on the plausibility of a strong transcendental response to...

179
On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to Scepticism Rosemary Jane Smith PhD University of York Philosophy May, 2015

Upload: others

Post on 08-Oct-2020

1 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

On the Plausibility of a

Strong Transcendental

Response to Scepticism

Rosemary Jane Smith

PhD

University of York

Philosophy

May, 2015

Page 2: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

2

Abstract

I argue that the strong transcendental strategy can offer us a serious and robust response the

sceptic who doubts that we can have knowledge of the extra-mental.

This sceptic is motivated by sceptical hypotheses to worry that I could have all the

thoughts and experiences I do in fact have if the world were radically different to how I take it

to be. Transcendental arguments start from a premise about our thoughts or experience and

move on to show that something must be the case because it is a necessary condition of our

having such thoughts or experience. As such, transcendental arguments are particularly well-

positioned to answer this sceptic, as the premises of a transcendental argument are drawn from

the mental propositions the sceptic accepts.

Some philosophers have argued that the same concerns that drive the sceptic to doubt

the extra-mental should also give her cause to doubt the mental. To prevent the sceptic

retreating to this thought, I show that these arguments are only effective against propositions

that were unlikely to form the basis of a transcendental argument.

Strong transcendental arguments (STAs) are differentiated from weak transcendental

arguments as being those that move from mental premises to conclusions about the extra-

mental world. I defend STAs against Stroud‘s objection that this is not possible, on the basis

that the objection rests on an illicit assumption of dualism about mind and world. I argue for

the plausibility of supervenience physicalism as a metaphysical picture upon which such

inferences would be possible.

I show how a dispositionally essentialist understanding of the laws of nature would

plausibly support a metaphysically necessary psychophysical law, from which we could draw

the bridging premise of an STA. This changes the dialectic, forcing the sceptic to defend

specific metaphysical positions, such as resemblance nominalism, and to engage substantially

with philosophy. The plausibility of strong transcendental arguments tells us something of

what must be true of the world for the sceptic‘s arguments to even get started.

Page 3: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

3

ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................................. 2

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ............................................................................................................................. 7

AUTHOR’S DECLARATION ......................................................................................................................... 8

CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................................................... 9

1.1 SCEPTICISM DEFINED .................................................................................................................... 9

1.2 SCEPTICISM, APPEARANCE, AND REALITY IN LITERATURE ..................................................................... 13

1.3 A POTTED HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL SCEPTICISM ........................................................................... 16

1.3.4 SIXTH CENTURY BC—JAINIST EPISTEMOLOGY ......................................................................................... 19

1.3.2 FIFTH CENTURY BC—SOCRATIC SCEPTICISM ........................................................................................... 19

1.3.3 FOURTH OR SIXTH CENTURY BC—LAOZI ................................................................................................ 20

1.3.4 FOURTH CENTURY BC TO THIRD CENTURY AD—PYRRHONIAN SCPETICISM .................................................. 21

1.3.5 THIRD TO FIRST CENTURY BC—ACADEMIC SCEPTICS ................................................................................ 22

1.3.6 FOURTH CENTURY AD—AUGUSTINE ..................................................................................................... 23

1.3.7 MEDIEVAL SCEPTICISM ........................................................................................................................ 23

1.4 SCEPTICISM AS AN ENDURING CONCERN .......................................................................................... 25

1.5 TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS AS A RESPONSE TO SCEPTICISM ............................................................ 26

CHAPTER 2: TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS ........................................................................................ 30

2.1 THE TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION ................................................................................................ 30

2.2 KANT’S COPERNICAN TURN .......................................................................................................... 32

2.3 THE REFUTATION OF IDEALISM ...................................................................................................... 35

2.3.1 TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM AND MATERIAL IDEALISMS ............................................................................ 35

2.3.2 THE PROOF ........................................................................................................................................ 36

2.3.3 THE KANTIAN AND CARTESIAN ‘I AM’ ............................................................................................. 38

2.3.4 TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM, BERKELEYAN IDEALISM, AND SCEPTICISM ....................................................... 41

2.4 AUSTIN ................................................................................................................................... 45

Page 4: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

4

2.5 STRAWSON: INDIVIDUALS ............................................................................................................ 48

2.6 STRAWSON’S TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION AND THE BOUNDS OF SENSE ............................................... 50

2.7 STROUD AND TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS .................................................................................. 52

2.7.1 TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS AS ANTI-SCEPTICAL ................................................................................. 53

2.7.2 GOALS FOR TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS ............................................................................................ 55

2.7.3 STRAWSON: NATURALISM AND SCEPTICISM ............................................................................................ 56

2.7.4 STROUD AND WEAK TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS................................................................................ 57

2.7.5 STROUD’S TAXONOMY OF TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS ........................................................................ 59

2.8 WHY A STRONG TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENT IS NEEDED TO ADDRESS MY SCEPTIC ................................. 60

2.8.1 AGAINST WEAK TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS ..................................................................................... 61

2.8.2 STRAWSONIAN WEAK TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS ............................................................................. 62

2.9 CONCLUSION ............................................................................................................................ 63

CHAPTER 3: WHAT’S SO SPECIAL ABOUT THE MENTAL? ........................................................................ 64

3.1 INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................................................... 64

3.2 DOUBTING ONE’S OWN MIND ...................................................................................................... 65

3.3 EMOTION ................................................................................................................................. 66

3.3.1 ANTICIPATED AND REMEMBERED EMOTION ............................................................................................ 67

3.3.2 LINGUISTIC VAGUENESS ....................................................................................................................... 68

3.3.3 DISTINGUISHING MOODS AND EMOTIONS .............................................................................................. 69

3.3.4 PRESENTLY FELT EMOTIONS.................................................................................................................. 70

3.4 VISUAL EXPERIENCE .................................................................................................................... 73

3.4.1 ‘I THINK I CAN PROTRUDE MY TONGUE WITHOUT ITS COMING OUT’ ............................................................. 73

3.4.2 ‘I SEE A SEAL AS MY SISTER’ ................................................................................................................... 74

3.4.3 ‘I THINK I SEE A RED CARPET THAT’S NOT RED’ .......................................................................................... 75

3.4.4 INTROSPECTION, INTROSPECTIVE JUDGEMENTS, AND NEUROSURGEONS FROM ALPHA CENTAURI ..................... 78

3.4.5 BLINDSIGHT ....................................................................................................................................... 80

3.5 PERIPHERAL AND FOVEAL VISION ................................................................................................... 80

3.6 THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF THOUGHT .............................................................................................. 83

3.7 THE GENERAL ARGUMENT ........................................................................................................... 84

3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY .................................................................................... 85

3.9 THE ARGUMENT FOR INCORRIGIBILITY ............................................................................................. 87

Page 5: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

5

3.10 THE SUPERSTITIOUS MAN .......................................................................................................... 89

3.11 CAPGRAS SYNDROME ................................................................................................................ 91

3.12 CONCLUSION........................................................................................................................... 95

CHAPTER 4: MIND IN WORLD—STRONG TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS WITHOUT A CHASM OF

NECESSITY ............................................................................................................................................... 96

4.1 STROUD, TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS, AND THE VERIFICATION PRINCIPLE ........................................... 97

4.2 THE BRIDGE OF NECESSITY ........................................................................................................... 99

4.3 TRUE OF THE MIND VS TRUE OF THE WORLD ................................................................................... 100

4.4 AN OBJECTION: THE PSYCHOLOGICAL AND NON-PSYCHOLOGICAL ARE DIFFERENT CATEGORIES OF FACT ......... 102

4.5 MIND IN WORLD ...................................................................................................................... 103

4.6 SUBSTANCE DUALISM ................................................................................................................ 103

4.7 MONISM AND IDEALISM ............................................................................................................. 105

4.8 TRANSCENDENTAL IDEALISM ........................................................................................................ 106

4.9 PHYSICALISM ........................................................................................................................... 107

4.9.1 DEFINING PHYSICALISM ..................................................................................................................... 107

4.9.2 DEFENDING SUPERVENIENCE PHYSICALISM: DIFFERING MENTALLY WHILST NOT DIFFERING PHYSICALLY ......... 108

4.9.3 DEFENDING SUPERVENIENCE PHYSICALISM: INDETERMINISM ................................................................... 111

4.10 SUPERVENIENCE, THE COMPLETENESS OF PHYSICS, AND COLOURED FILTERS .......................................... 113

4.11 WHAT IS ‘PHYSICS’ AND WHY IS IT COMPLETE? .............................................................................. 115

4.12 SUPERVENIENCE VIA ENTAILMENT ............................................................................................... 116

4.13 MULTIPLE REALISEABILITY ......................................................................................................... 118

4.14 CONCLUSION.......................................................................................................................... 119

CHAPTER 5: METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY AND THE LAWS OF NATURE .................................................. 121

5.1 THE SECOND PREMISE ................................................................................................................ 122

5.2 LAWS OF NATURE AND THE HUMEAN DICTUM ................................................................................. 123

5.3 NECESSITY, ANALYTICITY, AND THE A POSTERIORI ............................................................................. 126

5.4 DISPOSITIONAL ESSENTIALISM AND SCIENTIFIC REALISM ..................................................................... 128

5.5 LAWS AND PROPERTIES ............................................................................................................... 133

5.6 BIRD’S ESSENTIALISM ................................................................................................................. 137

Page 6: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

6

5.7 DISPOSITIONAL ESSENTIALISM AND REALISM ABOUT UNIVERSALS ......................................................... 139

5.8 DISPOSITIONS .......................................................................................................................... 144

5.9 FINKS, ANTIDOTES, AND MIMICS .................................................................................................. 146

5.10 REPAIRING THE CONDITIONAL ANALYSIS: CETERIS PARIBUS LAWS ....................................................... 147

5.11 FUNDAMENTAL DISPOSITIONS CANNOT BE FINKISH.......................................................................... 148

5.12 THE METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY OF LAWS OF NATURE ....................................................................... 151

5.13 FINKISH DISPOSITIONS, PSYCHOPHYSICAL LAWS, AND THE SCEPTIC ...................................................... 154

5.14 NECESSITARIANISM ABOUT LAWS ................................................................................................ 158

5.15 REGULARITY AND DISPOSITIONAL ESSENTIALISM ............................................................................. 161

5.16 CONCEIVABILITY AND THE ILLUSION OF NOMIC CONTINGENCY ............................................................ 161

5.17 CONCLUSION.......................................................................................................................... 163

CONCLUSION ......................................................................................................................................... 165

BIBLIOGRAPHY ...................................................................................................................................... 167

Page 7: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

7

Acknowledgements

Acknowledgement is due to a great many people who have joined me

on this eight year Odyssey into the transcendental.

To my supervisor, Tom Stoneham, for his insightful guidance,

questioning, and support. To David Efird, for introducing me to

Donald Davidson and helping me realise that what excited me about

the argument from triangulation was its transcendental form.

To the members of my thesis advisory panel. To Andrew Ward, for

his probing questions and challenging me to a deeper understanding of

Kant. To James Clarke, for his support and encouragement, for sharing

my interest in transcendental arguments, and for offering me a

different perspective on them.

Special thanks to Julie Kay, who has helped me in ways

innumerable and been a bastion of support and knowledge in the battle

against university systems.

To those kind friends and strangers whose donations kept a roof

over my head in these final months: Marcus Smith, Edward Allison,

Shelley MacGregor, Steve Cooke, Alice Pember, Heath Graham,

Amanda Snyder, Jessica Meats, Lee Harris, Greg Eden, Paul Spirito,

and all those who wished to remain anonymous.

To my parents for their support, financial and personal, and to the

rest of my family, for their tolerance.

Finally, to Steve Cooper, Clare Wall, and Fred Prior, without whose

friendship and support I would not have made it.

Page 8: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

8

Author’s Declaration

I declare that this thesis is a presentation of original work of which I am the sole author. It has

not been previously presented for an award at this university or any other. All sources are

acknowledged as references.

Page 9: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

9

Chapter 1: Introduction

And now, after all paths (as people are persuading themselves), have been tried in vain,

there prevails in the sciences a weariness and utter indifferentism, which is the mother

of chaos and night—yet is also the source, or at least the prelude, of their approaching

reform and enlightenment after ill-applied diligence has left them dark, confused, and

useless.

For it is futile to try to feign indifference concerning inquiries whose object

cannot be indifferent to human nature. (Kant A x1)

Kant refers to the plight of metaphysics, for which he charts a rocky history, from which, he

tells us, philosophers ultimately gave up, viewing all paths as exploited and found wanting,

becoming indifferent in the face of apparently irresolvable difficulties (Kant A ix–x).

A similar indifferentism towards scepticism has arisen in modern times. Metaphysics is

only considered lost by certain factions, but there is a general belief that in the question of

what is to be known about the nature of reality, we shall only begin to make progress if the

sceptic is ignored. Thus, epistemology, when it deals with the sceptic at all, focuses its

energies on giving us reasons to dismiss her, instead of answering her.

I do not think the sceptic‘s incessant questioning can be so easily dismissed. I find that

she still wants an answer, and I still want to give it to her.

1.1 Scepticism Defined

There is more than one type of scepticism, so I will start by defining the kind of scepticism

that interests me. I am perfectly willing to concede that there are some kinds of scepticism we

are entitled to ignore, and some which it would be wrong to suggest the philosophical

mainstream pretends any kind of indifferentism towards. Moral and religious scepticism have

become very popular, and it is not only regarded as common, but relatively unproblematic to

be sceptical about moral absolutes or the existence of God. Scepticism about objective

1 References to Kant will be to the 1781 (A) and 1787 (B) editions of the Critique of Pure Reason. Translation is

from the Pluhar (1996).

Page 10: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

10

standards for beauty or art are similarly respectable positions. Which is not to suggest that they

do not have their detractors. Rather, they are not subject to the same kind of scorn that the kind

of scepticism that concerns me is subjected to. I speak of the sceptical worry that we cannot

have any knowledge of non-mental objects. This is a sceptic who examines the evidence of her

sensory experience and concludes that it might have been caused by a world greatly different

from that which appears to be present in her experience, or that she believes to exist. Having

considered certain sceptical scenarios, she finds that all the evidence available to her could just

as easily have existed had she been dreaming, or the victim of a malicious demon‘s

fabrication, or, most worrying of all, that she might have been an isolated solipsistic

consciousness who, in her madness, hallucinates the experience of a non-mental world that

does not exist at all.

It is this last hypothesis that most directly concerns me. I think it is the most worrying,

but also the most plausible. Although others doubt its success, I am satisfied with the cogito,

or some version of it at least, and that I cannot intelligibly doubt my own existence. I do not

think my thoughts are in fact being had by an evil demon, even if I am otherwise the benighted

fool of such a creature; without the ability to generate doubt for my own existence, positing an

evil demon would mean that there is at least one other being in existence beyond me, even if

they are evil. It is rather more worrying that I might be entirely alone. Similarly, a dreamer

who is sometimes awake and has a physical body in some real world is better off than the

deluded solipsistic consciousness.

Nevertheless, I think these other hypotheses can be valuable in allowing us to explore

the capabilities for fabrication of the solipsistic, purely mental consciousness. As Descartes

realised, dreams are an altered state of mind we all experience regularly, informing our

understanding of the great variety of falsehoods we can be brought to believe.

Ernest Sosa (2007), has argued that we cannot have beliefs in dreams, that all we have

are imaginings, but I hold, with Ichikawa (2008: 523), that even if this is so, the ‗quasi-

affirmation‘ that takes the place of belief in imaginings is subjectively indistinguishable from

beliefs when one is dreaming. Similarly, for the general disjunctivist thought that there is

something fundamentally different about veridical perceptions and the content of dreams,

imaginings, and hallucinations. One may insist as one likes that veridical perception is

significantly different from dreaming, or that one knows one is not dreaming or hallucinating

when one is under normal or optimal waking conditions, but when I am dreaming I have no

Page 11: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

11

such knowledge. Some have experienced lucid dreaming—a state in which they are asleep and

dreaming and they know that this is the case. I congratulate them on their good fortune; I have

never had this pleasure. I have, however, dreamt that I had woken up when I was still

dreaming. I have even run certain tests upon myself and either believed that I had passed them

or made some excuse for why they failed.

In fact, I think I very much do have beliefs in dreams, but for the purposes of

argument, I think it may be stipulated. The sceptic who concerns me thinks I might have all

the beliefs and experiences I do in fact have even if the world were radically different. I think

she deserves a robust response. I think her sceptical scenarios are prima facie plausible, and

cannot be dismissed solely on the basis that I can tell, really, when my experiences are real.

Nothing hangs on the mechanism of dreaming or hallucination. What concerns me is

that there seems to have been persistent doubt, throughout history, about the relationship

between our sensory experience and the external world. A concern that such experience might

be generated by one‘s own mind, or some other mechanism via which that which appears to

our senses is not that which it appears to be.

I avoid the term ‗external world‘ scepticism, although I think what is generally meant

by that term matches the doubt that concerns me. My discomfort with the term ‗external‘ lies

in the ambiguity concerning what is and what is not ‗external‘. Does it mean ‗external to the

self‘? Defining the self is a complex quest with oft disputed results. If one identifies the self

with one‘s body there is a clear conflict with the sort of scepticism that doubts the existence of

a physical world. Does it mean ‗external to the mind‘? Well, then we run the risk of begging

the question against cognitive extension advocates, like Andy Clark (see his 2008), who

maintain that many of our cognitive resources may be located outside the body. For example,

some of my memory might be said to be stored ‗external‘ to my body, on my computer, where

I keep my notes. The scepticism that concerns me is worried that there might not be any

computer existing distinct from my mind; this is only a concern for the cognitive extension

advocate if he already accepts that the computer is not a purely mental object. I would expect

most cognitive extension theorists to have such a commitment, but to force them into a

question begging position if they are worried by the sort of scepticism that concerns me seems

unnecessarily restrictive. Words like ‗external‘ and ‗internal‘ are evocative of physical

distinctions, or a distinction between the mind and the physical, and are therefore confusing.

Page 12: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

12

I shall thus talk of the ‗mental‘ and the ‗non-mental‘ or ‗extra-mental‘, rather than the

‗internal‘ and the ‗external‘. This should clarify that the concern is specifically that

propositions concerning non-mental objects2 are not known with the same degree of certainty

that seems available to at least some propositions concerning mental objects or properties. The

worry will encompass doubts about the existence of non-mental entities without begging the

question for theories of mind that assume mind-body identity, or even that the mind may

extend to objects external to the body.

This is the form of scepticism towards which there seems to be a peculiar kind of

indifferentism. This is the position against which we are told we argue without an opponent;

anyone who claims to be a sceptic of this kind is accused either of insanity or insincerity.

Hume (ECHU 5.1.34)3 is right that it is not a doubt that is evinced in my everyday behaviour.

