, for exam-

    ple, Gretchen Helmke, Courts under Constraints: Judges, Generals, and Presidents in Argentina

    (2005);Law and Economic Development(Hans-Bernd Schfer and Angara V. Raja eds. 2006).

    14. See, for example, Gregory C. Sisk and Michael Heise, Judges and Ideology: Public and

    Academic Debates about Statistical Measures, 99 Northwestern University Law Review 743

    (2005).

    15. The richness is well illustrated by James L. Gibson, From Simplicity to Complexity:

    The Development of Theory in the Study of Judicial Behavior, 5Political Behavior7 (1983). As

    the date of his article shows, the literature has been around for many years. That it has not

    caught on with the legal professoriat may be in part because of its death of implications for the

    understanding or reform of legal doctrine and in part because it challenges the mystique of an

    apolitical judiciary, in which lawyers and law professors are heavily invested.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    12/24

    do not look outside conventional legal textsmainly statutes, constitu-tional provisions, and precedents (authoritative judicial decisions)for

    guidance in deciding new cases. For legalists, the law is an autonomous

    domain of knowledge and technique.16 Some legalists are even suspi-

    cious of precedent as a source of law, because it is infected by judicial

    creativity.

    But if judges are not legalists, what are they? Might they simply be

    politicians in robes? Empirical scholars have found that many judicial

    decisions, by no means limited to the Supreme Court, are strongly influ-

    enced by a judges political preferences or by other extralegal factors,

    such as the judges personal characteristics and personal and profes-

    sional experiences, which may shape his political preferences or operate

    directly on his response to a case. No responsible student of the judicialsystem supposes that politics (in a sense to be explained) or personal

    idiosyncrasy drivesmostdecisions, except in the Supreme Court, which

    indeed is largely a political court when it is deciding constitutional

    cases. Legalism drives most judicial decisions, though generally they are

    the less important ones for the development of legal doctrine or the im-

    pact on society.

    But one must be careful about dividing judicial decisions (or judges)

    into legalist and political, or, what is closely related, asserting a Mani-

    chaean dualism between law and politics. The dualism works only when

    law is equated to legalism, and that is too narrow. Justice Scalia was

    not stepping out of his proper role as a judge when he said inRichardson

    v. Marshthat the rule that juries are presumed to follow their instruc-tions is a pragmatic one, rooted less in the absolute certitude that the

    presumption is true than in the belief that it represents a reasonable

    practical accommodation of the interests of the state and the defendant

    in the criminal justice process.17 This is just as proper a judicial state-

    8 Introduction

    16. Legal formalists emphasize the specifically legal virtues of the clarity, determinacy, and

    coherence of law, and try to sharpen the distinction between legislation and adjudication.

    Roughly, they can be divided into rule-formalists and concept-formalists. The former place

    more value on determinacy, emphasizing the importance of clear rules and strict interpretation,

    while the latter emphasize the importance of system and principled coherence throughout the

    law. Thomas C. Grey, Judicial Review and Legal Pragmatism, 38 Wake Forest Law Review

    473, 478 (2003). Modern American formalistscomprising what one might call the School of

    Scaliaare mainly rule-formalists. Id. at 479. The most important thing [for Scalia] is that lawshould be put in the form of rules wherever possible. Id. at 499.

    17. 481 U.S. 200, 211 (1987).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    13/24

    ment as the legalist assertions for which Scalia (he of such pronounce-ments as that the rule of law is the law of rules18) is more famous.

    This is so even though the statement has political implications. Criminal

    defendants are at a disadvantage if a judges or prosecutors missteps can

    be forgiven by the judges telling the jury to disregard them, for the bell

    cannot be unrung; the jurors cannot exclude what they should not have

    heard from their consideration of the defendants guilt.

    Law in a judicial setting is simply the material, in the broadest

    sense, out of which judges fashion their decisions. Because the materials

    of legalist decision making fail to generate acceptable answers to all

    the legal questions that American judges are required to decide, judges

    perforce have occasionalindeed rather frequentrecourse to other

    sources of judgment, including their own political opinions or policyjudgments, even their idiosyncrasies. As a result, law is shot through

    with politics and with much else besides that does not fit a legalist

    model of decision making.