When I make a cup of tea I seem to assume that the kettle, mug, water, and teabag are all

there; that the laws of physics hold, that the electricity in the kettle‘s element will heat the

water and that the application of hot water to the teabag will cause the chemical reaction that

we call an infusion of tea. Trust—in a very great deal—is a necessary part of survival, and

hence continued existence in the world as a human being. Yet I am convinced that it is as

much a part of human nature to worry quite seriously about scepticism from time to time as it

is to operate as though those doubts were unjustified at every moment for which they are not

called to mind. Trust is rarely an attitude consciously avowed in a continuous manner. Indeed,

trust is only a sensible attitude where there is reason to doubt. Otherwise we there would be no

need for trust, as we would have knowledge.

The ‗sceptic‘ is almost always talked about in inverted commas. No one, we are told, is

really a sceptic. She is either someone we falsely believe we must defend our positions

against, or she is a hypothesised opponent against whose imagined critiques we test our

theories. However, I do not think this reflects reality as well as it has been the habit of modern

philosophers to assert.

2 Or, objects matching non-mental descriptions, or objects with non-mental properties. It is my hope that there are

at least some objects matching non-mental descriptions or possessed of non-mental properties, that also have

mental properties or match mental descriptions.

3 References to the Hume (1748 and 1777), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, are given by

‗ECHU‘.

Page 13: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

13

I argue both that the sceptic can be found in real human beings who have claimed to be

sceptics in the past, and that, for many of us, consistently and throughout philosophical

history, the sceptic is a live and serious part of ourselves. In this second guise, the sceptic is

not an external opponent, real or imagined. I do not claim that as we go about our daily

business we fail to believe or make knowledge claims in a normal manner. Rather, in our daily

lives we trust that we are in a good epistemic position to make knowledge claims or declare

our beliefs reasonable. This trust is natural, as Hume suggests, and sensible, for we seem to

have no alternative basis upon which to make decisions about how to act. It is not inconsistent

with possession of a general disposition to think and act as if there is a world outside one‘s

own mind for one to worry that one does not actually have good reason for doing so, from

time to time. Moreover, such worry can be found both with the layperson who finds herself

momentarily provoked by such worry, and with the serious philosopher.

1.2 Scepticism, Appearance, and Reality in Literature

Evidence that laypeople share these moments of worry is not merely anecdotal. It is evident in

the continued popularity of films like Inception (Nolan 2010), The Matrix (Wachowski and

Wachowski 1999), eXistenZ (Cronenberg 1999), The Truman Show (Weir 1998) etc., which

capture the popular imagination by offering us literal presentations of sceptical hypotheses,

asking how we know that we are not currently dreaming or that our experiences are not being

fabricated by a computer or an evil scientist. Moreover, concern with the relationship of

appearance to reality is a recurring theme in literature, and especially in film and theatre,

where the audience is asked to ‗suspend disbelief‘ and accept as true the fictions that play

before them, even as each viewer must know that before them are actors merely playing at

being the characters they present, effects that merely represent the events the writer and

director sought to evoke.

It is no coincidence that the phrase ‗Cartesian Theatre‘ has come to represent the

theory of mind in which mental images are displayed to a watching subject, as the theatre

provides a familiar example of a person who willingly takes themselves to be absorbed in

something they know to be a mere imitation of reality. (Although, one should not suppose

from this that having a concern about discrepancies between appearance and reality entails

acceptance of the Cartesian Theatre model of mind.)

Page 14: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

14

The phrase ‗willing suspension of disbelief‘ originally comes from Coleridge (2004)

and refers to an act of ‗poetic faith‘ in relation to lyrical ballads. It is today much more

familiar in the discussion of film and theatre, often quoted in discussions of theatre

practitioner Stanislavski‘s naturalism4, which advocates rendering ‗what ifs‘ as ‗as ifs‘, see,

for example, Bailey (2011: 139). Stanislavski (1961: 247) describes ‗the great difference

between nature and postcards… between a thought image and physical contact‘, and yet he

also asserts ‗in every psychological act there is a great deal of the physical‘ (Stanislavski

(1961: 225)), indicating that although he marks the difference between mental presentation

and physical reality, he also sees the two as inextricably linked. One who practices

Stanislavski‘s naturalism (which has become the norm for most of our film and television) is

in a constant attempt to reduce the barrier between appearance and reality.

Yet, the drive to resist absorbing oneself within illusion as though it were reality also

has a respectable theatrical tradition. The practitioner, Brecht, rejects such ‗naturalism‘ as not

only failing to bridge the gap between the world of the play and the real world, but as allowing

for deceit and manipulation of an audience that should be alert and critical, alienated from the

text by a variety of distancing techniques (Verfremdungseffekt), conscious that the play is a

mere representation, allowing for analysis and judgement (see Brecht 1961).

Always in the theatre is this question of whether the artifice should be allowed to

interfere with the absorption; whether the audience can ever really be a part of the world of the

play. The ‗play within the play‘ is often used to confront the audience with their own

relationship to illusion. Hamlet is a particularly striking example. Its ostensive purpose within

the play is to echo the real events of Hamlet‘s father‘s murder by his uncle, prompting

Claudius, ‗frighted by false fire‘ to reveal his guilt (Shakespeare 1997, Hamlet: III.ii).

However, its tropes of illusion and reality are enmeshed in the play‘s themes of trust and

deceit; appearance and reality; existential doubt; and death, the unknown country. Hamlet‘s

metaphor, ‗frighted by false fire‘, underscores how we can be prompted to react to illusion just

as we would to veridical experience. Hamlet‘s great soliloquies are exquisite explorations of

human doubt, as Hamlet hesitates to act when he does not know what to believe. While few of

us are faced with the choice of whether to believe the word of a ghost, or challenged to avenge

4 ‗Naturalism‘ here refers to the theatrical practice of creating a performance that is as similar to reality as

possible, and should not be confused with philosophical naturalism.

Page 15: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

15

our fathers, the agony of acting on imperfect information is a fundamental human experience

that has kept the interest of audiences through centuries and across continents5.

Fear of madness and an inability to tell appearance from reality is also a classic theme

of horror, and one upon which Hitchcock drew heavily. His film, Vertigo (Hitchcock, 1958), is

named for a dizzying experience produced by a distortion of the senses and deals directly with

the unsettlingly blurred line between sanity, dreams, nightmares, and madness: the inability to

tell appearance from reality.

In this way we can see that even films and plays that do not deal directly with sceptical

hypotheses show a repeated concern with our inability to tell whether the world matches our

beliefs about it. The fact that this worry is used by masters of their crafts in some of their most

seminal works to evoke memorable scenes of existential angst (Hamlet) and psychological

horror (Vertigo) should suggest to us that something central to the human psyche is being

tapped into, and not merely an esoteric doubt restricted to the overly philosophical thinker.

The evidence of such sustained concern shows that scepticism is not a ‗merely‘ philosophical

worry of little relevance to ‗ordinary‘ people.

On the other hand, it may be tempting to think that such evidence is no reason to think

that the philosopher should be concerned by such things. After all, a film like Inception is not

really a good exploration of the dreaming argument. It might be thought that the ‗common

man‘ does not seriously worry about such things, but rather enjoys titillating his faculties in

the same way that he enjoys watching a horror film, which provokes fear, but from which he

knows he is never really in any danger. Perhaps this is true for some, although in general it

seems to me a rather patronising view of the non-philosopher (or rather, the untrained

philosopher, as I am inclined to think that all people engage in philosophy with varying

degrees of rigour). Nevertheless, it would be well to demonstrate that there has been sustained

philosophical concern for scepticism, too.

5 Whilst an exact figure for the number of translations of Hamlet is hard to come by, its cross-culture popularity

is remarkable, with translations including Arabic, Japanese, Romanian, Yiddish, Zulu, Korean, and Indian

languages, as well as Esperanto and even Klingon, suggesting that we project an enduring relevance for the play

and its themes into our future as well as relating it to the present. (See Litvin 2011, Anzai 1999, Cinpoeðs 2010,

Berkowitz 2002, Huang 2011, and Shakespeare 2000)

Page 16: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

16

1.3 A Potted History of Philosophical Scepticism

Scepticism has a long history of being taken quite seriously by very serious thinkers, and an

almost equally long history of those thinkers being scoffed at for doing so. Thus Hobbes

writes in his first objection to Descartes:

But since Plato and other ancient philosophers discussed this uncertainty relating to the

objects of the senses, and since the difficulty of distinguishing the waking state from

dreams is common knowledge, I am sorry that Descartes, who is an outstanding

original thinker, should be publishing this old stuff. (Hobbes in Bennett 2007: 42)

It is tempting to regard outlying individuals as exceptions, like Peter Unger (see his 2003

Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism), who stands in near isolation6 in the modern discourse,

arguing that no one knows anything or can even be said to reasonably believe anything (Unger

2003: 1). It is easy to dismiss an individual as performing some error that leads them to

believe themselves a sceptic when they are not really. Thus, C H Whiteley (1975: 490) chides

Unger for insisting on a falsely absolutist standard for mental states like ‗knowing‘ and

‗believing‘. Unger argues that we must devise alternate terms for less absolute states, but

Whiteley replies: ‗Don‘t the required non-absolute modes of speech already exist?‘ (ibid.).

It is easy to tell one man his attempt to revive scepticism is merely a redefinition of

terms—that scepticism is not really worrying as we never demanded certainty for knowledge

in the first place. It is often said that the illusory nature of scepticism is evident in the fact that

no sane person could be said to believe it. Thus, Whiteley (1975: 489) asks of Unger ‗How

can anyone sanely hold these views?‘. I would turn this on its head and ask: if Unger sanely

holds these views, can we still judge them mad? Or unholdable by the sane? Ah, but Unger is

not really a sceptic, it will be said, he does believe in knowledge as we commonly understand

it, he has just been illicitly redefining knowledge as something much stricter than what we

commonly mean.

Let us call this the ‗Argument from Sanity‘, made explicit, it runs like this:

1. A sane person is able to live successfully

6 Bryan Frances has also made a foray into scepticism in his 2005, Scepticism Comes Alive; I could find no

reviews or responses to this, so have focused on the discussion of Unger.

Page 17: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

17

2. Living successfully involves making judgements, and taking action based on these

judgements, to preserve one‘s life7

3. One could not make and act on judgements that preserved life unless one takes at least

some of our beliefs to be justified and true89

4. Therefore, in order to live successfully, I must take myself to have at least some

justified, true beliefs (arguably quite a few)

5. Therefore, in order to be sane, I must take myself to have at least some justified, true

beliefs

6. Therefore, anyone who does not take themselves to have at least some justified, true

beliefs is not sane

7. The sceptic denies that any of her beliefs are justified

8. Therefore, the sceptic cannot be sane

9. I live successfully

10. Therefore, I am sane

11. Therefore, I am not a sceptic

It is worth noting that either living successfully or being sane suffices as proof of not being a

sceptic on this argument. I think often it is tacitly supposed that one cannot live successfully if

one is not sane, but this is not the case. One in four people live with some kind of mental

illness (McManus et al 2009), yet only 23,531 people (Care Quality Commission 2015: 34)

were detained under section three of the UK Mental Health Act, as being a danger to

themselves or others, in 2013–14, suggesting that far fewer than one in four people are unable

to live their lives successfully due to mental illness (0.0004% of the population). Obviously

the criteria for being sectioned under the Mental Health Act are not the criteria I have given

here for unsuccessful living, so the point is not as powerful as it could be, but I think this

simply underscores how unhelpful it is for philosophers to dismiss each others‘ opinions in

terms of mental illness. I would suggest that the philosophical habit of dismissing positions as

impossible to sanely hold is a vague, misleading, and unproductive practice as a whole.

7 For added impact, one might add further conditions, such as that the actions I take should preserve my comfort

and promote my happiness.

8 If we are good Humeans we might say that the actions of a successful life are motivated by the desire to

preserve one‘s life and the belief that an action will preserve one‘s life; the desire for the action to facilitate

successful life will make us desire to have beliefs that are justified and true.

9 I am running this argument on justified, true belief, rather than knowledge, as that is the minimal claim. If the

argument works for justified, true belief, it should work for knowledge if the requirements for knowledge include

true, justified belief. However, the definition of knowledge is contentious, and depending on one‘s take on

‗justification‘ a true belief might be justified and not count as knowledge.

Page 18: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

18

Let us limit ourselves to talking of living one‘s life successfully—I imagine that

Unger‘s apparent success is a significant reason that Whiteley assumed him to be sane. In this

way one may run Whiteley‘s criticisms of Unger:

1. Living successfully involves making judgements, and taking action based on these

judgements, to preserve one‘s life

2. One could not make and act on judgements that preserved life unless one takes at least

some of our beliefs to be justified and true

3. Therefore, in order to live successfully, I must take myself to have at least some

justified, true beliefs (arguably quite a few)

4. The sceptic denies that any of her beliefs are justified

5. Therefore, the sceptic cannot live successfully

6. Unger is not only preserving his life but publishing books and pursuing a career in

philosophy at a leading university

7. Therefore, Unger is living successfully

8. Therefore, Unger is not really a sceptic

Premise 2 appears to be the key, but it is by no means obviously true. Much depends on what

it means for a belief to be taken as justified and true—which is the point of dispute between

Whiteley and Unger—but it is also not obvious that one needs to take beliefs to be justified

and true (whatever that means) in order to act upon the judgements that preserve life. One

might make judgements and act on them on the basis that certain beliefs are justified and true

whilst harbouring some doubt that they really are. Sometimes I judge that the milk has not

turned and put it in my tea even though I am not completely sure I am justified in doing so—I

have a cold and I am not sure the sniff I gave the milk is enough to determine whether it was

bad or not.

Moreover, numerous philosophers throughout history have urged us to avoid making

judgements altogether, as is shown below. It has not always been the case that anyone who

claimed to believe the assertions of scepticism was deemed either mad or insincere. Many

seem to have lived successfully whilst avoiding judgements, or at least taking themselves to

not be justified in committing to any firm belief.

In the next few sections I will chart a history of scepticism that reflects persistent

doubts about the reliability of our senses; serious philosophers who advocate suspension of

judgement and avoidance of knowledge claims; and other, equally serious philosophers who

have found these doubts about our ability to have knowledge of this kind deserving of a

substantial direct response, and not a mere dismissal.

Page 19: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

19

1.3.4 Sixth Century BC—Jainist10 Epistemology

In the sixth century BC, Jainist epistemology developed as a theory of qualified assertion in

order to fit the requirements of Jainist metaphysics. As Koller writes: ‗[B]ecause reality is

many-sided and cognition true only from a limited perspective, all ordinary knowledge claims

need to be qualified… by adding the syāt qualifier‘ (Koller 2000: 400–1). In this way the

metaphysics of anekāntavāda (which holds that existence is many-sided) is rendered

compatible with everyday talk via the epistemic theory of qualified assertion (syādvāda).

Because humans, with our limited perspective, can never achieve full knowledge, the Jainist

adds a caveat, ‗syāt‘ (meaning ‗in some ways‘ or ‗from a certain perspective‘) to everyday

assertions. Whilst this incompleteness should not be simply equated with, say, Cartesian

doubt, it does show that Jainists thought seriously about the limitations of knowledge and the

fact that what we can know is limited by our perspective.

1.3.2 Fifth Century BC—Socratic Scepticism

Socratic scepticism is described in Plato‘s Apology, where Socrates supposes the oracle at

Deplhi to have named him the wisest man in the world because he ‗understands that his

wisdom is worthless‘ (Plato, Apology, 23b11

). Socrates contrasts himself, in Plato‘s dialogue,

with skilled artisans and politicians. He initially considers himself less knowledgeable than

these men because he does not know that which they claim to know. Yet he finds, on

questioning them, that their reasons for the knowledge they claim are insufficient. The wisdom

of Socrates thus lies in him knowing that he does not know these things: ‗About myself I knew

that I know nothing‘ (22d).

We can understand Socratic scepticism as an approach to the quest for knowledge, a

method of withholding the claim to knowledge so as to avoid making assumptions and

encouraging further questioning. Whilst knowledge is not explicitly ruled out, it is made clear

10 Jainism is generally thought to have been founded by Mahāvīra, a sixth century BC contemporary of the

Buddha. See Kumar (2001: 5).

11 References are to the 2002 Grube and Cooper edition.

Page 20: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

20

that living with a complete lack of knowledge, and preserving a state of doubt, is perfectly

possible and, indeed, to be advocated for philosophical endeavour.

1.3.3 Fourth or Sixth Century BC—Laozi12

At a similar time in China Laozi writes: ‗To know and yet (think) we do not know is the

highest (attainment); not to know (and yet think) we do know is a disease‘ Laozi13

(1891: 71).

Scepticism is advocated as a cure for a disease, the disease from which we live in pain is in

thinking that we know that which we do not. To be diseased is the norm; the sage who knows

he does not know is the exception, his status a goal to be obtained. Here, the disquiet that

prevents one from living a good life lies not in doubt, but in baseless knowledge claims. As

with Socrates, this is a warning against dogmatism. The recommendation is that the

philosopher should risk not recognising his own knowledge by promoting doubt, rather than

insisting upon knowledge that is not justified.

In case the reader fears there may be a contradiction between this supposition that the

untrained mind is dogmatic and my assertion that she is prone to sceptical doubt, I would urge

you to dismiss it. Firstly, it is very possible to be dogmatic at some times and sceptical at

others. One should not be surprised that contradictory attitudes can be found in untrained

minds (or in trained minds, for that matter; we are none of us perfectly consistent reasoners).

Secondly, to experience doubt does not prevent one later coming to a conclusion and

becoming dogmatic about it. Indeed, we may suppose that one may prescribe training to

prevent the adoption of dogmatic positions in response to the spectre of sceptical doubt.

Thirdly, as I have already noted, though I think many of us do experience periods of

(sometimes quite intense) sceptical doubt, I did not suppose that this is often a sustained

position, rather, I suggested that doubt primarily occurs against a background of trust. For

many, firm beliefs—in political ideologies, in the affection of one‘s partner, and so forth, in

addition to more foundational beliefs—undergo moments of doubt before returning to their

12 Also rendered ‗Lao-tsu‘.

13 The edition cited is an 1891 translation, which assumed a single author. Tradition dates the text to a single

author in sixth century BC (see Loewe and Shaughnessy 1999: 746), but the date of the original text is unknown

and there is some suggestion that the Laozi is actually a collection of texts gathered over a period of time between

340 and 249 BC (see Brooks and Brooks 1998: 151).

Page 21: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

21

former assurance. We should not be surprised that sceptical philosophers have found

dogmatism amongst untrained minds despite a human tendency towards at least occasional

scepticism.

Moreover, to suppose that the trained and untrained form completely separate camps is

not only misguided, but a somewhat pessimistic view of the power to philosophy to affect

everyday lives. We should not dismiss lightly the way in which the Socartic claim that ‗the

wisest man in the world is the one who knows that he knows nothing‘ has struck a chord

across the centuries. Versions of this thought are repeated throughout literature. The wise fool

is a common trope in literature, thus, Touchstone says in As You Like It: ‗I do now remember a

saying: ―The fool doth think he is wise, but the wise man knows himself to be a fool‖‘

(Shakespeare 1997, AYLI, V.i). The intertwining of popular and philosophical scepticism is

symptomatic of the longevity of its interest for human beings.

1.3.4 Fourth Century BC to Third Century AD14—Pyrrhonian Scpeticism

Pyrrhonian sceptics found tranquillity in their scepticism. The arguments of Pyrrhonian

sceptics like Sextus Empiricus are constructed by presenting appearances and judgements

alongside antithetical counterparts to provoke precisely the suspension of judgement that most

modern epistemologists are so concerned to avoid. The suspension of judgement that is

deemed impossible for the sane.

It seems the Pyrrhonians found ways to live successfully without knowledge, or at the

very least believing that they did not have knowledge. From our earliest philosophy it has been

argued that a full life is not wedded to the possession of knowledge, or to believing that one

possesses knowledge, or that one should be able to assert knowledge. Indeed, some argue that

life is fuller and more satisfying where no knowledge claims are made.

One might think that this argues against my purpose. The Pyrrhonians claimed to be at

peace with (or at least sought to attain peace with) their lack of knowledge. However, it is

clear, nonetheless, that knowledge and lack thereof was an issue that Pyrrhonians struggled

with and viewed as centrally important. Their arguments sought to break us out of the very

14 Pyrrho is thought to have lived from 365/60–275/70 BC (Svavarsson 2010: 36), his thought inspired the

founding of the Pyrrhonian school by Aenesidemus in the first century BC (Bett 2010: 5); the most complete

account of Pyrrhonian scepticism is found in the works of Sextus Empiricus, in the second and third centuries AD

(Pellegrin 2010: 120)

Page 22: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

22

natural inclination to seek after the knowledge they believed impossible to attain. Unlike the

modern movement that seeks to convince us that ‗ordinary‘, non-philosophically trained folk

are content to believe that they have a wide variety of knowledge, the whole Pyrrhonian

philosophy is premised on the thought that people are commonly involved in a fruitless

struggle for knowledge that philosophy can wrest us free from.

1.3.5 Third to First Century BC—Academic Sceptics

Academic sceptics like Cicero argued that nothing can be known, as we cannot distinguish

false presentation from true (Cicero, Academica, II, xxiii, 76-II, xxviii, 9015

), and reason (or

dialectic) cannot provide certainty (Cicero, Academica, II, xxviii, 90-xxx, 98). Yet, unlike the

Pyrrhonian sceptic, Cicero argues that:

[E]ven many sense percepts must be deemed probable if only it be held in mind that no

sense presentation has such a character as a false presentation without differing from it

at all. Thus the wise man will make use of whatever apparently probable presentation

he encounters… if he were not to approve them life would be done away with…

(Cicero, Academica, II, xxxi, 99)

Thus, the academic sceptic takes something akin to the modern pragmatist position (although,

he does not take the pragmatist position of dismissing the sceptic). Cicero is adamant that

sceptical arguments are effective and nothing can be known, and that it is important to

recognise this to avoid dogmatism: ‗the wise man will never assent‘ (Cicero, Academica, II,

xxiv, 78), he will merely form probable beliefs. This concern to avoid assertions echoes the

Jainist argument that one should not assert ‗X is Y‘. Advocating probability is notably

different to advocating the perspectival caveat of syāt, but both seem motivated by an

acknowledgement of the limitation of our ability to know absolutes from the subjective

perspective.

Acting on probable beliefs without ever claiming knowledge does not seem to have

caused any problems for Cicero. One might, as with Unger, call this merely a refusal to use the

term ‗knowledge‘ in the way that it is commonly employed with regard to non-certain, but

highly probable, beliefs. Nevertheless, if our concern is to reflect genuine language usage, it is

15 References are to the 1933 Rackham translation.

Page 23: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

23

clear that from ancient times there has been a consistent current of thought that shows

individuals as unwilling to ascribe the term ‗knowledge‘ to their probable beliefs.

1.3.6 Fourth Century AD—Augustine

As noted by Klima, Allhoff, and Jayprakash Vaidya (2007: 1) there is still a tendency to

assume that nothing much of philosophical interest happened between ancient times and

Descartes—that scepticism, along with other philosophical issues, ceased to be of interest or

subject to substantial thought. This is false. For example, Augustine (Confessions 5.10.1916

)

confesses that he briefly fell sway to scepticism in 383–4 AD17

: ‗The thought came to my

mind that the philosophers whom they call Academics were shrewder than others. They taught

that everything is a matter of doubt, and that an understanding of truth lies beyond human

capacity‘. Yet, within a relatively short period of time (386–7 AD) he rejected the scepticism

he had embraced and attacked it in his Contra Academicos. Arguing that happiness lies in

wisdom and that Academic sceptics are not wise.

Augustine‘s argument rests on a questionable reading of Cicero to the effect that

wisdom and happiness might be found in the search for truth, even if there can be no

knowledge: ‗―why can‘t someone who searches for truth be happy, even if he cannot find it?‖‘

(Contra Academicos 1.3.718

). Augustine‘s attack takes a fruitless search for knowledge to be

inducing despair as opposed to tranquillity, powerfully feeling that a defence of the

attainability of knowledge was required.

1.3.7 Medieval Scepticism

In c. 1100, Al-Ghazali, an Islamic philosopher and theologian, wrote Deliverance from Error.

In it he outlines a project that will sound familiar to readers of Descartes‘s meditations. He

writes:

16 References are to the 1991 Chadwick translation.

17 Date estimates comes from O‘Daly (2001: 159)

18 References are to the 1995 Against the Academics translation by King.

Page 24: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

24

My aim is to perceive the deep reality of things; I wish to seize the essence of

knowledge. Certain knowledge is that in which the thing known reveals itself without

leaving any room for doubt or any possibility of error or illusion, nor can the heart

allow such a possibility. One must be protected from error… However, when I

examined what I know, I found myself lacking this kind of certain knowledge (Al-

Ghazali 2002: §§25–8)

Compare:

Some years ago I was struck by the large number of falsehoods that I had accepted as

true… Reason now leads me to think that I should hold back my assent from opinions

which are not completely certain and indubitable (Descartes Meditations: I.18–19)

Descartes‘s standard of certainty—immunity from doubt—is often cast by modern

philosophers as a peculiarity of Cartesian thought that has infected our discourse and from

which we must be cleansed. Yet, Al-Ghazali‘s position that ‗perceiving the deep reality of

things‘ is dependent on leaving no ‗room for doubt‘ and being ‗protected from error‘ predates

the Meditations by five hundred years.

Both texts move on from this starting point to question first the reliability of the senses,

and then ‗intellectual truths‘ (Al-Ghazali 2002: §31) or ‗simpler and more universal things‘

(Descartes Meditations: I.20), like the truths of mathematics or geometry. Their conclusions

are very different. Where Descartes hits on the cogito as a first principle, from which he

believes all knowledge can be derived, Al-Ghazali is unable to establish a first principle and

concludes the reverse, that ‗no construction of a proof is possible‘ (Al-Ghazali 2002: §34). Al-

Ghazali dwellt for two months as a sceptic, ‗though neither in theory nor in outward

expression‘ (ibid.) before he was ‗cured‘ by God‘s revelation:

I recovered my health and mental equilibrium. The self-evident principles of reason

again seemed acceptable; I trusted them and in them felt safe and certain. I reached this

point not by well-ordered or methodical argument, but by means of a light God the

Almighty cast into my breast, which light is the key to most knowledge (Al-Ghazali

2002: §§ 34–5)

It is tempting to see in this a religious version of Hume‘s naturalism. Where Al-Ghazali‘s

return to trust in self-evident principles is attributed to God, Hume attributes this to human

nature. However, where Hume‘s naturalism argues for contentment with less than certainty,

Page 25: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

25

there is no such concession in Al-Ghazali. Rather, I would argue that we see the proto-

Humean element in Al-Ghazali‘s statement that his theory and outward expression did not

reflect his inner doubt: i.e. Al-Ghazali continued to think and act as though he believed, even

though he was philosophically consumed by doubt. Al-Ghazali‘s restoration to trust in ‗self-

evident‘ principles does not mark an acceptance that certainty is not required for knowledge.

Rather, it lies in the conclusion that certainty about deep reality is founded on faith in God.

The exclusion of doubt as a requirement for knowledge was also advocated by Henry

of Ghent19

, who, drawing on Aristotelian principles, held that ‗there can be knowledge only by

apprehending what is certain and determinate‘(Summa Quaestionum Ordinarium, a.1 q.1,

1.320

). Given this, Ghent constructs an argument that ‗a Human Being Cannot Know

Anything‘ (Summa Quaestionum Ordinarium, a.1 q.1, 1), on the basis of the untrustworthiness

of the senses, ‗The senses apprehend nothing of what is certain concerning a thing‘ (Summa

Quaestionum Ordinarium, a.1 q.1, 1.3); combined with our complete reliance upon them for

knowing contingent objects, ‗All human intellective cognition has its knowledge in the senses‘

(Ghent, Summa Quaestionum Ordinarium, a.1 q.1, 1.2).

1.4 Scepticism as an Enduring Concern

The above is a truncated and simplified account of scepticism through the ages, but what it

reveals are concerns that have persistented across time, in diverse cultures, and which existed

long before Descartes and the Cartesian doubt. We see that philosophers such as the Jainists,

Socrates21

, Laozi, and Cicero not only did not claim knowledge, or ‗full‘ knowledge, but

advised against it. The Pyrrhonians advocated a way of life founded upon accepting the

impossibility of knowledge, and other philosophers, such as Henry of Ghent, Augustine, and

Al-Ghazali, seem to have lived under sustained doubt, or belief in the impossibility of

knowledge, for at least some period of time. Moreover, we see again and again arguments for

doubt motivated by the uncertainty of the senses alongside their central role in our knowledge

claims. ‗All human intellective cognition has its knowledge in the senses‘ but, ‗The senses

19 1217–93 AD (Klima, Allhoff, and Jayprakash Vaidya 2007).

20 References are to the Pasnau 2002 translation, reprinted in Klima, Allhof, and Jayprakesh Vaidya 2007.

21 Or Plato in the guise of Socrates, I take no position on this point.

Page 26: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

26

apprehend nothing of what is certain concerning a thing‘ (Ghent, Summa Quaestionum

Ordinarium, a.1 q.1, 1.2–3). Cicero argues that we cannot distinguish false presentation from

true (Cicero, Academica, II, xxiii, 76-II, xxviii, 90), and Sextus Empiricus articulates

extensively the conflicting deliverances if the senses in the Ten Modes, particularly modes one

to seven (see Outlines of Scepticism, I.xiv22

). More loosely, there is Jainist thought that the

human perspective is fundamentally limited.

From some of our earliest recorded philosophy we see the same concern that there is,

or might be, a mismatch between how the world seems to us and how it really is. The

responses to this concern differ. Some believe that knowledge, though difficult to attain, is not

out of reach. Some philosophers find contentment in accepting the problem as irresolvable.

Some abandon knowledge for probability. Some turn to a higher power to guarantee our

knowledge. However, although the responses may differ, the worry that appearance may not

match reality, and that our senses may not be a reliable source of information, is a clear

undercurrent through time.

Moreover, we see that the concern that that which we perceive may not match reality is

recurrent in literature, which reflects the cultural interests of the mind untrained by

philosophy. We question our senses. We question what evidence suffices for knowledge. We

are disquieted and fascinated by illusion and we unsettle ourselves by exploring sceptical

hypotheses in our literature.

It would be wrong to say that only one sceptical interest arises from this milieu of

doubt, but I think my sceptic, the sceptic who is concerned that she might have just the

thoughts and experiences she has now if the world were radically different—even if there were

no world outside of her own mind at all—articulates a prominent thread. I think she demands a

robust, direct answer to her concern, and I think that such an answer would offer substantial

reassurance to those who have been plagued by this doubt through the ages.

1.5 Transcendental Arguments as a Response to Scepticism

I want to give the sceptic a robust answer. I think her questions reflect valid and genuine

worries and deserve a serious response. By ‗robust‘ and ‗serious‘, I mean that I want to give

her an answer that acknowledges the common ground between us. Rather than dismissing her

22 References are to the 2005 Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes edition.

Page 27: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

27

worry as misguided or nonsensical, I want to accept her framing of the argument, but show

that her conclusion is false. I take her argument to be:

1. I have a complex mental life that includes experience which seems to present

an extra-mental world

2. I could have just these thoughts and experiences in sceptical scenario S where

there is no extra-mental world

3. I cannot get outside my own perspective—the only evidence I have to justify

my beliefs are my own thoughts and experiences

4. Therefore, I have just as much justification to believe that there is an external

world that is much as it appears as to be as I have to believe that I am in S

5. Therefore, I do not know that I am not in S

In saying that I take her argument seriously, I mean that I accept her standards for evidence

and do not take her worry to be unintelligible. A serious and robust response must therefore be

one that starts from the evidence she accepts: the thoughts and experience that make up my

complex mental life which seems to present an extra-mental world. It is therefore my

challenge to show that there is not ‗just as much‘ justification to believe the sceptical scenario

is could be the cause of this complex mental life as there is to believe that the world is much as

it seems.

The key to answering this type of sceptic is to only use premises the sceptic would

accept. She is not a sceptic content to simply keep asking ‗Yes, but why?‘ in the manner of a

small child. She is principled. She is ourselves when we contemplate our own thoughts and

experiences and worry that there might not be anything else. In particular, she is concerned

that there seems to be a discrepancy between her assurance for her own thoughts and

experiences and her beliefs about the world outside those thoughts and experiences.

Transcendental arguments are particularly suited to the purpose of offering a robust

and serious response to this type of sceptic. There is more than one type of transcendental

argument, and I will look in more detail at what exactly it is for an argument to be

transcendental in chapter two, but as a generalisation, we can take an argument to be

transcendental if it starts from a premise about our thoughts or experience, and moves on to

show that something must be the case because it is a necessary condition of our having

thoughts or experience, or of our having a certain type of thoughts or experience. Given that

the transcendental argument starts from a premise concerning precisely the type of proposition

that the sceptic does not doubt—indeed, a type of proposition about which she has such

Page 28: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

28

assurance that she holds in question anything for which she does not have equal assurance—if

it can be shown that that which she doubts is a necessary condition of this, she will have to

abandon her doubt.

I distinguish two broad categories of transcendental argument: strong and weak. A

strong transcendental argument is one that shows that the truth of some proposition concerning

the mental has as a necessary condition a proposition concerning the extra-mental. A weak

transcendental argument is one that focuses on elucidating the necessary connections between

mental concepts, the conclusion of will concern what we should believe to be the case. In

recent years, the preference has overwhelmingly been to focus on weak transcendental

arguments. I argue that no weak transcendental argument can offer reassurance against my

sceptic, and that therefore I will go on to defend the plausibility of strong transcendental

arguments.

It may be wondered why the sceptic prizes propositions concerning her thoughts and

experience. In recent years, some have to come to question whether the same sceptical

scenarios that lead us to doubt the extra-mental might not also give us cause to doubt the

mental. In chapter three, I examine these arguments. I argue that although in some respects it

must be conceded that we do not know our own minds perfectly, not all propositions are

brought into doubt; moreover, the type of propositions brought into question (e.g. our

knowledge of our own emotions) are not of the sort that the sceptic was inclined to prize in the

first place.

Having secured that there are at least some propositions concerning the mental to form

the first premise of a transcendental argument, in chapter four, I go on to examine the

criticisms that have been raised against the plausibility of strong transcendental arguments. In

particular, I consider Stroud‘s challenge that we cannot build a ‗bridge of necessity‘ from

psychological premises to conclusions about the world. I argue that Stroud‘s criticisms rest on

the illicit supposition that the mind is not a part of the world. I show that supervenience

physicalism is a viable metaphysical picture, and one which would explain how propositions

concerning the mental can have the truth of extra-mental propositions as a condition of their

truth. I argue that no metaphysical picture of the relationship between mind and world that

could generate the restrictions on reasoning that lead to the impossibility of reasoning from

premises about the mind to conclusions about the extra-mental world can be assumed. Given

that the sceptic cannot rule out the supervenience physicalist picture of mind and world, she

Page 29: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

29

cannot simply assert that the world is such that reasoning from premises concerning the mind

to conclusions concerning the world is implausible.

In chapter five, I explore what form the second premise of a strong transcendental

argument could take and propose that it should be a psychophysical law of nature, and that a

dispositional essentialist view of properties would guarantee the metaphysical necessity of

such a law so that if it could be found it would be true at all possible worlds where the mental

property existed. I do not give a strong transcendental argument myself, but I show how one

could be constructed on the basis that some mental proposition prized by the sceptic will only

be true at worlds where some extra-mental proposition is also true. This will be the case if

there is a metaphysically necessary psychophysical law, for the truth of dispositional

essentialism will mean that any world at which the prized mental property is present will be a

world at which it is in a stimulus and/or manifestation relation to certain physical properties.

Which is to say that it could not be the case that the truth of propositions concerning the

mental life we do have could be equally well explained if we were subject to a sceptical

scenario in which there was not physical world.

A full defence of dispositional essentialism and watertight argument for a specific

strong transcendental argument would be a much larger project than there is space for in this

thesis. However, I will show that it is entirely plausible that such an argument could be given.

Moreover, I show that any response from the sceptic will involve her taking up and defending

specific philosophical positions, such as nominalism about the laws of nature or a Cartesian

dualist picture of the relationship between mind and world. This, in itself, is no small

achievement. As such, the sceptic becomes not merely the natural, recurrent human worry I

have outlined above, but a concrete position with theses to defend. This is a shift in the

dialectic that can itself offer comfort. We can know something of what must be true of the

world for the sceptic‘s arguments to get started.

Page 30: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

30

Chapter 2: Transcendental Arguments

It is my contention that transcendental arguments, and especially strong transcendental

arguments, are particularly suited to responding to the sceptic. To understand why this is, we

must first understand what a transcendental argument is. The purpose of this chapter is to

articulate what is meant by the term ‗transcendental argument‘ broadly, and to provide a finer

account of different types of transcendental argument, understanding their similarities and

differences as they have arisen through their historical context.

Transcendental arguments are various in their form and the term is best understood as a

kind of family resemblance concept, for which Kant‘s transcendental deduction should be

regarded as a historical anchor and point of origin. It would not be right to say that the Kantian

project provides a paradigm, as the development of transcendental arguments has progressed

as often by misunderstanding Kant as it has by direct inspiration. Nevertheless, the name is

owed to Kant, and the branches of modern discourse that I am particularly interested in trace

their origins to his work.

I distinguish transcendental philosophy as an epistemological theory of what can be

known and of the structure of knowledge, from a transcendental argument, being an argument

structured and defined by a specific methodological approach. The distinction between the two

is not always carefully maintained in the literature, and this is to a certain extent due to a

failure to make the distinction in reading Kant. I shall therefore begin this chapter by

providing an account of Kant‘s transcendental project and what we can learn from it in order

to develop a satisfactory response to scepticism.