    The decision-making freedom that judges have is aninvoluntaryfree-

    dom. It is the consequence of legalisms inability in many cases to decide

    the outcome (or decide it tolerably, a distinction I shall elaborate), and

    the related difficulty, often impossibility, of verifying the correctness of

    the outcome, whether by its consequences or its logic. That inability,

    and that difficulty or impossibility, create an open area in which judges

    have decisional discretiona blank slate on which to inscribe their de-

    cisionsrather than being compelled to a particular decision by the

    law. How they fill in the open area is the fundamental question that thisbook addresses, though lurking in the background and occasionally

    coming to the fore is the question how theyshouldfill it in.

    Although judges often exercise a political judgment in the open area,

    political is an equivocal term that must be carefully parsed before it

    can be usefully applied to judicial behavior. It could refer to a judge

    whose decisions reflect his loyalty to a political party. It could refer to a

    judge whose decisions faithfully mirror the platform of a political party,

    though as a matter of conviction rather than of party loyalty. It could re-

    fer to a judge whose decisions reflect a consistent political ideology,

    which might be liberal or conservative and thus correlated (though

    Introduction 9

    18. Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 University of Chicago Law Re-

    view1175 (1989).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    14/24

    imperfectly) with the Democratic or Republican Party platform, butwhich might instead be an ideology embraced by neither major party,

    such as libertarianism or socialism. The empirical literature that refutes

    legalism as a complete or even approximate description of actual judicial

    behavior does not distinguish among these different gradations of po-

    litical. Political could even describe decisions based on purely techni-

    cal policy judgments, judgments that involve finding the best means to

    agreed-upon ends; any issue of governmental policy is in that sense po-

    litical. At the opposite extreme, a judge might be political in a sense

    divorced from policy: he might, like a legislator, use charm, guile, vote

    trading, and flattery to induce other judges to go along with him, though

    his aim might be to produce legalistic decisions. (He might thus be what

    is called in a variety of nonpolitical settings a good politician.) Thestrategic theory of judicial behavior, discussed in chapter 1, emphasizes

    political judging in this means rather than ends sense. Many legisla-

    tors have no policy preferences of their own, but are merely political

    brokers for their constituents. Judges, however, unless elected, do not

    have constituents.

    Ringing changes on the political might seem to exhaust the possible

    nonlegalist factors in adjudication. It does not begin to. The possible

    other factors (call them personal) include personality traits, or tem-

    perament (and thus emotionality at one end of the temperament spec-

    trum and emotional detachment at the other end), which are more or

    less innate personal characteristics. They include personal background

    characteristics, such as race and sex, and also personal and professionalexperience. The political or ideological factors that influence adjudi-

    cation may themselves be by-products of personal factors rather than

    products of an informed, disinterested, and coolly analytical study of

    public issues. Also figuring in judicial decisions arestrategic consider-

    ations, already alluded to, which need not be related to either the politi-

    cal views or the personal characteristics of a judge. A judge might join

    the majority opinion in a case not because he agreed with it but because

    he thought that dissenting publicly would magnify the effect of the ma-

    jority opinion by drawing attention to it. (Dissent aversion helps to

    explain, as we shall see in chapter 1, the puzzling effect of panel compo-

    sition on appellate decisions.)Institutionalfactorssuch as how clear or

    unclear the law is, salary and workload, and the structure of judicial pro-

    motionalso influence judicial behavior.

    10 Introduction

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    15/24

    1

    Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior

    There are many positive (that is, descriptive as distinct from normative)

    theories of judicial behavior.1 Their primary focus is, as one would ex-

    pect, on explaining judges decisions. The theories are the attitudinal,

    the strategic, the sociological, the psychological, the economic, the orga-

    nizational, the pragmatic, the phenomenological, and, of course, what I

    am calling the legalist theory. All the theories have merit and feed into

    the theory of decision making that I develop in this book. But all are

    overstated or incomplete. And missing from the welter of theoriesthe

    gap this book endeavors to fill, though in part simply by restating and

    refining the existing theoriesis a cogent, unified, realistic, and appro-

    priately eclectic account of how judges actually arrive at their decisions

    in nonroutine cases: in short, a positive decision theory of judging.I begin with the attitudinal theory,2 which claims that judges deci-

    19

    1. For reviews of the literature, see Lawrence Baum,Judges and Their Audiences: A Perspec-

    tive on Judicial Behavior, ch. 1 (2006); Barry Friedman, The Politics of Judicial Review, 84

    Texas Law Review 257 (2005). For an anthology suggestive of the diversity of the literature,

    see Supreme Court Decision-Making: New Institutionalist Approaches (Cornell W. Clayton and

    Howard Gillman eds. 1999).

    2. See, for example, Jeffrey A. Segal and Harold J. Spaeth,The Supreme Court and the Attitu-

    dinal Model Revisited(2002); Robert A. Carp and Ronald Stidham, Judicial Process in America

    294 (2001) (tab. 101); William N. Eskridge, Jr., and Lauren E. Baer, The Supreme Courts

    Deference Continuum: An Empirical Analysis (from Chevronto Hamdan) (Yale Law School,

    May 11, 2007); Andrew D. Martin, Kevin M. Quinn, and Lee Epstein, The Median Justice on

    the United States Supreme Court, 83 North Carolina Law Review 1275 (2005); Micheal W.

    Giles, Virginia A. Hettinger, and Todd Peppers, Picking Federal Judges: A Note on Policy andPartisan Selection Agendas, 54Political Research Quarterly623 (2001); Tracey E. George, De-

    veloping a Positive Theory of Decision Making on U.S. Courts of Appeals, 58Ohio State Law

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    16/24

    sions are best explained by the political preferences that they bring totheir cases. Most of the studies that try to test the theory infer judges

    political preferences from the political party of the President who ap-

    pointed them, while recognizing that it is a crude proxy. The emphasis

    is on federal judges, in particular Supreme Court Justices. State judges

    are of course not appointed by the President, and sometimes the method

    of their appointmentfor example, by nonpartisan electionmakes it

    difficult to classify them politically.3

    Justices and judges appointed by Democratic Presidents are predicted

    to vote disproportionately for liberal outcomes, such as outcomes fa-

    voring employees, consumers, small businessmen, criminal defendants

    (other than white-collar defendants), labor unions, and environmental,

    tort, civil rights, and civil liberties plaintiffs. Judges and Justices ap-pointed by Republican Presidents are predicted to vote disproportion-

    ately for the opposite outcomes.

    Other evidence of a judges political leanings is sometimes used in lieu

    of the party of the appointing President, such as preconfirmation editori-

    als discussing the politics or ideology of a judicial nominee.4 A neglected

    possibility is a fourfold classification in which the intermediate cate-

    gories would consist of judges appointed when the President and the

    Senate majority were of different parties (divided government). How-

    ever, Nancy Scherer finds no difference in the decisions of federal dis-

    trict judges appointed by divided versus united government,5 and I

    find only a small difference (as shown in Table 1 6) in the case of federal

    court of appeals judges appointed by Republican Presidents. But when

    20 The Basic Model

    Journal 1635, 1678 (1998). For criticism, see Frank B. Cross, Political Science and the New

    Legal Realism: A Case of Unfortunate Interdisciplinary Ignorance, 92Northwestern Law Re-

    view251 (1997); Barry Friedman, Taking Law Seriously, 4Perspectives on Politics261 (2006).

    3. Paul Brace, Laura Langer, and Melinda Gann Hall, Measuring the Preferences of State

    Supreme Court Judges, 62Journal of Politics 387 (2000); Carp and Stidham, note 2 above, at

    296297.

    4. Jeffrey A. Segal and Albert D. Cover, Ideological Values and the Votes of U.S. Supreme

    Court Justices, 83 American Political Science Review 557 (1989); Segal et al., Ideological

    Values and the Votes of U.S. Supreme Court Justices Revisited, 57 Journal of Politics 812

    (1995). See also Martin, Quinn, and Epstein, note 2 above, at 12851300.