2.1 The Transcendental Deduction

The name, ‗Transcendental Deduction‘, has often misled scholars into conflating Kant‘s

transcendental philosophy with we would now call ‗transcendental argument‘. There are

transcendental arguments within the Critique of Pure Reason, but ‗Deduction‘, here, is not

being used in our modern sense to mean ‗proof‘. Rather, Kant offers us a defence of certain

indispensable propositions in the manner described in ‗The Principles to any Transcedental

Deduction‘ by analogy to an eighteenth century Prussian legal practice, whereby the rights to a

Page 31: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

31

property are established by ‗deduction‘ in the form of tracing the claim back to its origin.23

The ‗Transcendental Deduction‘, therefore, does not try to prove or justify any particular claim

in the modern sense of ‗deduction‘, in which one offers an argument whereby the warrant of

premises transfers by entailment to a conclusion. Rather, it seeks to elucidate where our

concepts come from. The following is worth quoting at length to understand the full meaning:

When teachers of law talk about rights and claims, they distinguish in a legal action the

question regarding what is legal (quid iuris) from the question concerning fact (quid),

and they demand proof of both. The first proof, which is to establish the right, or for

that matter the legal entitlement, they call the deduction [This term also applies in

philosophy] We employ a multitude of empirical concepts without being challenged by

anyone. And […] neither from experience, nor from reason can we adduce any distinct

legal basis from which the right to use them emerges distinctly.

But there are […] some that are determined for pure a priori use […] proofs

based on experience are insufficient to establish the legitimacy of using them in that

way; yet we do need to know how these concepts can refer to objects even though they

do not take these objects from any experience. Hence when I explain in what way

concepts can refer to objects a priori, I call that explanation the transcendental

deduction of these concepts. (Kant, A 84–5, B 116–17; comment in square brackets is

the translator‘s, ellipses are mine.)

He starts from the supposition that certain claims constitutive to our understanding of the

world are known to hold, and then sets about providing the ‗justification‘—not in our modern

sense of providing the reasons to believe, but rather, having noted that we do believe he seeks

to show why we are right to do so.

When Stroud first characterised transcendental arguments in his influential 1968 paper,

‗Transcendental Arguments‘, his account was skewed by a failure to distinguish the

Transcendental Deduction and the Refutation of Idealism as discrete projects within Kant‘s

Transcendental Aesthetic. Stroud writes:

The transcendental deduction (along with the Refutation of Idealism) is supposed to

provide just such a proof [against scepticism] and, thereby, to give a complete answer

to the sceptic about the existence of things outside us. (Stroud 2000a: 9–10)

There is no doubt that Kant considered scepticism as deserving of a response. He felt that it

was: ‗a scandal to philosophy and to human reason in general that the existence of things

23 See Kitcher‘s ‗Introduction‘ to the Pluhar 1996 edition: xlii; also Henrich 1989: 29–46.

Page 32: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

32

outside us […] must be accepted merely on faith‘ (B xl). However, the scandal to which Kant

refers is not that we do not know that things exist outside us. On the contrary, he is convinced

that we do know this. The scandal is that we have to take truths such as this on trust, as no one

has been able to articulate our justification.

It is in this sense that I understand the Transcendental Deduction to be an articulation

of Kant‘s transcendental philosophy, rather than as a transcendental argument. To be

transcendental in this sense is not to seek knowledge of things as they are in themselves

(independently of us), but rather to note what we do know, of the existence of things outside

us, and to justify this knowledge claim via an articulation of the necessary connections

between the nature of our thoughts and experience and the things we know. This

transcendental philosophy is not a proof, but an articulation of a metaphysical picture.

2.2 Kant’s Copernican Turn

The insight that enables Kant‘s Transcendental Deduction is that which Kant characterised as

his ‗Copernican turn‘: a way of solving a fundamental problem via a radical shift in point of

view. Just as Copernicus realised that we were failing to understand the movements of the

stars because we supposed that they were revolving around the Earth, Kant‘s realisation is that

we have been considering fundamental epistemological questions from the wrong perspective.

He writes of the ‗turn‘:

We here propose to do just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain the celestial

movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming that all the

heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator, he reversed the process, and tried the

experiment of assuming that the spectator revolved, while the stars remained at rest.

We may make the same experiment with regard to the intuition of objects. If the

intuition must conform to the nature of the objects, I do not see how we can know

anything of them a priori. If, on the other hand, the object conforms to the nature of our

faculty of intuition, I can then easily conceive the possibility of such an a priori

knowledge. (B xvi)

Kant is proposing that our mistake has been trying to find proof of the existence of things

outside us by supposing that our experience (intuition) of them is caused by the objects. As we

can thus only know of the objects by that experience, anything we know of them must be a

posteriori. Kant supposed that only a priori truths can be necessary, so no argument based on a

Page 33: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

33

posteriori truths can entail a necessary conclusion. In other words: if we suppose that our

experience is caused by objects outside us, we cannot have a proof of the existence of objects

outside, as that experience can only contain a posteriori knowledge, which cannot be

necessarily true, and is thus open to doubt. His ‗Copernican turn‘ is to suppose that ‗the object

conforms to the nature of our faculty of intuition‘—i.e. the nature of the object we experience

is in some sense determined by our experience of it. If this is the case, then we can know the

nature of objects outside us by considering what objects could be formed by our ‗faculty of

intuition‘. As we can know about our own minds and experience a priori, we should, Kant

supposes, be able to work out what kinds of things we can have knowledge of, and thereby

know the nature of the objects our experiences are of.

Kant attributed this awakening from his ‗dogmatic slumber‘ to Hume, whom he felt

had clarified the problem, but failed to identify the solution it required. Hume‘s insight is that

there are some propositions that cannot be justified either via the evidence of the senses (for he

supposed that there was no necessary connection discoverable by the senses24

(ECHU 7.8)), or

by analytic a priori argument, yet which are still such that we must believe them. For Hume (T

1.4.1.825

) it is simply a fact about our nature that we cannot believe the sceptical conclusion:

‗as experience will sufficiently convince anyone […] that tho‘ he can find no error in the

foregoing [sceptical] arguments, yet he still continues to believe‘. It is this thought of there

being certain psychological facts about beliefs that we cannot relinquish that intrigued Kant,

but it is in their response to this realisation that Hume and Kant differ.

Hume supposes that imagination draws a connection between one object and another

on the basis of an effect‘s constant conjunction with its cause, and thus we are able to get on

with our lives, supposing that such a connection exists. However, this is a contingent ‗happy‘

fact about how we are constituted, about our nature (see T 1.4.1.12). ‗This sceptical doubt,‘ he

writes (T 1.4.2.57), ‗is a malady that can never be radically cured‘. We would be consumed by

it, if we did not have some way of setting it aside: ‗Carelessness and in-attention alone can

afford us any remedy‘ (ibid.). I argued in the introduction that the persistence of disquiet in the

face of perennial doubt shows that sceptical doubt is just as natural as our careless

24 I will discuss Hume‘s sceptical arguments in more detail in 4.2. For now the concern is how Kant responded to

Hume‘s thought.

25 References to the Hume (1739–40), A Treatise of Human Nature, are given by ‗T‘.

Page 34: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

34

inattentiveness to such doubt. Inattention to doubt, after all, does not mean that doubt is not

present nor worth attending to. I think it is for this reason that many, like Kant, are not content

to be fortuitously, if naturally, inattentive to the doubt. Our anti-sceptical convictions require

some justification. Something more substantial is required, and this is what Kant hopes to

offer—what he thinks is scandalous that we have not offered already. An explanation of how it

is that we can know the things we know.

The Transcendental Deduction is Kant‘s account of the metaphysics that explains our

right to the use of the ‗categories‘ in knowledge claims about objects of experience. These

categories are given as unity, plurality, allness (categories of quantity); reality, negation, and

limitation (categories of quality); inherence and subsistence, causality and dependence, and

community (categories of relation); possibility, existence, and necessity (categories of

modality) (see A 80/B 106). Kant does not argue for each of these specifically in the

Transcendental Deduction, but, rather, provides an account of our mental processing

(synthesis) that accounts for how the application of these concepts (the categories) is

necessary for our cognizing of the objects of experience in the way that we do. It is

justificatory in that its aim is to show that this is the only possible explanation for the

necessary application of these concepts. Its purpose is not to defend that the concepts are

necessarily applied. It is transcendental because it demonstrates the dependence of objects of

experience upon the application of the categories to the manifold of intuition to form an

experience that we, as human beings, can understand. Kant‘s psychological model requires

that there be a ‗unity of appreception‘, in which we are able to attribute unity to an object of

experience by relating it to ourselves in a way that reflects that oneself is a unified being: ‗the

possibility of appearances lies in ourselves, and their connection and unity (the presentation of

an object) is to be met with merely in us)‘ (Kant A 130).

It‘s important to understand this in the context of Kant‘s transcendental idealism.

Objects of experience are not things are they are in themselves, independent of the human

mind: ‗[For] what is merely in us cannot determine the character of an object distinct to our

presentations‘ (Kant A 129). These are objects of the ‗phenomenal realm‘ formed by the

application of the categories to the manifold of intuitions. It is the metaphysical supposition

that the objects of our experience are not completely independent of our mental faculties and

what we are capable of experiencing that allows for an account to be given of why they are

necessarily applicable.

Page 35: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

35

2.3 The Refutation of Idealism

It will no doubt strike the reader that the transcendental philosophy outlined above will not be

of great use against my sceptic. This sceptic‘s worry is precisely that we cannot have

knowledge of objects that exist independently of the mind. Moreover, she will not be satisfied

with a deduction in the quasi-legal/historical sense that Kant gives where the application of the

categories to in space is assumed and thus merely to be explained. Hers is the disquiet that

comes upon Hume in his study, though he is able to set it aside in his daily life. To her there is

more than one equally plausible explanation for why I have just these thoughts and

experiences, and therefore, she insists, we must prove her doubt wrong, or she will not be

satisfied.

However, the Transcendental Deduction is not the only kind of transcendental

argument articulated in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kant also gives us the Refutation of

Idealism, which can be understood as a transcendental argument in a way that more closely

aligns to how the term is used in modern discussions. I stress that Kant does not draw this

distinction himself. Rather, it is a meaningful distinction for us because a) the second kind of

argument is more relevant to the needs of my sceptic, and b) this distinct kind of argument that

has had a significant impact upon philosophers of the twentieth and twenty-first centuries.

Over the next few sections I will examine the Refutation of Idealism for its form as a

transcendental argument, and also for its relevance as a response to my type of sceptic. This

second point is particularly significant as a refutation of idealism is exactly what she is

worried we cannot have, but in order for such a refutation to be given, one must be clear as to

what kind of idealism one is refuting.

2.3.1 Transcendental Idealism and Material Idealisms

Kant added the ‗Refutation of Idealism‘ to The Critique of Pure Reason for its second edition.

He explains (Kant B 274–5) that he sought to distance himself from what he called ‗material

idealism‘; of which he identified two sorts: 1) problematic idealism, and 2) dogmatic idealism.

Kant associates problematic idealism with the philosophy of Descartes, and defines it as the

Page 36: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

36

claim that the existence of external objects in space is doubtful and indemonstrable26

. He

associates dogmatic idealism with Berkeley, and takes it to be the position that the existence of

external objects in space is false and impossible. The purpose of the refutation, then, is not

simply to show these positions to be false, but to demonstrate the way Kant‘s own philosophy

differs from them.

The theorem to be established as a refutation of these positions is given as ‗The mere,

but empirically determined, consciousness of my own existence proves the existence of objects

in space outside of me‘ (Kant B 275).

Kant (ibid.) takes Descartes‘s position to be that the only empirical assertion for which

one can have certainty is that of one‘s own existence (that ‗I am‘): the empirically determined

consciousness of my own experience. Kant accepts Descartes‘s criterion of not forming a

‗decisive judgement‘ before it is shown that the truth of a proposition cannot be put into doubt,

and aims is to show that this singularly indubitable proposition (the claim that ‗I am‘) has as a

necessary condition that one has already had some genuine experience of spatial objects

external to oneself (the proposition that he takes Descartes to doubt and Berkeley to hold as

false).

In the next section I will outline Kant‘s ‗Proof‘, before going on to show how one‘s

understanding of what ‗I am‘ means and what ‗objects in space outside of me‘ are affects

one‘s understanding of and response to this argument.

2.3.2 The Proof

Kant (B 275–6)‘s proof runs as follows:

1. I am conscious of my own existence as determined in time

2. All determination in regards to time presupposes the existence of something

permanent in perception

3. Something cannot be that permanent something (which determines my existence in

time) if it is within me

4. So, this permanent something must be external to me

26 It is perhaps unfair of Kant to say that for Descartes the existence of the material world remains in doubt;

Descartes offers his own argument for the existence of the material world from what he takes to be indubitably

certain premises (see Descartes ‗The Principles of Philosophy‘, II.i (Descartes (1931) in my bibliography).

Page 37: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

37

5. Hence, this perceived permanent thing cannot be a mere representation, and must

be a genuinely external thing

6. So, the determination of my existence in time has as a necessary condition, the

existence of genuine external objects

7. Necessarily, consciousness of my own existence in time requires the possibility of

determination in time

8. So, consciousness of my existence in time necessarily requires the existence of

things external to me

(See Kant B 275–6)

Having set out this argument in an unusually succinct paragraph, Kant then proceeds to

provide a number of ‗Comments‘, which serve to clarify some of the more opaque premises.

Comment I clarifies the first premise (see Kant B 276–7). Kant starts from the claim (which he

acknowledges to be indubitable) that ‗I am‘, here interpreted as consciousness of one‘s own

experience as ‗determined‘ in time. As Kant understands it, the expression ‗I am‘ can be

granted to accompany all thoughts, which can be read to mean that for Kant there is no

consciousness without self-consciousness, no conscious thought without an awareness that

there is a person, me, who thinks.

Additionally, he writes that this expression (‗I am‘) ‗directly includes the existence of a

subject‘, but not ‗a cognition of that subject‘ (Kant B 277). What is it for an expression to

‗include‘ the existence of a subject but not any cognition of it? Well, Kant (ibid.) goes on to

say that without any cognition of the subject there is no empirical cognition, by which he

means, experience. This is because, for Kant, experience involves both the thought of

something existent and ‗intuition‘, and the subject must be determined in relation to that

intuition. The form of ‗intuition‘ here must be time, as Kant has argued that this is an internal

intuition. So, when Kant says that the expression ‗I am‘ includes the existence of a subject, but

not the cognition of it, he means that knowing or recognising that I am (rather than simply

having the self-conscious awareness that is involved in any thought) requires the subject to be

‗determined‘ in time.

In what sense ‗determined‘? In the sense that the subject‘s thought or perceptions must be so

ordered such that one happens after another one, as this is the only way that we (human

beings) can proceed intelligibly. To know that I am, I must be able to think ‗I am‘ at two

different times, and to relate these two thoughts such that I appreciate that I am the same being

that existed at t1 and thought ‗I am‘, and then at t2, with that same thought ‗I am‘. Otherwise

one simply does not have enough information to make sense of what this ‗I‘ is of which we are

Page 38: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

38

to assert its existence when we think—at least, we cannot understand ourselves as a unified

being, possessed of both those thoughts and persisting through time (what Kant calls the ‗unity

of appreception‘).

However, Kant (B 277–8) goes on to argue in Comment II, this representation cannot

be determined in time without the existence of external things, as we only understand time

through change in something permanent. Why should this permanent thing be external to me,

though? Well, Kant (ibid.) argues that as the presentation ‗I‘ is not itself an intuition, there will

be no predicate of ‗I‘ that could ‗serve as correlate for the time determination in internal

sense‘. Kant‘s meaning here is not entirely clear, but I interpret it as the thought that as ‗I‘ is a

mere ‗spontaneous‘ representation, that itself can only be made sense of when determined by

time, it can have no characteristic—and no permanence, in and of itself—against which time

could be determined. There is not that stability in self-awareness in and of itself such as to

provide the relation that this thing is the same thing thinking that ‗I am‘ at t2 as the thing that

thought ‗I am‘ at t1. This must be so, as what permanence ‗I‘ has, it derives from time, and so

it cannot be that which in turn provides the permanence time needs to be determined by.

Hence the ‗something permanent‘ must be external, and, Kant thinks, material.

2.3.3 The Kantian and Cartesian ‘I am’

The ‗I am‘ of problematic idealism, or Cartesianism, is the conclusion of the cogito. It is

established in a dialectical context in which the only direct experience is inner experience.

From this perspective the Cartesian problematic idealist will accept that ‗I am‘, but will hold

that belief in external spatial objects can only be justified indirectly.

Kant argues that outer experience is direct—inner experience is mere presentation until

‗determined‘. The Kantian ‗I‘ accompanies all thoughts and experiences, but is merely formal.

As he describes it, all thought and experience directly include the existence of a subject, but

not the cognition of that subject. This is why he holds that there is no consciousness without

self-consciousness—cognition requires recognition—and that my consciousness of my

existence is of that existence being determined in time.

On Kant‘s account of experience there are always two factors. There is something, ‗I

am‘, that accompanies all thought and experience, but it is empty unless it can be related to an

‗intuition‘. What Kant understands by the term ‗intuition‘ is somewhat ambiguous, but what

Page 39: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

39

he says of it is this: ‗thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind‘

(Kant A 51/B 75). This is enigmatic, to say the least, but I take the implication to be that

intuitions are the content of our thoughts, but without some sort of conceptualisation they can

be nothing to us—they will be content that lacks meaning and usefulness to us because we will

not know how to process it. Hence, if the ‗I am‘ is an empty thought without determination,

then it seems that determination is going to involve some sort of conceptualisation of

‗intuitions‘—the content of thought or experience. ‗Time‘ is what Kant calls the ‗form‘ of

inner intuition. It is a ‗form‘ in the sense that it imposes form upon our thoughts. It has a kind

of organisational capacity. So, the thought is that time in some way helps conceptualise the

content of thought or experience so as to enable one to recognise that ‗I am‘. How does this

work?

Kant is working from a Humean bundle picture of identity:

For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on

some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain

or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can

observe any thing but the perception. (Hume, T 1.4.6.3)

For Hume, there is no ‗I‘ to find on introspection, only a bundle of experiences. Similarly, the

Kantian ‗I‘ is empty because it is nothing over and above its thoughts and experiences. So

Kant‘s thought is that, rather than supposing that ‗I‘ am something to be found upon

introspecting, that which I do find upon introspecting—the experiences and thoughts that I

have—are all accompanied by the ‗presentation‘ ‗I am‘. The thought that ‗I am‘ brings an

appreciation that I am the same being whose having of those two thoughts ties them together.

Making sense of a series of thoughts or experiences requires the recognition that the ‗I am‘

that accompanied E1 is related to the ‗I am‘ that accompanied E2 in the sense that it is the

same ‗I am‘ that accompanies both. This relation can only be recognised, however, if E1 and

E2 can be distinguished. So they must be conceived of as distinct, and the organising factor (or

form) that will distinguish them must be time, as the material idealist wants to insist that our

inner knowledge is prior, so we cannot have access to the form of outer sense (i.e. space). I

determine that ‗I am‘ on re-encountering/recognising the same ‗I‘ accompanying E1 and E2 at

different times.