    5. Nancy Scherer,Who Drives the Ideological Makeup of the Lower Federal Courts in a

    Divided Government? 35Law and Society Review191 (2001).

    6. Some of the classifications used in the data set from which the statistics in Tables 1 and 2

    are drawn are erroneous, such as classifying all votes for plaintiffs in intellectual property casesas liberal. I have corrected such errors; for the details of the corrections and a fuller analysis

    of the data, see William M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, Judicial Behavior: A Statistical Anal-

    ysis (University of Chicago Law School, Oct. 2007).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    17/24

    the President is a Democrat, it makes a significant difference whether the

    Senate is Democratic or Republican, probably because the Republican

    Party is more disciplined than the Democratic Party and therefore better

    able to organize opposition to a nominee.

    Table 2 is similar to Table 1 except limited to currently serving judges.

    Notice that the effects of divided government on judicial voting are more

    pronounced than in Table 1, consistent with the strong Republican push

    beginning with Reagan to tilt the ideological balance of the courts right-

    ward. Notice also that federal judicial decisions as a whole tilt toward

    Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior 21

    Table 1 Judicial Votes in Courts of Appeals as Function of United versus DividedPresidency and Senate, 19252002 (in percent)

    Republican President Democratic President

    VoteRepublican

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateRepublican

    Senate

    Conservative 55.8 55.9 49.6 55.3Liberal 37.1 35.9 43.5 37.9Mixed 7.1 8.2 6.8 6.8

    Sources: Appeals Court Attribute Data, www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/auburndata.htm

    (visited July 17, 2007);U.S. Court of Appeals Database,www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/

    appctdata.htm, www.wmich.edu/nsf-coa/ (visited July 17, 2007). Votes were weighted to

    reflect the different caseloads in the different circuits. Mixed refers to multi-issue cases in

    which the judge voted the liberal side of one or more issues and the conservative side of theother issue or issues.

    Table 2 Judicial Votes in Courts of Appeals as Function of United versus DividedPresidency and Senate, Judges Serving Currently (in percent)

    Republican President Democratic President

    VoteRepublican

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateRepublican

    Senate

    Conservative 66.9 63.2 49.7 57.0Liberal 25.6 27.0 39.5 35.6Mixed 7.5 9.8 10.9 7.5

    Sources: Appeals Court Attribute Data, www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/auburndata.htm(visited July 17, 2007);U.S. Court of Appeals Database,www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/

    appctdata.htm, www.wmich.edu/nsf-coa/ (visited July 17, 2007). Votes were weighted to

    reflect the different caseloads in the different circuits. Mixed refers to multi-issue cases in

    which the judge voted the liberal side of one or more issues and the conservative side of the

    other issue or issues.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    18/24

    the conservative end of the spectrum and that the tilt is more pro-

    nounced among currently serving judges.

    Presidents differ in their ideological intensity, and taking account of

    that difference can improve the accuracy of the attitudinal model. Seven

    of the nine current Supreme Court Justices were appointed by Republi-

    can Presidents, but it is more illuminating to note that four conservativeJustices were appointed by conservative Republicans (Scalia and Ken-

    nedy by Reagan, and Roberts and Alito by the second Bush), two liberal

    Justices by a Democratic President (Ginsburg and Breyer, appointed by

    Clinton), and one liberal and two conservative Justices appointed by

    moderate Republicans (Stevens by Ford, Souter and Thomas by the first

    Bush). See Table 3.

    There is also a divided-government effect in Supreme Court appoint-

    ments, as shown in Table 4.

    Whatever the method of determining a judges political inclinations,

    and whatever the level of the judiciary (Supreme Court, federal courts of

    appealson which there is now an extensive literature7or federal dis-

    22 The Basic Model

    Table 3 Ideology of Currently Serving Justices and the Appointing President

    Presidents Ideology

    Justices IdeologyConservativeRepublican

    ModerateRepublican Democratic

    Conservative 4 1 0Liberal 0 2 2

    Table 4 Conservative and Liberal Supreme Court Justices as Function of Unitedversus Divided Presidency and Senate, Justices Serving Currently