Page 40: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

40

Thus, Kant reaches the conclusion that ‗I am‘ is necessarily true for self-conscious

individuals by different means than the Cartesian problematic idealist, and one might question

whether it is the same ‗I am‘ that he uses as his first premise: ‗I am conscious of my own

existence as determined in time‘. Determination in time is necessary because of the bundle

theory of identity, to which Descartes in not committed. For Descartes, the ‗I‘ that exists is

only known to do so for as long as it is thinking, it is not recognising itself over disparate

moments of time as accompanying experiences. Everything is in doubt, including experiences,

until the realisation that doubt, as a form of thought, is only possible if there is one who is

doubting:

I have just said that I have no senses and no body… am I not so bound up with a body

and with senses that I cannot exist without them? But I have convinced myself that

there is absolutely nothing in the world, no sky, no earth, no minds, no bodies. Does it

now follow that I too do not exist? No: if I convinced myself of something then I

certainly existed. But there is a deceiver of supreme power and cunning who is

deliberately and constantly deceiving me. In that case I too undoubtedly exist, if he is

deceiving me. (Descartes Meditations, 2.24–527

)

As we shall look at again in chapter four, it is precisely the bareness of the Cartesian ‗I‘ and

the sharp division between mind and world in the Cartesian picture that make it difficult for a

transcendental argument to work on such a view. However, we can also see Kant‘s strategy.

He has tried to start from a premise his opponent accepts and to take the problematic idealist‘s

criterion of knowledge (indubitability) seriously. The argument then moves on:

If we accept that to be conscious of my own existence that consciousness must be

determined in time, there is still a question as to what determines time. Why should we think

that the experiences of t1 and t2 are separate such that they can be joined by me? Kant‘s

thought is this: we understand time through change in something permanent; ‗I‘ is a mere

‗spontaneous representation‘ determined itself by time. The intuitions that ‗I‘ accompanies are

similarly fleeting. Hence, the ‗something permanent‘ must come from outer sense—i.e. it must

be external. Moreover, outer sense must be so arranged that it contain things distinct from me

that persist over time. In order to understand them as being distinct from me they are

27 References to Descartes Meditations on First Philosophy are to the John Cottingham (1996) translation and are

abbreviated to ‗Meditations‘.

Page 41: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

41

conceived of as persisting even when not perceived. We need another dimension along which

they can be separated from us—to appreciate that things can persist in time although not

perceived. We need to think of them as being somewhere else. These things are external

spatial objects.

Thus, Kant believes he has proven the existence of material objects in a way that the

problematic idealist would be forced to accept: to be capable of recognising that I am, there

must be a material world. We have reason to think that the argument is not well-aimed if

considered as a direct response to Descartes, who has his own argument for the existence of

the material world and whose understanding of ‗I am‘ can be interpreted as significantly

different to the ‗I am‘ of Kant‘s first premise. However, one can certainly see what Kant is

trying to do: taking a psychological premise held immune from doubt by his opponent and

arguing that that which his opponent doubts (the existence of external spatial objects) is a

necessary condition of the truth of that premise. The strength of the justification of the first

premise should carry over to the justification of the conclusion, removing it from doubt. It is

this pattern of argument that, more than anything, has influenced the more recent philosophers

who interest me.

2.3.4 Transcendental Idealism, Berkeleyan Idealism, and Scepticism

I move now to consider the similarities and differences between Kant‘s transcendental

idealism and the Berkeleyan idealism that he also supposes to be refuted by this argument.

This is significant because the differences between the two are not as great as Kant believes,

and that this gives us reason to think that the Refutation will not be reassuring to the sceptic.

It is tempting to look at the Refutation of Idealism as an anti-sceptical argument, for it

seeks to establish the existence of external spatial objects. However, what is meant by

‗external‘ and ‗spatial‘ for the transcendental idealist is significantly different than what is

meant by my sceptic. Dogmatic idealism, as Kant presents it, is the position that the existence

of external objects in space is impossible. Kant (B 274) supposes that the mistake that leads

the dogmatic idealist to this position is the supposition that space is a property of things-in-

themselves. For Kant, space is the form of outer intuition. It orders and arranges the manifold

of intuition such that is it intelligible for us. Objects in space are material, but they are also

distinguished from things-in-themselves. Berkeley rejects matter because it is supposed to be

Page 42: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

42

some property of things-in-themselves, and he finds it, as such, unintelligible. However, it is

not nearly so clear that he rejects the existence of space as Kant understands it.

In the Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, Philonous, challenges Hylas to

define what matter is, and to argue for its existence, and what they find is that there is actually

no intelligible way of understanding what matter is, and, indeed, no need to suppose its

existence. Philonous says of the word ‗matter‘: ‗it is plain, by your own confession, there was

included no idea at all‘ (Berkeley TD II.22628

). However, Berkeley (TD I.190) clearly

differentiates matter from extension, saying: ‗no figure or mode of extension… can be really

inherent in matter‘. This is not necessarily to say that spatial objects do not exist, but rather

that properties (such as extension) which we attribute to space are a feature of the way our

ideas relate to one another, or, as Kant would say, the form that determines our (outer)

intuition. Extension is a property of sensations, and varies with them, as Berkeley (TD I.189)

writes: ‗as we approach or recede from an object, the visible extension varies‘. It is

‗acknowledged to have no existence without the mind‘ (Berkeley TD I.191), but this is not to

say that it does not exist at all.

Moreover, in the ‗Third Dialogue‘, Berkeley (TD III.261–3) also raises a possible

differentiation between ‗matter‘ or ‗material substance‘, as the philosophers talk about them,

and ‗matter‘ as a species of sensible thing. The latter Berkeley is perfectly happy to allow

exists. So, the question, then, is whether it is the philosopher‘s ‗matter‘ and ‗material

substance‘ that Kant sees the material idealism as denying or doubting.

On the one hand, Berkeley (TD III.261) has Philonous say: ‗With all my heart: retain

the word matter, and apply it to objects of sense, if you please, provided you do not attribute

to them any subsistence distinct from their being perceived‘. This is perfectly in accord with

Kant, and could almost be taken to express his own point of view. Matter can be said to be a

property of objects of sense—are these that different from what Kant calls ‗objects of

experience‘, ‗objects of sensibility‘, ‗objects as such‘, and even directly: ‗objects of sense‘?

(See, for example, Kant 1996: B 41, A 92–3/B 125–6, A 115–6, B 148–9). What Philonous

says appears to accord well with Kant‘s assertions that: ‗Space is nothing but the mere form of

all appearances of outer senses… Only from the human standpoint, therefore, can we speak of

28 References indicated by ‗TD‘ are to the 1734 edition as reprinted by Jonathan Dancy in 1998; I therefore use

the pagination of the 1734 edition, as included by Dancy.

Page 43: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

43

space, extended beings, etc. … This predicate is ascribed to things… only insofar as they are

objects of sensibility‘ (Kant A 26–7/B 42–3). Thus, Kant and Berkeley seem very much in

accord: matter, space, extension—these are properties of objects, but objects of sense, not the

transcendental object, or thing-in-itself.

However, Kant does specify that his project for the ‗Refutation of Idealism‘ is to prove

‗the existence of objects in space outside me‘—there is an externality to Kant‘s objects of

sense that would appear to not sit so well with Berkeley. For Berkeley (TD III.261) writes:

‗there is no matter, if by that term you meant an unthinking substance existing without the

mind‘. That said, there sometimes seems to be in Berkeley a blurring of the distinction

between a particular mind (as in the class of minded existents) and all minds. He writes:

sensible things cannot exist otherwise than in a mind or spirit. Whence I conclude, not

that they have no real existence, but that seeing they depend not on my thought, and

have an existence distinct from being perceived by me, there must be some other mind

wherein they exist… an infinite, omnipresent spirit. (Berkeley TD II.212)

I. e. sensible things (or at least, some sensible things) exist in the mind of God. Not external to

mind, in that it is not external to all minds, but certainly external to a mind, specifically, one‘s

own.

So it is at least arguable that Berkeley understands objects of sense to be external, yet

at the same time, I think we must allow that this is still something different to what Kant

means. Kant does not argue, as Berkeley does, that there is no such thing as a thing-in-itself,

but rather that: ‗The transcendental object… remains unknown‘ (Kant A 46/B 63). It does not

seem that the sort of externality we might claim for Berkeley would satisfy Kant. There is

something much more akin to the ‗philosophical‘ sense of matter in the materialism Kant

thinks it is wrong to reject. Furthermore, Kant sees no reason to rule out that which is

unknown, or even unknowable; but the fact that ‗matter‘ in the philosophical sense, is

unintelligible to us, is taken by Berkeley as a reason to suppose that it does not exist. Where

Berkeley states that there is nothing but the minded and sensible things, Kant argues that we

should not claim to know anything about things-in-themselves, and that admitting this does

not limit our knowledge of the existence of external objects in space.

What emerges from this discussion is that Berkeleyan idealism and Kantian

transcendental idealism are not entirely different in their belief that there exist objects of sense

Page 44: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

44

which have extension and object permanence rooted in something external to an individual‘s

mind. For Kant it is the outer sense of space, for Berkeley, God. They differ in that Berkeley

denies the existence of things-in-themselves, and although Kant does believe that there are

things-in-themselves, his Refutation of Idealism does not address this. Things-in-themselves

are unknowable.

My sceptic is concerned that she might have all the experiences she now has without

there being a mind-independent world causing those experiences. In this context, Berkeleyan

idealism represents a sceptical hypothesis. Extension is a mere relation of sensible things, and

our understanding of words like ‗matter‘ and ‗space‘ must be adjusted to match this. Berkeley

would say that this is how people untrained in philosophy speak anyway, but in my

introduction I showed that the possibility that what we experience is not caused by something

beyond the senses is regarded as a worry in many cultural items enjoyed popularly by those

untrained in philosophy.

Where Berkeleyan idealism expresses the sceptical hypothesis, transcendental idealism

can be understood as expressing the doubt. There is something out there (things-in-

themselves) that causes the intuitions we then form into spatiotemporal objects of sense, but

we cannot know anything about those things. The Refutation of Idealism offers comfort to

Kant because all he is concerned with are external objects in space—he has severed from his

concepts of space and externality the mind-independence I require to assuage the sceptic.

For this reason, transcendental idealism and the Refutation of Idealism cannot provide

me with a solution to this problem. However, I do find in this style of argument the kernel of

an approach, taken up by twentieth and twenty-first century analytic philosophers, wherein we

may find a viable approach.

So this, then, would seem to be the form of idealism Kant is anxious to distance

himself from. It is the theory that it is either false or indemonstrable that there should be

external objects in space; where ‗external‘ is taken in a more robust sense than Berkeley‘s

assertion that at least some perceived ideas exist in the mind of God, and yet is not so robust as

to refer to these objects as things-in-themselves. Moreover, Kant would reject an idealism that

asserted matter to be a property of things-in-themselves, and hence moved from a rejection of

things in themselves to a rejection of matter.

Page 45: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

45

2.4 Austin

Barry Stroud (2000d: 203)29

, gives the first use of the term ‗transcendental argument‘ as

coming from J L Austin in his 1939 paper ‗Are There A Priori Concepts?‘3031

. Austin‘s

primary purpose is not to give a definition of transcendental arguments, so what he means

must be extracted from his discussion.

Austin first raises the term in analysing an argument for universals, which he

characterises as being based on these assumptions: we sense multiple things that are different

to one another, we call the different ‗sensa‘ by the same ‗name‘ (‗we say ―This is grey‖, and

―That is grey‖‘), this practice is considered ‗justifiable‘ in the sense that it is indispensible. It

is then argued, firstly, that because we use the same name for different things, there must be

something that is identical that is so named and is in common to all the sensa to which it is

applied: a universal. Secondly, because the things sensed are ‗many and different‘, the

universal, as single and identical, must not be sensed (see Austin 2003: 33–4).

Austin (2003: 34) gives two ways in which we can understand the above argument to

be transcendental, one which is owed to Kant, and another which he says is not. It is ‗Kantian‘

sense in that it argues that: ‗if there were not in existence something other than sensa, we

should not be able to do what we are able to do‘. It is considered to be transcendental in

another sense in that it aims to ‗prov[e] the existence of a class of entities different in kind

from sensa (viz. name things [universals])‘ (ibid.).

He also examines another argument, which he holds to be transcendental:

A true statement is one which corresponds with reality: the statements of the scientist

are true: therefore there are realities which correspond to those statements. Sensa do

not correspond to the statements of the scientist… therefore there must exist other

29 References to Stroud are to the 2000 edition of his collected papers, Understanding Human Knowledge:

Philosophical Essays. Individual papers are distinguished as 2000a, 2000b, 2000c, and 2000d relative to their

positioning within that work.

30 References here refer to the 2003 edition.

31 Stern (2000: 8, n. 8) notes that there are preceding instances. Kant uses the term ‗transcendental arguemnt‘ at A

627/B 655, but he uses it to mean something that ‗goes beyond the legitimate employment of understanding‘

(ibid.), this is therefore a different use to both Kantian transcendental deduction and what in meant by the modern

term ‗transcendental argument‘. Additionally, C S Pierce used the term in 1902; however, as his use has had no

significant impact on the development of the use of the term, I leave it to one side.

Page 46: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

46

objects, real but not sensible, which do correspond to the statements of the scientist.

Let these be called ‗universals‘. (2003: 35)

Austin says that this argument is transcendental in that:

The ‗universal‘ is an x, which is to solve our problem for us: we know only that it is

non‐sensible, and in addition must possess certain characters, the lack of which

prohibits sensa from corresponding to the statements of the scientist. (ibid.)

Austin does not say how this relates to either of the characterisations of what it is to be

transcendental that he gave before, but I think we can draw two senses in which the argument

may be considered transcendental from this. Firstly, the argument starts from something

assumed to be true: ‗the statements of the scientist are true‘. Then we are given a problem:

Sensa do not correspond to the statements of the scientist. Given this, an explanation is

required of how both statements about sensa and scientific statements can be true. The

explanation is that there are real things which correspond to the statements of scientists and to

which sensa are appropriately related to make sense of them as well. This is transcendental in

the sense that the transcendental deduction is transcendental. It is not so much an argument as

an accounting for the justification we already have to hold certain statements to be true. The

first argument also reflects a flavour of this—one of the assumptions was that we were already

justified in the indispensible practice of referring to multiple sensa by the same name, and the

existence of universals provides an accounting for this.

One can see this sense of being transcendental as both similar and different to the

senses given above. In the first sense, we are able to know scientific statements to be true

because there is something in existence other than sensa. In the second sense, we could read it

as an attempt to prove the existence of a class of entities different in kind from sensa. In

another sense, it is like neither, for if it were a transcendental deduction in the true Kantian

sense, it would not be trying to give a truth, but rather an accounting for justification of

something that is already known.

Stroud reads this differently. On Stroud‘s (2000: 204) analysis, there is nothing special

about the first argument as Austin summarises it, it is just an instantiation of modus tollens: if

there did not exist a different kind of entity from sensa, we would not be able to name things;

we do name things, so there is a different kind of entities from sensa. Modus tollens is not a

Page 47: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

47

particularly special or new form of argument that we owe to Kant, so whatever it is that makes

transcendental arguments special must be something else.

Looking to the second argument for help, Stroud characterises it thusly:

attempting to prove something by showing that it is required as a solution to a

problem: in this case, how is it possible for science to make true statements about

reality, given that they are not statements about ―sensa‖. Stroud (2000d: 205)

Which sounds similar to my own reading, but what Stroud identifies as the characteristic

exhibited by this strategy is that the argument is to prove that one thing is a necessary

condition of another. As we shall see, this conforms to Stroud‘s overall conception of

transcendental arguments, but differs from the more Kantian reading. Moreover, as Stroud

(ibid.) states, this cannot be a sufficient condition for an argument‘s being transcendental. It is

much too broad: all valid deductions would thereby be transcendental. They also share the

characteristic of trying to show that something is a necessary condition of something we do

that is justified or indispensable. This, also, Stroud argues, is not enough: on this definition we

could transcendentally prove the existence of bananas on the basis of the fact that we eat them.

I wonder if Stroud has not got a bit muddled, here. It is not indispensably true that I eat

bananas. I think he is thinking of the indispensability of there being bananas on condition that

I have eaten some, which would be a much more ordinary form of necessity. However, to be

like Austin‘s examples, the thing known to be true is that which is indispensible, and this is

why the indispensability requires explaining. For the example to be relevantly similar it would

need for my eating of bananas to be indispensible, which it clearly is not.

Stroud goes on to note that Kant was specifically concerned with our thought and

experience of things, the objects of our thought or experience. Something that is required for

thought or experience has a special status, he argues (above what is required for the eating of

bananas). Stroud notes that Kant saw thought and experience as the starting point of

metaphysics, and a starting point that would make metaphysics a secure science—but why?

Well, we quite clearly do think and experience things. As Kant notes in the Refutation, even

the problematic and dogmatic idealist must grant that; and we might add: even the sceptic

does. Hence: anything that is found to be a necessary condition of thought or experience must

be true. As Stroud (2000d: 207) says: ‗they cannot fail to hold if we think at all‘.

Page 48: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

48

In this, I think Stroud is correct that this is an essential part of the kind of

transcendental argument we find in the Refutation of Idealism, precisely because the

Refutation is looking to a) start from a premise accepted by the problematic and dogmatic

idealists, and b) meet the high standard set for justification by the problematic idealist. It is

also true that this is a primary concern to Austin, who is dealing with the relationship of sensa

to universals. However, it is important to understand that it is not a transcendental argument in

the sense that the transcendental deduction is. Just as Kant would not have recognised the

Refutation as a transcendental deduction. Because for Kant the indispensability lies in the

assumption that requires explaining. I suspect this is why Austin differentiates both a Kantian

and a non-Kantian sense in which an argument may be a transcendental. One is an accounting

for the justification of some already accepted phenomena, the other is a proof of something

based on it being a necessary condition of some fact about thought or experience. In the latter

the nature of the proof is ‗transcendental‘ in that it seeks to ‗transcend‘ what Strawson would

later call the ‗bounds of sense‘ by starting with a premise concerning thought or experience an

moving to a conclusion concerning something ‗beyond‘ that boundary. In the former, the form

of deduction is not transcendental, it is simply the accounting for our justification to know

something we do in fact know, it is the subject matter (the application of the categories to

objects of sense) of the deduction that is transcendental.

A failure to differentiate these two kinds of transcendental approach has led to both

innovation and confusion. In a sense, it does not matter if one is reading Kant correctly, but as

philosophers have continued to reference their understanding of transcendental arguments

back to Kant, this confusion has influenced how transcendental arguments have developed.