    Republican President Democratic President

    JusticeRepublican

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateDemocratic

    SenateRepublican

    Senate

    Conservative 3 2 0 0Liberal 0 2 2 0

    7. Christina L. Boyd, Lee Epstein, and Andrew D. Martin, Untangling the Causal Effects of

    Sex on Judging (Northwestern University School of Law and Washington University School of

    Law and Department of Political Science, July 28, 2007); Cass R. Sunstein et al., Are Judges Po-

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    19/24

    trict courts8

    ), the assumed inclinations are invariably found to explainmuch of the variance in judges votes on politically charged issues. The

    hotter the issue (such as abortion, which nowadays is much hotter than,

    say, criminal sentencing), the greater the explanatory power of the polit-

    ical variable. The attitudinal theory is further supported by the unques-

    tionable importance of politics in the appointment and confirmation of

    federal judges;9 by the intensity of congressional battles, almost always

    politically polarized, over the confirmation of federal judges and partic-

    ularly Supreme Court Justices; and by the experiences of lawyers and

    judges. Every lawyer knows that the accident of which judges of a court

    of appeals are randomly drawn to constitute the panel that will hear his

    case may determine the outcome if the case is controversial. Every judge

    is aware of having liberal and conservative colleagues whose reactions topolitically charged cases can be predicted with a fair degree of accuracy

    even if the judge who affixes these labels to his colleagues would not like

    to be labeled politically himself.

    Further evidence is the tendency of both Supreme Court Justices and

    court of appeals judges to time their retirement in such a way as to maxi-

    mize the likelihood that a successor will be appointed by a President of

    Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior 23

    litical? An Empirical Analysis of the Federal Judiciary (2006); Thomas J. Miles and Cass R.

    Sunstein, Do Judges Make Regulatory Policy? An Empirical Investigation ofChevron, 73Uni-

    versity of Chicago Law Review823 (2006); Ward Farnsworth, The Role of Law in Close Cases:

    Some Evidence from the Federal Courts of Appeals, 86 Boston University Law Review 1083

    (2006); Jeffrey A. Segal, Harold J. Spaeth, and Sara C. Benesh, The Supreme Court in the Ameri-

    can Legal System 236242 (2005); Daniel R. Pinello, Gay Rights and American Law (2003);

    Frank B. Cross, Decision Making in the U.S. Circuit Courts of Appeals, 91 California Law Re-

    view1457, 15041509 (2003); David E. Klein,Making Law in the United States Court of Appeals

    (2002); Emerson H. Tiller and Frank B. Cross, A Modest Proposal for Improving American

    Justice, 99 Columbia Law Review 215, 218226 (1999); George, note 2 above; Richard L.

    Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Ideology, and the D.C. Circuit, 83 Virginia Law Review

    1717 (1997); Sheldon Goldman, Voting Behavior on the United States Courts of Appeals Re-

    visited, 69American Political Science Review491 (1975). For an interesting case study of how

    the political preferences of court of appeals judges affect decisions, see Paul J. Wahlbeck, The

    Development of a Legal Rule: The Federal Common Law of Public Nuisance, 32Law and Soci-

    ety Review613 (1998).

    8. C. K. Rowland and Robert A. Carp, Politics and Judgment in Federal District Courts

    (1996); Gregory C. Sisk, Michael Heise, and Andrew P. Morriss, Charting the Influences on

    the Judicial Mind: An Empirical Study of Judicial Reasoning, 73New York University Law Re-

    view1377 (1998); Ahmed E. Taha, Judges Political Orientations and the Selection of Disputes

    for Litigation (Wake Forest University School of Law, Jan. 2007), http://ssrn.com/abstract=

    963468 (visited Sept. 2, 2007).9. On which see, for example, Lee Epstein and Jeffrey A. Segal,Advice and Consent: The Poli-

    tics of Judicial Appointments(2005); John R. Lott, Jr., The Judicial Confirmation Process: The

    Difficulty with Being Smart, 2Journal of Empirical Legal Studies407 (2005).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    20/24

    the same party as the one who appointed the retiring Justice.10

    Still an-other bit of evidence is what might be called ideology driftthe ten-

    dency of judges to depart from the political stance (liberal or conserva-

    tive) of the party of the President who appointed them the longer they

    serve.11 A judge closely aligned with the ideology of the party of the

    President who appointed him may fall out of that alignment as new, un-

    foreseen issues arise. A judge who was conservative when the burning

    issues of the day were economic may turn out to be liberal when the

    burning issues become ones of national security or social policy such as

    abortion or homosexual rights.