2.5 Strawson: Individuals

Perhaps the most influential figure in the development of transcendental arguments since Kant

is P F Strawson. His two seminal works, Individuals (195932

) and The Bounds of Sense

(196633

), mark two significant transcendental paths of his early thought. The subtitle of

Individuals, ‗An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics‘, clearly demarcates his approach as

32 References refer to the 1987 edition.

33 References are to the 1976 edition.

Page 49: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

49

specifically descriptive, as opposed to ‗revisionist‘. It is a style of conducting metaphysics that

he attributes to Kant and Aristotle, and which is distinguished by seeking to clarify the

necessary connections between our concepts and describing the fundamental concepts that

underlie the varying metaphysical views of different times: the ‗permanent relationships‘

described in ‗impermanent idiom‘ (see Strawson, 1987: 10–11).

I particular, Strawson argues that material bodies and persons occupy a central place as

fundamental particulars (Strawson 1987: 11). There is no space here to examine his arguments

in any great detail, but the key is to note Strawson‘s methodology. The descriptive approach,

which Strawson attributes to Kant, is not exactly akin to the ‗accounting for our justification‘

approach that I have ascribed to the Transcendental Deduction. Yet this mapping out of

conceptual relations is strongly reminiscent of Kant‘s description of the categories and their

relation to our ability to have the kinds of thoughts and experiences we do in fact have.

Moreover, Strawson‘s arguments take the form of looking at what we are capable and

considering what must be the case for this to be so. Thus he moves from noting our ability to

identify particulars in speech to the necessity of there being objective particulars located in

space and time, distinct from the individual (see Strawson 1976: 9–30). From our ability to

reidentify particulars to the necessity of our supposing that there is some dimension along

which they continue to exist when not present to our minds, and via which they can again be

found by returning to the same ‗place‘—a point along that dimension at which the particular

was supposed to have been when last we encountered it, and at which it remained when we

moved to some other place along that dimension (see Strawson 1976: 31–8). Thus we move

from that which we certainly do know about our conceptual capacities to the discovery of how

we are required to conceive of the world in order to have these conceptions we do in fact have.

This, too, bares similarities to Kant, especially with regard to the importance of space

and time as organising factors in enabling us to conceptualise our experiences in the way we

do. Although the similarity should not be overstressed. The metaphysics Strawson describes is

not one of transcendental idealism, but one of material bodies located in dimensions of space

and time, rather than space and time as the forms imposed on inner and outer intuition in order

to ‗form‘ intelligible experiences for us. Nevertheless, it‘s never clear that what we get from

Individuals is an argument for the existence of persons and material objective particulars, or if

merely the concept of such things is essential to our human conceptual schemes.

Page 50: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

50

2.6 Strawson’s Transcendental Deduction and The Bounds of Sense

In The Bounds of Sense, Strawson attempts to reconstruct a version of the Transcendental

Deduction that is accessible from an analytic approach and which does not rely upon Kant‘s

transcendental idealism and what Strawson calls Kant‘s ‗transcendental psychology‘ (see

Strawson 1976: 88–89). By ‗transcendental psychology‘ Strawson means those elements of

the deduction that he sees as having a more explanatory role, detailing the way in which Kant

understands our faculties as they relate to experience as it functions under his transcendental

idealism.

As such, this is a deliberate departure from what I have characterised as an explanatory

kind of transcendental philosophy and a move towards a kind of transcendental argument, one

that rejects the transcendental idealism that Kant sees as a solution and that my sceptic regards

as a worry. It is this kind of transcendental argument that I believe may be fruitful in

answering the sceptic; although I hasten to add that I am not defending this argument in

particular, and shall therefore not dwell on defending its details.

Strawson‘s interpretation of the Transcendental Deduction is articulated over sections

five to eight of Part II of The Bounds of Sense. It may be summarised thusly. It is a necessary

condition of the possibility of experience that it be possible for one to self-ascribe diverse

experiences to a numerically identical self (Strawson 1976: 110). This self-ascription is taken

minimally as a kind of self-reflexiveness that is to be a necessary pre-condition of self-

consciousness (Strawson 1976: 107). The claim is not intended as a sufficient condition for

self-consciousness, but as a necessary precondition of it. Kant‘s acceptance of the bundle

theory of identity means that there is no empirical self to be encountered in experience;

Strawson cites in particular the passage where Kant writes:

In the synthetic original unity of apperception I am conscious of myself not as I appear

to myself, nor as I am in myself, but only that I am. This representation is a thought,

not an intuition. (Kant B 157; quoted in Strawson 1976: 95)

Which is understood to mean that one neither encounters a representation of oneself in

experience, nor oneself as a thing-in-itself, merely the accompanying thought ‗I am‘ that is

with all other experiences, linking them as a unified presentation. It is a ‗transcendental

consciousness‘, rather than an ‗empirical self-consciousness‘, in that while it does not

Page 51: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

51

constitute the recognition of oneself as a conscious being, it is a necessary condition of that

recognition, as it provides a unifying character to one‘s experiences (Strawson 1976: 95).

Strawson reads Kant‘s argument as being that the synthesis, by the imagination, of

diverse discrete sense data under the categories determined by the faculty of understanding, is

the necessary precondition of ascribing experiences to oneself, thus offering an explanation of

the ‗unity of diverse representations in a single consciousness‘ (Strawson 1976: 96; see also

97). He finds this explanation unsatisfactory, and seeks to provide an alternative account of the

precondition of self-ascription requiring this unity that does not rely upon such transcendental

psychological talk of ‗synthesis‘ and the workings of the faculties of imagination and

understanding. Instead, he thinks we can draw on the ‗necessary duality of intuition and

concept‘ (Strawson 1976: 97). This notion takes a little unpacking. Strawson characterises

‗intuitions‘ as: ‗[Kant's] word for awareness in experience of particular instances of general

concepts‘ (Strawson 1978: 20). They are to be distinguished, then, from mere awareness—

intuitions are awareness of something, but without bringing the intuition under a concept, one

cannot have a sense of what that awareness is of. Recall Kant‘s statement that: ‗thoughts

without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind‘ (A 51/B 75). Understood on

Strawson‘s interpretation, this means that intuitions are not really things of which we can be

aware unless they are conceptualised as particular instances of a certain kind of thing. At the

same time, the thought that ‗I am‘ is empty unless it is accompanying an intuition, for the

transcendental self is nothing more than the unification of diverse experiences as belonging to

the same individual. It is a symbiotic relationship: intuitions are not purely states of awareness

that the subject has, and if they were, the subject would not be able to make anything of them.

What, then, is it for an intuition to be brought under a concept? It is to make a

judgement about what the intuition is of, for example ‗―this is a heavy stone‖‘ (Strawson 1976:

101), and to make a judgement is to attribute objectivity to the thing judged, in the sense that it

has an existence independent of that which is perceived: ‗esse‘ (existence) is distinct from

‗percipi‘ (perception) (Strawson 1976: 100). Part of judging something to be the case is an

acknowledgement that it might not be the case, or it might not have been the case—there must

be room for correction (see Strawson 1976: 106). For a judgement to claim ‗objective validity‘

is for it to claim a validity independent of the subject. Judgement requires a distinction

between how things are objectively and how things are subjectively. When I apply a concept

and judge that an object of my experience is thus and so, I am inherently attributing to the

Page 52: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

52

object an existence as a part of an ordered reality that may differ from my experience of it,

thus: ‗experience of objects is possible only if objectively valid judgements are possible‘

(Strawson 1976: 98). It is only possible to make judgements if that which the judgements are

made of is of a unity distinct from the unity of one‘s own mind.

So. Experience is only possible under judgement. Experiences must have an order and

arrangement of their own distinct from the order and arrangement as we are aware of them, or

there will not be any meaning to the judegment. Therefore experience requires self-ascription

and a sense of an ordered reality distinct from what is ascribed to the self. It is therefore a

necessary condition of my having the experiences I do have that there be an objective, mind-

independent reality: ‗our pictures of the objective world and our picture of possible perceptual

routes through it cannot be independent of each other‘ (Strawson 1976: 105).

Thus, the Strawsonian interpretation of the Transcendental Deduction is one that aims

to show that the existence of a mind-independent objective reality is a necessary condition of

the possibility experience and self-ascription of experience. Given that we do have

experiences and do ascribe them to ourselves in a unified manner, there must be an objective

world (or at least, we must have a ‗picture‘ of such an objective world).

2.7 Stroud and Transcendental Arguments

Barry Stroud‘s attempts to offer a systematic characterisation and criticism of transcendental

arguments have been as influential as Strawson‘s move to take transcendental arguments

seriously in an analytic context. His criticisms have contributed towards a shift in focus

towards a less ambitious, weak form of transcendental arguments. I will look in detail at

Stroud‘s criticisms in chapter four, but for the moment, my purpose is to draw out what he

views as the defining characteristics of transcendental argument.

Stroud‘s assessment of what it is for an argument to be transcendental is variable. He

talks of the significance both of the ‗goal‘ of transcendental arguments and of the content of

their premises. At times he seems to focus overly on the historical origins in Kant, and at other

times to have more concern with how modern transcendental arguments can and do

distinguish themselves from this. Of course, it would be surprising if there were no

development to be found in Stroud‘s thought from 1968 to today, but it is often difficult to

untangle the different lines of thought and see what conclusions have actually been drawn. My

Page 53: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

53

purpose over the next few sections is to unpick the varieties of transcendental argument Stroud

identifies.

2.7.1 Transcendental Arguments as Anti-sceptical

Stroud initially saw the Transcendental Deduction and the Refutation of Idealism as part of the

same project, one aimed at refuting the sceptic. In his seminal 1968 paper, ‗Transcendental

Arguments‘ (Stroud 2000a), he begins his characterisation of what a transcendental argument

is with a return to Kant, and an outline of what he perceives the motivation of Kant‘s project

to be. At odds with the interpretation I have given, Stroud understands the question of our

‗rights‘ or ‗justification‘ for certain propositions, with which Kant is interested in the

Transcendental Deduction, as concerned with ‗the challenge presented by the epistemological

sceptic‘ (Stroud 2000a: 10). One can understand why he sees it thus when he quotes a passage

from the B text where Kant writes that it is ‗a scandal to philosophy and to human reason in

general that the existence of things outside us… must be accepted merely on faith‘ (B xl).

Stroud does not define the epistemological sceptic precisely, but one may infer from his

concerns that this is one who doubts our knowledge of the external world, and elsewhere he

has written that the concern of philosophical scepticism can be conceived of as the worry that

it is logically possible that things might seem to us just as they do without the existence of

physical or material objects outside the mind. His sceptic is this very similar to my own (see

Stroud 1979: 278).

Certainly, as can be seen in the Refutation, Kant is concerned with dispelling doubt in

the existence of things outside of us and, in that passage, he is concerned to show that his

philosophy can demonstrate the fault of such doubts. However, I think it is mistaken to

interpret Kant‘s understanding of what a transcendental deduction is concerned with in terms

of its potential as a tool against the sceptic. As outlined above, I think Kant is interested in

doing something subtly different. Kant believes that the a priori application of these concepts

has already been established; what he is looking to do in the deduction is demonstrate our

right to them.

To the analytic philosopher, this seems a very strange way to go about things: looking

for a justification of concepts that have already been established. I think this is why Stroud

feels the pressure to read these two projects within the Critique of Pure Reason as aimed at the

Page 54: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

54

same goal: rebutting the sceptic. Moreover, Strawson‘s work reconceiving the Transcendental

Deduction in a form similar to that of the Refutation of Idealism (in which an objective world

is established as a necessary condition of our thought and experience) encourages this view.

To do justice to Stroud, he does recognise this difference elsewhere. In ‗Kantian

Argument, Conceptual Capacities, and Invulnerability‘ (1994)34

he distinguishes two aspects

of Kantian strategy. One aspect he identifies is establishing ‗the invulnerability of certain

fundamental ingredients in our conception of the world‘; the other is ‗the question of how that

invulnerability is to be established‘ (Stroud 2000b: 158). Although Stroud states that this is not

a distinction Kant recognised himself, I would argue, rather, that Kant did distinguish between

these two aspects, but saw only the latter as being the direct concern of transcendental

deduction. True, the ‗invulnerability‘ of certain claims to knowledge is a significant aspect (or

at least, consequence) of Kant‘s transcendental philosophy—one that he explores in the

Refutation of Idealism and uses to emphasise the distinction between his own form of idealism

and that of dogmatic and problematic idealism—but it is distinct from the goal of the

Transcendental Deduction, and hence, I think, from what Kant would have thought of as the

distinctive kind of argument he engaged in there.

The invulnerability of the conclusion of a transcendental argument, ‗those broad

features of our conception of the world which are themselves necessary conditions of our

thinking about or experiencing anything at all‘ (ibid.), remains a focus of Stroud‘s

understanding of transcendental arguments. He returns to this thought again, in ‗The Goal of

Transcendental Arguments‘ (1999)35

, although there his aim is to persuade us that a different

goal might be more fruitful. This is because of the criticisms Stroud raises in ‗Transcendental

Arguments‘ and later papers which are that: 1. transcendental arguments that aim at defeating

an external world sceptic always rely on a suppressed verification principle, and 2. to reason

from premises about the mind to conclusions about the world would require an implausible

‗bridge of necessity‘. A full account and assessment of these criticisms is reserved for chapter

four, but for now it is sufficient to note that these thoughts motivate a move away from

thinking of sceptical arguments as a tool useful for directly refuting the external world sceptic.

34 References are to the 2000b edition.

35 References are to the 2000c edition.

Page 55: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

55

2.7.2 Goals for Transcendental Arguments

Although the title of the paper highlights the fact that he still thinks that the transcendental

target, as it were, is of significance, several different options are presented in ‗The Goal of

Transcendental Arguments‘. On Stroud‘s (2000d: 204) analysis of Austin, the arguments

considered are transcendental in that entities that ‗transcend‘ sense experience—universals—

are (intended to be) proven to exist on the basis that they are in some sense ‗required‘ for some

practice we undertake ‗justifiably‘ or indispensably. As Stroud takes these arguments to be

structurally no different from modus tollens, he declares that the key difference is their goal:

‗what makes it transcendental is not its logical form or its subject matter, but its aim or

goal‘(Stroud 2000d: 205). The goal here being establishing the existence of something not

found directly in sense experience.

Elsewhere, this goal-centric claim is qualified. Stroud writes that: ‗Kant was concerned

with the necessary conditions… in particular of our thinking or experiencing things—of there

being ―objects‖ of our thoughts and perceptions‘, and that: ‗To show that something is

required for thought or experience would be to show that it has a very special status…

transcendental status‘ (Stroud 2000d: 207). This suggests that what is distinctive is not just the

goal in the sense of demonstrating the truth of something that the sceptic denies or something

that transcends sense experience, but to do so in a specific way: by showing that the truth of

the conclusion is a necessary condition of thought or experience. Hence, the nature of the

premises and their subject matter would seem to be significant. Furthermore, he writes:

To say that scepticism can be used to draw attention to the special character of

transcendental arguments is not to say that the only point of going for transcendental

arguments is to refute scepticism, or to suggest that that is mainly what Kant was

trying to do. (Stroud 2000d: 211)

This is a distinct departure from his characterisation in ‗Transcendental Arguments‘36

, and it is

more useful to us. Being anti-sceptical is no longer considered the ‗goal‘, rather, consideration

36 Stroud (2000d: 208–9) claims that it is a mistake to suppose that he had Kant and Kant‘s transcendental

idealism in mind when, in 1968, he raised ‗those questions‘ about whether a transcendental strategy can succeed.

Certainly, it is fair to say that he was not considering the potential success of transcendental idealism and Kant‘s

transcendental deduction as an instantiation of this kind of strategy. However, he was drawing on his

Page 56: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

56

of the anti-sceptical role of many transcendental arguments helps draw out what is distinctive

about transcendental projects. Scepticism does this, he claims, because the very propositions

doubted by the sceptic are necessary conditions of our having the thoughts and experience

necessary to ask sceptical questions. As he puts it: ‗A positive, reassuring answer to the

question is shown to be built into our asking it, and so to be guaranteed‘ (ibid.).

Freed from taking the defeat of the epistemological sceptic as a defining element of

transcendental arguments, Stroud moves forward to advocate a different kind of transcendental

argument, with a different kind of goal. It is a goal he finds in Strawson‘s later work.

Strawson, he notes, has become content to explore the necessary connections between

concepts along the lines that ‗Given I have concept x, I must also have concept y‘ (see Stroud

2000b: 163 and 166, and 2000d: 213). This is because (according to Stroud 2000b: 165)

Strawson regards the sceptical question as ‗idle‘, in that we could never actually be made to

change our minds about the existence of objective particulars and so on. This is a shift towards

what we may call ‗weak‘ transcendental arguments, as opposed to ‗strong‘ transcendental

arguments, conceived of as attempting to rebut the epistemological or external world sceptic.

2.7.3 Strawson: Naturalism and Scepticism

In Skepticism and Naturalism (1985)37

, Strawson advocates a more ‗naturalistic‘ approach to

dealing with the sceptic than the kind of ambitious project he explored in The Bounds of

Sense. In this he advocates a response to scepticism that ‗does not so much attempt to meet the

challenge as to pass it by‘ (Strawson 1985: 3). This is a return to, or a reinterpretation of, the

Humean response to scepticism. Strawson conceives of it as both naturalistic and

transcendental.

Strawson understands Hume as saying that ‗all arguments in support of the sceptical

position are totally inefficacious; and, by the same token, all arguments against it are totally

idle‘ (Strawson 1985: 11). The sense in which Nature determines that we cannot accept the

understanding of what he took to be Kant‘s project as a way of understanding and characterising transcendental

projects in general.

37 Based on his Woodbridge Lectures delivered at Columbia University in 1983.

Page 57: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

57

sceptical conclusion is that belief in the body and in other minds is ‗inescapable‘ (ibid.). This

is transcendental in the sense that:

in order for the intelligible formulation of skeptical doubts to be possible or, more

generally, in order for self-conscious thought and experience to be possible, we must

take it, or believe, that we have knowledge of external objects or other minds.

(Strawson 1985: 21)

This is not the move that Stroud was so critical of in ‗Transcendental Arguments‘—i.e. a

move from a psychological fact about what we must believe to a fact about how the world

must be—it is what Strawson calls an ‗only connect‘ model of transcendental arguments (see

Strawson 1985: 21–2). The argument establishes something about how we must conceive the

world based on the concepts we must have in order to form sceptical doubts in the first place,

or to have self-conscious thought or experience at all. This kind of transcendental argument

harks back to the descriptive metaphysics of Individuals—transcendental arguments merely

elucidate the necessary connections between concepts. It is a natural fact that we cannot accept

the sceptic‘s conclusion, and therefore the question is idle.

2.7.4 Stroud and Weak Transcendental Arguments

Stroud, although wanting something weaker than what he calls ‗strong‘ or ‗would be‘

transcendental arguments, still thinks that there is something more than this ‗natural fact‘

about what we can believe that transcendental arguments can uncover for us. He thinks that

via this kind of Strawsonian conceptual analysis we might be able to establish a sort of

invulnerability to certain beliefs; we might find that some beliefs are required in order for us to

have any beliefs at all, and it would be from this that we could say that it would be impossible

to find that belief false. This he takes to be stronger than Strawson‘s thought, because it

bestows a kind of ‗invulnerability‘ on certain beliefs. There would thus be some kind of

reassurance in knowing that it would be impossible to find these beliefs to be false. (See

Stroud 2000b: 165–6, and 2000d: 216.)

To defend this sense that weak transcendental arguments can deliver invulnerability,

Stroud draws particularly on what he thinks of as the ‗weak‘ version of Davidson‘s

transcendental argument from triangulation, the gist of which is that: ‗If we ascribe beliefs to

Page 58: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

58

others, we must assume that they, and, by extension, we, are largely correct‘38

, thus rendering

it impossible for us to find that our beliefs about the world are not, for the most part, true. This

is outlined particularly in ‗Radical Interpretation and Philosophical Scepticism‘ (1999)39

.

Stroud writes:

The possibility from which the sceptical line of thinking begins is therefore not one

which anyone could consistently find to be actual. It involves the presence of certain

38 To say that this is a very brief account of Davidson‘s argument is an understatement. Davidson‘s argument

from triangulation is arises from his theory of meaning and radical interpretation, unfurled across many papers.

The above is a summary sufficient for the discussion of what Stroud takes from Davidson, focusing on the role of

charity in the ascription of belief to others. This ‗charity‘ is understood through principles of Coherence and

Correspondence, according to which, in order to interpret another, one must attribute a certain amount of logical

consistency to the thoughts of a speaker, and a certain amount of correspondence with features of the world that

are shared with the interpreter (see Davidson 2002b: 148–9; 2002d: 211). This is more than simply a condition of

interpreting others, however, it is a condition it is a condition of knowing out own minds (see Davidson 2002a).

For Davidson, meaning is communal, ‗Communication begins where causes converge‘ (Davidson 2002b: 151).

Moreover, our very ability to have beliefs is dependent upon an understanding of objectivity (that beliefs can be

false), which Davidson holds to only be possible when confronted by error, which in turn is only possible against

a background of successful communication with another minded being about a shared external world of which

you are both largely correct. In order to understand someone contradicting your own assertions and beliefs, you

must have been referring to enough of the same things to interpret one another intelligibly. Davidson thus holds

that ‗Belief is in its nature veridical‘ (Davidson 2002b: 146). From this theory of meaning two possible kind of

transcendental argument emerge, one that is ambitious/strong, and one that is more modest. The difference turns

on whether we actually need to be in successful communication with another minded being about a shared

external world of which we are both largely correct, or if the same results can be achieved if we merely believe

that this is the case. Davidson at first thought that the former would be true, arguing that the coherence required

for interpretation would ‗yield correspondence‘ (Davidson 2002b: 137), that interpretation requires making

speakers right most of the time (ibid.), that ‗most beliefs are correct‘ (Davidson 2002c: 168), and that ‗a theory of

interpretation cannot be correct that makes a man assent to very many false sentences‘ (Davidson 2002c: 169).

However, in ‗Afterthoughts‘ (Davidson 2002b: 154–7) Davidson distances himself from these ambitious, anti-

sceptical claims, saying that what his arguments enable is not so much a refutation of the sceptic, but telling him

to ‗get lost‘; we have to attribute truth to a speaker‘s beliefs and consistency with our own, and to that extent it

does not matter whether those beliefs ‗correspond‘ to an independent reality. It is this, more modest argument

that Stroud argues in favour of: that we must assume that we and those we speak to are largely correct in our

beliefs.

39 References are to Stroud 2000c.

Page 59: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

59

specific beliefs, but attribution of those beliefs requires our finding them to be largely

true. Believing a certain set of propositions to be all or mostly false precludes our

assigning them as contents of the beliefs of any people we find to have beliefs. (Stroud

2000c: 198)

‗Invulnerability‘ is thereby understood in terms of our inability to find something to be actual.

Because belief attribution requires the assumption that both myself and the person to whom I

attribute beliefs are correct not just in that belief, but in most of our other beliefs. Scepticism,

as the thought that all or most of our beliefs might be false, is thus not simply ‗idle‘, but in a

certain sense impossible. In holding that I have beliefs that might be false the sceptic attributes

to me beliefs. Which is only possible if most of my beliefs are believed to be true. A weak

Davidsonian argument can thus be used to show that the belief that most of my beliefs are

largely true is invulnerable in the sense that I cannot doubt the truth of that belief without

believing it to be true. This does not show that it is not possible that I might be subject to a

sceptical scenario; rather, if this kind of weak transcendental argument is correct, then we

cannot believe the scenario to be true.

2.7.5 Stroud’s Taxonomy of Transcendental Arguments

We can therefore identify several different types of transcendental argument. 1. those that aim

to defeat the sceptic on the basis that it is a condition of sceptical doubt that the sceptical

hypothesis not hold. 2. those that aim to establish the existence of entities that ‗transcend‘

sense experience on the basis of some practice or belief that is indispensible to us. 3. those that

aim to establish that something is the case because it is a necessary condition of thought or

experience (the goal is not definitive here, it may be either anti-sceptical or not). 4.those that

aim merely to establish ‗natural facts‘ by articulate the necessary connections between our

concepts (these arguments are not directly anti-sceptical, but can be used to show that the

sceptical question is ‗idle‘, because we could not believe it). 5. those that aim to establish

invulnerability from sceptical doubt on the basis that it is a condition of our having thought or

experience that it be impossible to believe the sceptical hypothesis to be possible.

1 and 2 I understand as ‗strong‘ transcendental arguments, with 1 as ‗very strong‘, in

the sense that it not only aims to rebut sceptical doubt, but show that the truth of that which is

doubted is a condition of the doubt itself. I understand 4 and 5 to be ‗weak‘ transcendental

Page 60: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

60

arguments in the sense that they do not aim to establish that anything be true of the world, but

focus on showing what we must believe. I take it that whilst both of these arguments as

‗weak‘, Stroud sees 4 as weaker than 5, as its focus is on articulating natural facts about what

we must believe, given other beliefs we have, rather than establishing ‗invulnerability‘ for any

proposition. I take 3 to be more of a general characterisation of what it is for an argument to be

transcendental as a whole, not just because it covers both strong and weak transcendental

arguments as Stroud understands them, but because it characterises what I, also, find

interesting in them: establishing that something must be the case because it is a necessary

condition of thought or experience (whether that be merely that we must believe something, or

that something extra-mental is true) has value because thought and experience are prized as

more certainly know than the extra-mental, and if something is a necessary condition of the

truth of some prized proposition concerning the mental, then the justification we have for our

belief concerning the mental is transferred to whatever is a necessary condition of the truth of

that belief.

2.8 Why a Strong Transcendental Argument is Needed to Address my

Sceptic

In the preceding sections I have outlined an understanding of transcendental arguments as

these have descended from Kant. It is not possible in this space to articulate all varieties of

argument that have been termed transcendental, but these cover the broad categories. Clearly

the kind of deduction Kant originally described in the transcendental deduction will not be of

use in the context of responding to my sceptic. We cannot simply assume the truth of the

propositions the sceptic doubts, and providing an internally consistent account of the

psychological that cause us to have the types of thoughts and experiences we do have is not

sufficient. The sceptic concedes that one explanation for us having the types of thought and

experience we do have is that the world is much as it seems. The issue is that she thinks these

thoughts and experiences could be as easily explained by something radically different.

Page 61: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

61

We must then look to either strong or weak transcendental arguments as Stroud

describes them40

. Most recent philosophers have favoured the latter, taking strong

transcendental arguments to have been shown to be problematic by Stroud‘s criticisms.

However, I argue that weak transcendental arguments cannot provide a satisfactory answer to

my sceptic. In the remainder of this chapter I will articulate why weak transcendental

arguments cannot be of use to us, before going on in the rest of my thesis to defend the

plausibility of strong transcendental arguments.

2.8.1 Against Weak Transcendental Arguments

I am not convinced of the efficaciousness of Stroudian weak transcendental arguments against

scepticism. Perhaps one can construct an argument that shows that there are certain beliefs that

I simply cannot find to be false, but it does not follow from my being unable to find something

false that it is not false. Of course, Stroud does not think we should try to show the sceptical

scenario is not true, merely that it is impossible for us to believe it to be so, but this does not

render these belief invulnerable to doubt. Firstly, the Davidsonian style argument Stroud

advocates can only establish that at one time or at most times I must believe something to be

the case, or, at its most ambitious, that most of my beliefs are correct. But even if I must at

most times believe most of my beliefs to be correct, or even actively believe the denial of the

sceptical hypothesis, this does not rule out my intelligibly wondering if I am justified to such a

belief. That it was once necessary for me to conceive of the world in a certain way does not

make my doubting it now incoherent. Furthermore, even if the argument shows that I have to

conceive of it being that way now, it can still make sense to ask whether that which I have to

believe is so really is so.

Moreover, if such an argument were to succeed, I cannot help but concur with Burge

(2003: 345) that it would be rather more unsettling than reassuring, as: ‗The sceptic can

40 Stroud is not the only philosopher to have made these kinds of distinctions. Robert Stern, in particular,

provides a detailed taxonomy of transcendental arguments in his Transcendental Arguments and Scepticism

(2000) that is rich and interesting. He also distinguishes between strong and weak transcendental arguments, and

advocates for a more ‗modest‘ approach (see Stern 2007). I focus on Stroud for the influential role his writings

have taken in framing the debate, and because his account sets up what I take to be the main criticism strong

transcendental arguments face, which I will respond to in chapter four.

Page 62: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

62

heartily agree with the claim [that we cannot do otherwise than to find some of our beliefs

true] and say that that just brings out our pitiful, irrational plight‘. If anything, the success of

Stroudian weak transcendental arguments heightens the worry.

Strawson could respond to Burge on this front by questioning whether the sceptic has

thereby shown our plight to be irrational; although we may be wrong, that does not mean that

we cannot have good reason to believe. The role of transcendental arguments under his

picture, then, could be to show us why our beliefs are still reasonable.

This is not accessible to Stroud. As we have seen, Stroud wants something stronger

than that with which Strawson is prepared to settle. He wants invulnerability. This suggests

that Stroud feels that there is something about sceptical arguments that requires a more

substantial response; some kind of ‗ruling out‘, even if it does not require direct proof of the

falsity of sceptical scenarios. Hence, I think we can say that motivation for employing

Stroudian weak transcendental arguments evaporates: they are at best ineffectual, and at worst,

somewhat disturbing.

2.8.2 Strawsonian Weak Transcendental Arguments

The question then becomes one of whether Strawsonian weak transcendental arguments could

satisfy our sceptic. I hope it is clear that they could not. Strawson‘s argument is that key

claims hang together well to form a coherent point of view. Perhaps a system of beliefs in

which the belief that the extra-mental exists hangs together well with beliefs about induction

and other beliefs appropriate for our point of view on the world, but the sceptic‘s worry is that

so could other systems for which these beliefs are fundamentally false. Stawson claims that

although there may be some changes to the point of view, it will remain a fundamentally

human point of view (Strawson 1985: 26–7), but he offers no reason to suppose that this is the

only possible human point of view. Admittedly, it seems massively prevalent. However, given

that we can and (at least some of us) do question this point of view, it seems that a human

point of view should account for this human questioning, and provide some answer as to why

human beings should stop their questioning. This is what the sceptic I have identified

demands, and Strawsonian weak transcendental arguments cannot answer her. Strawson holds

that the sceptic‘s questions are idle because it is a natural fact that we cannot sustain her doubt,

but it is an equally natural fact that, even if not constantly, many of us do still entertain these

Page 63: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

63

doubts, and have done throughout history. If the reasonableness of belief in that which the

sceptic doubts stems from its hanging together as a part of a natural, human point of view, it

must be equally reasonable to entertain these doubts from time to time, unless we invoke

something stronger than this natural fact, as with Stroud‘s argument that we must believe some

things even it is does not follow from this that those things are true. In which case we are right

back in the disturbing situation described by Burge.

2.9 Conclusion

In this chapter I have examined the nature of transcendental arguments from their origins in

Kant, through their development into strong and weak transcendental arguments during the

twentieth and twenty-first century. I have argued that what is useful against the sceptic in

transcendental arguments is that they start from a premise concerning thought or experience,

which the sceptic does not doubt, and they move to show that something must be the case

because it is a necessary condition of thought or experience. Although I argue that

transcendental arguments are not necessarily anti-sceptical, they have a clear application if it

can be shown that something the sceptic doubts is a necessary condition of thought or

experience.

I have furthermore argued that strong transcendental arguments are to be preferred in

offering a robust response to the sceptic who concerns me, as weak transcendental arguments

have been shown to be either ineffectual, or, if they did work, they would actually land us in a

situation even more worrying than the one the sceptic was originally concerned about.

Namely, that it might be impossible for us to believe the truth about the world if a sceptical

scenario does hold.

In the next two chapters I will go on to defend the plausibility of strong transcendental

arguments. In chapter three I will defend the principle that my sceptic must accept at least

some propositions concerning the mental to be certainly known. I will then go on in chapter

four to argue that Stroud‘s criticisms of strong transcendental arguments rest on the illicit

assumption of a metaphysical picture that is less plausible than the one that would need to be

true for a strong transcendental argument to be viable.

Page 64: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

64

Chapter 3: What’s So Special about the Mental?

3.1 Introduction

The power of a transcendental argument comes from that fact that its first premise is

something prized and undoubted by the sceptic. The hard labour of the strong transcendental

argument is to show that something the sceptic doubts is necessarily entailed by that which she

already accepts: the first premise, an undoubted mental proposition. Why should she cede this

much?

It may seem that even if a transcendental argument works, the sceptic can easily shift

her ground to the mental premise. She may say: ‗True, if you have experiences and thoughts of

the sort you describe, I may be forced to grant that only certain sorts of world could give rise

to such experiences and thoughts. However,‘ she will add, ‗I do not grant this. How do you

know that the content of your thoughts and experiences are just what you think they are?

What‘s so special about the mental?‘ The first task of this chapter, then, shall be to defend the

mental against sceptical attack.

I will examine a number of initially worrying doubts, and I will grant that some of

these are successful in their targets. However, I shall argue that although these cast doubt on

our confidence in our ability to know the nature and content of some of our thoughts and

experiences, they do not motivate doubt that there are such thoughts and experiences, and that

at least some broad features of our thoughts and experiences remain untouched by such

challenges. It may seem that this is not a very reassuring response—that the broad features of

at least some of our thoughts and experiences can be known and believed with confidence—

but the first premise of a strong transcendental argument need not, in itself, be substantial and

reassuring. It is only intended as a starting point, from which an STA can be given so as to

provide us with something stronger.

I shall then move on to provide a positive argument for the incorrigibility of my beliefs

about what I believe. I take care to distinguish this from Cartesian infallibility. The reasons

why I know what I believe with an assurance I do not have for my knowledge of the external

world are not connected to any assumptions about transparency of the mind in general or

Page 65: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

65

metaphysical claims entailing the mind is of a fundamentally different kind of stuff41

to other

things. Many philosophers have sought to tease apart privileged access from its Cartesian

heritage, and I will argue that there is no really compelling reason to suppose that the STA

theorist must be lumbered with all the faults of Cartesianism simply because she will need to

advocate a privileged access that bears surface similarities to the Cartesian spectre.

3.2 Doubting One’s Own Mind

The question of why the sceptic is not interested in casting doubt on first personal mental

propositions as well as non-psychological propositions has recently received attention in

response to research conducted in the field of psychology and neurobiology. Doubt has been

raised about our ability to know our own emotions, our assessment of our own visual

experiences, the phenomenology of thought, even our ability to recognise our own experiences

as belonging to us. Eric Schwitzgebel, in particular, has taken these doubts as providing

plentiful reason for supposing that introspection is in many areas ‗highly untrustworthy‘

(Schwitzgebel 2008: 246), as unreliable as perception, if not more so. If introspection should

prove as unreliable as perception it will not affect the possibility of some strong transcendental

argument succeeding (at least in so far as one might show some non-mental fact to be as

securely known as some mental fact) but it will certainly call into question the value of such

an exercise. Perhaps my sceptic has no interest in doubting her own mind, but if I cannot

demonstrate that she has some reason for prizing at least some mental propositions above non-

mental ones it will be wondered why anyone should be interested in this sceptic at all.

In this sections 3.3–3.7 I will examine the reasons for doubting the trustworthiness of

introspection. I will agree that in some cases we have reason to be less certain about what

introspection can deliver to us. However, I do not accept the extent of the untrustworthiness

Schwitzgebel ascribes, and I shall argue that we are not given sufficient reason to doubt

41 I use the term ‗stuff‘ so as not to limit this objection to talk of different ‗substances‘, definition of which may

be controversial. The term should be taken to include any kind of ontological categorisation that would define

objects of different types so fundamentally distinct that one could not reason from propositions about one to

propositions about another.

Page 66: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

66

introspection where it counts: i.e. where it is needed for the construction of a strong

transcendental argument.

I shall start by accepting Schwitzgebel‘s broad definition of ‗introspection‘ as ‗a

species of attention to currently ongoing conscious experience‘, and ‗the primary method by

which we normally reach judgments about our experience‘ (Schwitzgebel 2008: 248)42

. As

will be seen later in the chapter, I will need to be much more specific as to the sort of

introspection I wish to defend. However, this broad definition will do for the purposes of

assessing criticisms of the kind that are intended to make us doubt introspection as a whole.

3.3 Emotion

Schwitzgebel‘s begins his argument against our knowledge of our own emotions by launching

a barrage of questions:

Are emotional states like joy, anger, and fear always felt phenomenally—that is, as

part of one‘s stream of conscious experience—or only sometimes? Is their

phenomenology, their experiential character, always more or less the same, or does it

differ widely from case to case? For example, is joy sometimes in the head, sometimes

more visceral, sometimes a thrill, sometimes an expansiveness—or, instead, does joy

have a single, consistent core, a distinctive, identifiable, unique experiential character?

Is emotional consciousness simply the experience of one‘s bodily arousal, and other

bodily states, as William James (1981 [1890]) seems to suggest? Or, as most people

think, can it include, or even be exhausted by, something less literally visceral? Is

emotional experience consistently located in space (for example, particular places in

the interior of one‘s head and body)? Can it have color—for instance, do we

sometimes literally ‗see red‘ as part of being angry? Does it typically come and pass in

a few moments (as Buddhists sometimes suggest), or does it tend to last awhile (as my

English-speaking friends more commonly say)? (Schwitzgebel 2008: 249)

He anticipates that we will not be able to give answers to all these questions with equal speed

and ease—‗one-two-three‘. It is tempting to suppose that some of his assumption of difficulty

42 This seems broadly in line with definitions of introspection given by other authors; for instance, Bayne and

Spencer (2010: 1) write: ‗In this paper we use ‗introspection‘ and its cognates solely to refer to a mode of first-

personal access to one‘s current (or immediately prior) conscious states, episodes or processes, and we leave to

one side uses of the term that apply to non-occurrent and non-conscious mental states (background motivations,

dispositional states, etc)‘.