    There is more: the outcome of Supreme Court cases can be predicted

    more accurately by means of a handful of variables, none of which in-

    volves legal doctrine, than by a team of constitutional law experts.12

    While there is a high correlation between how a given federal appellate

    judge (court of appeals judge as well as Supreme Court Justice) votes for

    the government in nonunanimous (hence close) constitutional crimi-

    nal cases and in nonunanimous statutory criminal cases, there is a low

    correlation between the votes of different judges for and against the gov-

    ernment in criminal cases.13 Some judges have a progovernment lean-

    24 The Basic Model

    10. Ross M. Stolzenberg and James Lindgren, Politicized Departure from the United States

    Supreme Court (University of Chicago and Northwestern University, Mar. 18, 2007); James F.

    Spriggs and Paul J. Wahlbeck, Calling It Quits: Strategic Retirement on the Federal Courts of

    Appeals, 18931991, 48Political Research Quarterly573 (1995); Deborah J. Barrow and Gary

    Zuk, An Institutional Analysis of Turnover in the Lower Federal Courts, 19001987, 52 Jour-

    nal of Politics 457, 467468 (1990). Another straw in the wind is the surprising finding in a

    recent study that Supreme Court law clerks self-described political identity (Democratic or Re-

    publican) influences the political valence of their Justices votes. Todd C. Peppers and Christo-

    pher Zorn, Law Clerk Influence on Supreme Court Decision Making (Roanoke College, De-

    partment of Public Affairs, and University of South Carolina, Department of Political Science,

    June 14, 2007).

    11. See Andrew D. Martin and Kevin M. Quinn, Assessing Preference Change on the US

    Supreme Court, 23Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 365 (2007); Susan Haire, Be-

    yond the Gold Watch: Evaluating the Decision Making of Senior Judges on the U.S. Courts of

    Appeals (University of Georgia, Department of Political Science, 2006).

    12. Andrew D. Martin et al., Competing Approaches to Predicting Supreme Court Deci-

    sion Making, 2 Perspectives on Politics 761 (2004); Theodore W. Ruger et al., The Supreme

    Court Forecasting Project: Legal and Political Science Approaches to Predicting Supreme Court

    Decisionmaking, 104Columbia Law Review1150 (2004). The variables are (1) circuit of ori-

    gin; (2) issue area of the case; (3) type of petitioner (e.g., the United States, an employer, etc.);

    (4) type of respondent; (5) ideological direction (liberal or conservative) of the lower court rul-

    ing; and (6) whether the petitioner argued that a law or practice is unconstitutional. Id. at1163.

    13. Ward Farnsworth, Signatures of Ideology: The Case of the Supreme Courts Criminal

    Docket, 104Michigan Law Review67 (2005); Farnsworth, note 7 above.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    21/24

    ing, others a prodefendant leaning, and these leanings appear to be whatdrives their votes in close cases whether the case arises under the Con-

    stitution or under a statutethough from a legalist standpoint the text

    of the enactment being applied ought to drive the outcome, and there

    are huge textual differences between the Constitution and statutes. Apo-

    litical judges would not be expected to vote the same way in both types

    of case.

    All this is not to say thatalljudicial votes are best explained as politi-

    cally motivated,14 let alone that people become judges in order to nudge

    policy closer to their political goals. We shall see in subsequent chapters

    that to explain the political cast of judicial decisions does not require as-

    suming that judges have conscious political goals. No attitudinal study

    so finds, and data limitations cannot explain the shortfalls. Even at thelevel of the U.S. Supreme Court many cases do not involve significant

    political stakes, but that cannot be the entire explanation either. Think

    of Oliver Wendell Holmes. The publication of his correspondence after

    his death revealed that he was a rock-ribbed Republican, yet he voted re-

    peatedly to uphold liberal social legislation (such as the maximum-

    hours law at issue in theLochnercase, in which he famously dissented)

    that he considered socialist nonsense. He may of course have been an

    exception among Supreme Court Justices in this as in so many other re-

    spects. He may have few successors in point of political detachment in

    todays more politicized legal culture.

    We get a sense of the attitudinal models predictive limitations in Ta-

    bles 5 and 6, in which judicial votes that lack any political valence arecoded as other, and the liberal, conservative, mixed, and other votes

    are correlated with the party of the President who appointed the judge

    who cast the vote. Notice that apart from the substantial percentage of

    votes that were either mixed or other, a large percentage of conservative

    votes were cast by putatively liberal judges (judges appointed by Demo-

    cratic Presidents) and a large percentage of liberal votes were cast by pu-

    tatively conservative judges. Notice, as in the earlier tables, the apparent

    trend toward the increased politicization of court of appeals voting re-

    Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior 25

    14. See, for example, Cross, note 7 above; Cross, note 2 above, at 285311; Sunstein et al.,

    note 7 above; Daniel R. Pinello, Linking Party to Judicial Ideology in American Courts: A

    Meta-Analysis, 20Justice System Journal219 (1999); C. Neal Tate and Roger Handberg, Time

    Binding and Theory Building in Personal Attribute Models of Supreme Court Voting Behavior,191688, 35American Journal of Political Science460 (1991); Sheldon Goldman, Voting Be-

    havior on the United States Courts of Appeals Revisited, 69 American Political Science Review

    491 (1975).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    22/24

    sulting from judicial appointments by Republican Presidents. But no-

    tice, too, that the differences between the two types of judge, exhibited

    in the first two rows of the tables, though significant, are only partial.

    And a comparison just of means obscures the fact that the distributions

    overlap; some judges appointed by Republican Presidents are less con-

    servative than some appointed by Democratic Presidents. This does not

    refute the attitudinal model, but it does highlight the fact that the party

    of the appointing President is an imperfect proxy for a judges judicial

    ideology. One reason is that ideological issues important to judges need

    26 The Basic Model

    Table 5 Judicial Votes in Courts of Appeals as Function of Party of AppointingPresident, 19252002 (in percent)

    VoteRepublican

    PresidentDemocratic

    President

    Conservative 42.2 37.6Liberal 28.1 33.3Mixed 5.9 5.1Other 23.9 23.9

    Sources: Appeals Court Attribute Data, www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/auburndata.htm

    (visited July 17, 2007);U.S. Court of Appeals Database,www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/

    appctdata.htm, www.wmich.edu/nsf-coa/ (visited July 17, 2007). Votes were weighted to

    reflect the different caseloads in the different circuits. Mixed refers to multi-issue cases in

    which the judge voted the liberal side of one or more issues and the conservative side of the

    other issue or issues.

    Table 6 Judicial Votes in Courts of Appeals as Function of Party of AppointingPresident, Judges Serving Currently (in percent)

    VoteRepublican

    PresidentDemocratic

    President

    Conservative 51.2 42.5Liberal 22.9 33.1Mixed 7.3 7.6Other 18.7 16.9

    Sources: Appeals Court Attribute Data, www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/auburndata.htm

    (visited July 17, 2007);U.S. Court of Appeals Database,www.as.uky.edu/polisci/ulmerproject/appctdata.htm, www.wmich.edu/nsf-coa/ (visited July 17, 2007). Votes were weighted to

    reflect the different caseloads in the different circuits. Mixed refers to multi-issue cases in

    which the judge voted the liberal side of one or more issues and the conservative side of the

    other issue or issues.

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    23/24

    not have salience in political campaigns; capital punishment is a currentexample. Another reason is that judges pride themselves on being politi-

    cally independent rather than party animals.

    An explanation for the attitudinal models predictive limitations that

    would hold even if all decisions involved significant political stakes is

    that a case may pose a conflict between two political values, both of

    which are important to a judge, as when, for example, a civil rights suit

    (liberal) is brought challenging affirmative action (a conservative bte

    noire). One might think that in such a case the political considerations

    would cancel and the decision could be attributed to conventional legal

    reasoning. But no; the political considerations are unlikely to weigh

    equally in the judges mind, and if they do not, the heavier may deter-

    mine his decision. A notable example isBuchanan v. Warley.15

    Decided ata time when the Supreme Court was strongly disinclined to invalidate

    racially discriminatory laws, it nevertheless invalidated a southern ordi-

    nance that forbade blacks to live on any block in which whites were in

    the majority, and vice versa. The ordinance had blocked the plaintiff, a

    white, from selling property to a black. The Court distinguished mere

    social rightsthe right of blacks to associate with whites (and like-

    wise of whitesnotto associate with blacks, a right that the whites who

    remained in the neighborhood were denied), which the Court had re-

    fused to recognize inPlessy v. Fergusonfrom those fundamental rights

    in property that the Fourteenth Amendment was intended to secure to

    blacks on equal terms with whites.16 The distinction is not found in the

    equal protection clause. Michael Klarman argues persuasively that theCourt simply thought government interference with property rights a

    worse affront to personal liberty than segregation of schools and other

    public facilities, especially since the person complaining that his prop-

    erty rights were being infringed was the white seller.17 The upshot was

    that the Court issued a liberal decision, rejecting racial segregation in

    private housing.

    The attitudinalists traditional preoccupation with politically charged

    cases decided by the Supreme Court creates an exaggerated impression

    of the permeation of American judging by politics.18 Most cases decided

    Nine Theories of Judicial Behavior 27

    15. 245 U.S. 60 (1917).

    16. Id. at 79.17. Michael J. Klarman,Unfinished Business: Racial Equality in American Law 8384 (2007).

    18. Brian Leiter,Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Essays on American Legal Realism and Natural-

    ism in Legal Philosophy187, 188 n. 22, 192 (2007).

  • 8/14/2019 HOW JUDGES THINK

    24/24

    by American courts are neither politically charged nor decided in theSupreme Court. And to use the political party of the appointing Presi-

    dent as a proxy for a Justices political inclinations misleadingly implies

    thatpartisanpolitics pervades Supreme Court decision making. A Presi-

    dent invariably appoints most judges (usually more than 90 percent)

    from among members of his own political party, but once appointed they

    are more likely to want to be good judges than to want to toe anyones

    political line. You do not find judges saying, even to themselves, How

    would Bill Clinton [or George Bush, etc.], who appointed me, decide

    this case? Nevertheless, in the frequent cases in which a political judg-

    ment is required to close the deal because legalist analysis of the case

    leads nowhere, the judge is likely to lean toward the position that the

    political party to which he belongs (or belonged) would support, for it isusually not an accident that he belongs to that party rather than another.

    But lean toward is different from identify with. Supreme Court Jus-

    tices are political, but politically independent. Most of them, indeed, are

    outside (either more liberal or more conservative) the range bounded by

    the political preferences of the President and the Senate that confirmed

    them.19

    Anyamount of political judging challenges orthodox conceptions of

    the judicial process, however, and the attitudinalists have shown that

    there is plenty at all levels of the American judiciary (though more, the

    higher the level). Yet their findings, while heresy to the legal establish-

    ment, have the paradoxical effect of blunting criticisms of the courts as

    acting undemocratically when they invalidate legislative and executiveacts. As explained by Mark Graber,

    Judicial review is established and maintained by elected officials. Adju-dication is one of many means politicians and political movements em-ploy when seeking to make their constitutional visions the law ofthe land. Elected officials provide vital political foundations for judi-cial power by creating constitutional courts, vesting those courts withjurisdiction over constitutional questions, staffing those courts withjudges prone to exercising judicial power, assisting or initiating litiga-tion aimed at having those courts declare laws unconstitutional, andpassing legislation that encourages justices to make public policy inthe guise of statutory or constitutional interpretation. Judicial review

    28 The Basic Model

    19. Michael Bailey and Kelly H. Chang, Comparing Presidents, Senators, and Justices:

    Interinstitutional Preference Estimation, 17Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 477,

    508 (2001).