Page 67: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

67

rests with the fact that the answer to many of these questions (the first one, for instance) was

‗sometimes‘ or, ‗in some cases‘, and any initial hesitancy arises from the fact that although

there are clear answers to be had, the questions need to be refined. However, when it comes to

‗Is emotional experience consistently located in space (for example, particular places in the

interior of one‘s head and body)?‘ I find myself unsure. As a physicalist, I am confident that it

occurs in space, but do I always feel it as specifically spatially located? What about the states,

such as unconscious anger, that I want to confidently assert do not always have a phenomenal

feel? Perhaps that should be my answer, then: if I do not feel it consciously at all, I cannot feel

it as specifically in a certain place. Yet, what about those emotions I am sure are conscious. I

am pretty sure that I think of them as being located in space—joy is in my head, my chest; fear

is in my stomach—but is the trembling of my fingers a part of how my nervousness feels, or a

mere consequence of it? I am not sure, and I must concede that the answer does not come to

me instantly ‗one-two-three‘, and it is not just because so many questions have been fired at

me at once.

Schwitzgebel (2008: 250) is quick to say that it is not simply that language fails us.

The question is whether the trembling of my fingers was really a part of the phenomenology of

my nervousness at the time when I was nervous. It is not so much concerned with whether I

should class the trembling of my fingers as a part of what it was for me to be nervous as

whether I felt the trembling as a part of my nervousness. And that is a question to which I do

not feel confident that I could give a swift and sure answer.

3.3.1 Anticipated and Remembered Emotion

Schwitzgebel also calls us to consider the things in life that we really get pleasure or suffering

out of (ibid.), and how often we misjudge these. He asks the reader whether she really enjoys

Christmas. It is important to distinguish two questions so as to prevent a misleading answer. I

am sure many people put on a show of enjoying Christmas when they do not, and many people

complain of how Christmas is really a miserable season—that there are more suicides at that

Page 68: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

68

time of year than any other43

, and so forth. However, these would not seem to be examples of

people who do not know whether they enjoy Christmas or not; these are examples of people

who note a discontinuity between actual enjoyment felt and expectation, hopes, or conventions

concerning what we are meant to enjoy. Similarly, I often find that I do not mind doing the

dishes as much as I thought I would, but that does not mean that I do not know that I do not

mind it when I am actually doing it. It means that I misremembered or overestimated how

bothersome it would actually be when I was not doing it.

3.3.2 Linguistic Vagueness

Schwitzgebel also asks whether one might not be happier weeding than at a restaurant with

friends. Again, I think this confuses the issue between conventionally pleasurable activities

and awareness of actual pleasure felt. Many introverts feel that they ought to enjoy dinner out

with friends more than they do, but this does not mean that they are not aware of how they

actually feel when they are out with friends. Also, although I can report that working in my

allotment is calming or makes me feel better, I am not entirely sure whether it would be

correct to categorise my feelings when I am there as ‗happy‘, or ‗pleasurable‘. Certainly, it is

not the same experience as that which I have when laughing at a good friend‘s joke. This is

more of a linguistic issue about the vagueness of such concepts. Many things that count as

‗happy‘ can be quite different to each other. If I find myself uncertain whether one experience

is more enjoyable than another, might not the problem be that I am comparing degrees of

‗happiness‘ where the ‗happiness‘ in question is in fact two quite different emotions? If I am

40% Happy-A when out with my friends and 80% Happy-B when weeding, does it make

sense to say that I am twice as ‗Happy‘ when I am weeding? Surely not. Say that Happy-A is

‗having fun‘ and Happy-B is ‗contentment‘ or ‗satisfaction‘. We may think of all of these

things as in some sense ‗happy‘, but I feel satisfied by doing many things that are not exactly

‗fun‘. Weeding would seem to be an obvious example.

43 In fact, there is evidence to suggest that there are fewer suicides around Christmas, but the popular belief at

least suggests that many people feel that it is not the happiest time of the year. See Sparhawk (1987) and Phillips

and Wills (1987).

Page 69: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

69

3.3.3 Distinguishing Moods and Emotions

In addition to a failure to distinguish different types of happiness, philosophers who employ

counter-examples that challenge our self-reports of happiness often ignore that one may have

more than one emotion at once. Thus, Haybron‘s 2007 paper repeatedly uses evidence that a

person was stressed or depressed to counter self-reports of happiness as a part of his argument

for ‗affective ignorance‘—or ignorance of one‘s own emotions.

Some of this relies on a rather slanted interpretation of a fictional man, Glen, who

insists that he is happy whilst living a stressful city life, but upon visiting a friend in the

country realises from his sense of relief (or ‗decompression‘) than he had been unhappy, ‗not

because he didn‘t understand what happiness is, but simply because he was oblivious to the

character of his emotional condition‘ (Haybron 2007: 395). This last is a characterisation of

Glen‘s experience that Haybron surely cannot simply write into the example. It begs the

question of how we are to understand Glen‘s experience. Haybron returns to this example

surprisingly often, considering that it is an entirely fictional account and thus represents

empirical evidence of nothing but Haybron‘s preconceived ideas. The entire section, ‗Can We

Tell Pleasure from Pain?‘ (Haybron 2007: 405–6) relies on demonstrating how supposing that

we struggle to tell pleasure from pain provides an explanation from Glen‘s faulty reporting,

but the story itself is not enough to suggest real people report falsely in the way that Glen

does.

In supporting his thesis that affective ignorance is extensive, Haybron (2007: 409–10)

relies on surveys that over-emphasise a binary view of emotion, such as Andrews and Withey

(1976), which purports to show only 3% of people reporting negative well-being when asked

to pick from a scale of smiley faces how they would rate themselves. Haybron takes this as

evidence of poor self-reporting on the basis that the incidence of depression and similar mood

disorders is much greater than that. However, there has long been a call for more multifaceted

assessments of subjective well-being, as advocated for by Ed Diener (1994). Moreover,

Haybron appeals to symptoms of depression or anxiety as signs that a person‘s self-reports of

being happy are false, but, as Beck and Alford (2009: 8) write, ‗depression is a complex

pattern of deviations in feelings‘ consisting of a ‗cluster of signs and symptoms‘. It is not

defined as feeling sad all the time or never feeling happy.

Page 70: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

70

Reporting that one feels happy is not necessarily wrong simply because one also has

symptoms of depression or anxiety. Well-being, depression, and anxiety are complex

experiences that cannot simply be contrasted to being sad-right-now or happy-right-now.

Moreover, Haybron himself notes a difference between our reliability concerning focused

states with a ‗more or less specific object or (phenomenological) location‘ and ‗moods‘, which

‗have no particular location or object‘. In this sense, he distinguishes moods from ‗emotions‘,

which he holds to be more object-focused and intense, but, supposing this is correct, he fails to

acknowledge that this difference could mean that moods and emotions which he treats as

binary opposites could co-exist. The depressed person whose serotonin deficiency creates a

general low mood, low energy, an inability to act on desires, etc., nevertheless feels joy when

laughing at a friend‘s joke, watching a favourite movie, and so on for other, specific, object

focused events. It is for this reason that the widely-used PHQ-9 (for depression) and GAD-7

(for General Anxiety Disorders) employed by mental health professionals in primary care ask

patients to assess their mood over a week or two weeks at the start of a session, rather than

asking the patient how they feel at that specific moment (see Robert L. Spitzer, Janet B. W.

Williams, Kurt Kroenke, and colleagues, 2010a and 2010b). At times, Haybron seems to

recognise this, noting towards the end ‗mood is not a singular entity like that‘ (2007: 414); it is

puzzling that he does not seem to take this into consideration elsewhere—for instance where

those with higher coronary activity are labelled ‗distress deniers‘ (2007: 411), as opposed to

people whose mood is not a singular entity.

Perhaps our self-reporting of moods is unreliable because it is vaguer and can be

misunderstood because of presently felt emotions. Perhaps we are not perfect at assessing how

we have felt in the past and how we are likely to feel in the future. This says nothing of

presently felt emotions.

3.3.4 Presently Felt Emotions

Schwitzgebel invites one to consider one‘s current experience in reading his article, and

unleashes another barrage of questions:

Is it completely obvious to you what the character of that experience is? Does

introspection reveal it to you as clearly as visual observation reveals the presence of

the text before your eyes? Can you discern its gross and fine features through

Page 71: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

71

introspection as easily and confidently as you can, through vision, discern the gross

and fine features of nearby external objects? Can you trace its spatiality (or

nonspatiality), its viscerality or cognitiveness, its involvement with conscious imagery,

thought, proprioception, or whatever, as sharply and infallibly as you can discern the

shape, texture, and color of your desk? (Schwitzgebel 2008: 251)

Again, I feel matters of language confuse this. I am not sure, upon reflecting on my present

experience of reading his paper, or writing my thesis, what exactly it is that I am feeling, but I

feel fairly sure that it is more that I do not have a name for it, than that I am unclear as to what

I am feeling.

To avoid this issue, Schwitzgebel invites the reader to contemplate some event that

provokes a strong emotion, and this is easily done. I remember some event from my past that

‗riles‘ me up (ibid.). I firmly report that I feel bitter, sad, angry. I turn to contemplate

Schwitzgebel‘s question: ‗Can you discern its gross and fine features through introspection as

easily and confidently as you can, through vision, discern the gross and fine features of nearby

external objects?‘, and I must confess that I cannot. However, I am equally sure that this is

because I do not quite know what Switzgabel means by ‗gross and fine features‘ in the way

that I discern the gross and fine features of the table. I never expected my emotions to bounded

or clearly demarked in the way that the table is bounded and clearly demarked—at least from

the perspective of my meagre human vision. I know that from a finer perspective I would find

it harder to delimit where the table ended and the air began. I am not sure in what sense my

sensory apparatus are proving more reliable in reporting the gross and fine features of the table

than my introspection is in reporting mental objects, except in so much as that the table itself

is less vaguely delimited than my emotions. There is also an uneasiness in the comparison, as

it seems to me that better sensory apparatus reveals the vagueness of the table‘s physical

boundary, whereas no improvement on my introspective capabilities could make the concept

of calmness or happiness less vague.

Schwitzgebel may have a point in noting the disagreements in the literature on the

experiential character of emotion, ‗disputes which at least seem to be about the emotional

phenomenology itself‘(ibid.). I could perhaps insist that this is a mistake of reporting. I have

never been convinced by arguments that start from noticing a divergence of opinions and go

on to conclude from this that there is no fact of the matter—no one opinion that is true.

Page 72: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

72

However, it is certainly evidence in favour of a lack of introspective clarity that my

conclusions have not been easily reached by others.

The most convincing argument against the introspective clarity of emotions, however,

is a familiar one from psychoanalysis:

My wife mentions that I seem to be angry about being stuck with the dishes again

(despite the fact that doing the dishes makes me happy?). I deny it… But I‘m wrong, of

course, as I usually am in such situations: My wife reads my face better than I

introspect‘ (Schwitzgebel 2008: 252)

This argument is convincing. Who has not at some point come to discover that whilst they

thought they were fine, they really were not? One may be brought to see, either by an outsider,

or upon later reflection, that, actually, one has been impatient, or raised one‘s voice, or been

overly forceful in setting down an object, and these are signs that, in actuality, one is angry

about something, or at least angrier than one thought one was. Schwitzgebel (ibid.) concedes

that anger is not an ideal example, as it necessarily involves less favourable conditions for

reflection than quiet contemplation. However, if one is not aware that one is angry, one may

not realise that one is in less than favourable conditions in which to assess one‘s own

reflective capabilities.

Nevertheless, it is worth noting that this point only brings into question emotions or

moods that I am not aware that I have, not strong, object-focused, well-defined, presently felt

emotions. Arguably, paradigmatic cases are to be found—agony and ecstacy—that we may

know ourselves to be experiencing even if our general mood is vague and difficult to define.

For the majority of emotions and moods, I cede that I am not an infallible judge of my

emotional experiences. However, I do not think there are many strong transcendental

arguments (if any) that start from a proposition concerning these kinds of experience.

Furthermore, I suspect that this is at least partially due to the fact that we are generally much

less inclined to place emotional experience under the list of things about which we hold

ourselves peculiarly sure. A great deal of literature (e.g. Pride and Prejudice, or Gone With

the Wind), has been written centring around the fact that people often do not realise what their

‗true‘ feelings are for quite some time. This suggests that our ability to read our own emotions

with confidence is not actually all that commonly assumed.

Page 73: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

73

3.4 Visual Experience

A much more worrisome challenge is that which Schwitzgebel levels against our visual

claims. Take some familiar claim, such as that I am having a visual experience of redness.

Schwitzgebel (2008: 253) is willing to grant that is ‗hard to go wrong‘ about such simple

visual cases as a patch of bright red, revealed to the ‗inward glance‘. However, he maintains

that it is equally ‗hard to go wrong‘ about much of external perception. He notes a traditional

assumption that sceptical hypotheses (such as that I might be dreaming, or that I might be a

brain-in-a-vat (BIV)) do not undermine our judgements about our visual phenomenology. He

challenges this assumption, noting that our judgements are often incoherent in dreams, and

giving several examples to back up this point.

Over the next few sections I shall examine his examples, first from the point of view of

what they might mean for a dreamer, and then from the point of view of whether they could be

‗massaged‘ by neurosurgeons into the beliefs of a BIV. I argue that Schwitzgebel is confusing

introspection with judgements about introspection, a point that emerges when one presses for

clarity as to what exactly he is supposing in his examples. I think there is some sliding here

between talk of introspection and judgements based on introspection, which is muddying the

discussion. These are his examples:

Example 1: ‗I think I can protrude my tongue without its coming out‘

Example 2: ‗I think I see a red carpet that‘s not red‘

Example 3: ‗I see a seal as my sister‘

(See Schwitzgebel 2008: 258)

3.4.1 ‘I think I can protrude my tongue without its coming out’

Example 1, ‗I think I can protrude my tongue without its coming out‘, is an incoherent

judgement, but it is not clear exactly what this is supposed to show. The example is under-

described, and there are a number of ways one might seek to clarify what is happening here,

but it is not obvious that they would cast doubt on one‘s judgement.

The dreamer can be understood as making a linguistic mistake. Schwitzgebel mentions

that such examples can seem quite insightful, and one way that might come to pass is this: I

fancy I have come to understand some hidden way in which protruding my tongue could

involve keeping it in my mouth. In this case, the incoherence lies in the dreamer either failing

Page 74: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

74

to notice, or to remember, the meaning of the word ‗protrude‘. To protrude is simply for

something to stick out. I have failed to maintain an understanding of what it is for something

to ‗protrude‘ in English, so my statement is incoherent in English. The incoherence in terms of

judgement, however, is illusory. What I have really done is to amend my understanding of

what the word ‗protrude‘ means to include not only those things that stick out, but also those

things which do not. Perhaps it seems profound because some part of my mind is aware of the

English meaning, and knows that it would be impossible for this sentence to be true in

English. In my dream language, though, it is fine. My judgement that I have thought

something profound is flawed, but then, I do not think that anyone supposed that judging one‘s

thoughts to be profound was an example of introspection. Rather, it is a case of comparing

one‘s thoughts to some objective (or, at least, intersubjective) standard of significance.

This is but one way to understand what might be going on in the example. Perhaps

Schwitzgebel has in mind a case where the dreamer believes that they have discovered some

secret working of the universe that allows protrusion without physical emergence—perhaps

my tongue is protruding in some other dimension. However, it seems to me that this would be

nothing more than a slightly more elaborate version of the familiar mistakes one makes about

the structure and organisation of the non-mental world whilst dreaming. It is not a mistaken

judgement about the content of one‘s thoughts or experience based upon introspection; it is a

mistake about the nature of that which causes those thoughts and experiences. I would be

mistaken about my dream-experience, whatever that might be, being caused by my tongue

protruding into ‗other dimensions‘, but would not be mistaken about the experience I was

having.

3.4.2 ‘I see a seal as my sister’

The third example is not dissimilar, and I would argue it is even less convincing. When I see

my sister as a seal there is nothing wrong with the introspective element of my judgement. I

am having an experience as of a seal being before me, and I think that my sister is that seal.

The use of ‗see‘ is misleading, because it can refer to both my visual experience and to how I

understand something—how I ‗see‘ it. I am not incorrect about my visual experience as of a

seal. I am incorrect in my understanding, because I believe that my sister is a seal. However, I

am not incorrect in my introspection of what my understanding of the situation is. Again, the

Page 75: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

75

introspective element of my judgement is not at fault. I know that I believe my sister to be a

seal in the dream.

One might seek to make a more subtle point about beliefs here. If a belief is a

disposition to assent to certain propositions, then I am wrong that in my waking life I am

generally disposed to assent to the proposition that my sister is a seal. However, this does not

undermine my correct assessment that at that time, in that dream, I am disposed to assent to

the proposition that my sister is a seal44

. I can introspect on this and deliver the correct

assessment of my current disposition, even if I am unable to introspect and discover that in

general this is not my disposition, that in the past it was not my disposition, and that in the

future it is unlikely to be my disposition again. However, this is merely a manifestation of the

fact that in dreams we believe many things to be true that we know to be false upon waking; it

does not relate to our ability to assess correctly what our present beliefs actually are.

Furthermore, even if it did, it must be conceded that this example has strayed far from

what Schwitzgebel was aiming at as regards introspection of visual presentations of bright

primary colours. Our beliefs about seals and sisters are far more complicated and prone to

error. I might form a belief about seals being fish because they swim in the sea, or that my

sister is a Buddhist, and be wrong in a perfectly ordinary way that implies nothing about

introspection. That one can make poor judgements of this kind about the nature of creatures

outside of oneself in dreams does not affect one‘s ability to introspect correctly about the

content of one‘s experience.

3.4.3 ‘I think I see a red carpet that’s not red’

What of the second example, then? ‗I think I see a red carpet that‘s not red.‘ It certainly seems

more to the point as regards casting doubt on our visual experience, and it also sounds like the

sort of case that would cause profound doubt about the accuracy of our judgements about the

colours we experience. However, its phrasing leaves much room for ambiguity. In this section

44 There are those who argue that it is not possible to have beliefs in dreams, but I do not think they will have

much interest in this discussion. If the sceptic thinks I might be dreaming and therefore have incorrect beliefs, she

is clearly not of this point of view.

Page 76: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

76

I will argue that, as with the other examples, it is from this ambiguity that the worry arises, not

the possibilities that might actually be being expressed by this example.

We can understand the quoted sentence as:

(A) a judgement that you are having a red phenomenology that has been caused by a

carpet that is not red

(B) a judgement that you are seeing a red carpet that does not present a red

phenomenology

(C) a judgement that you are seeing a carpet that is both red and not red

(D) you are actually having a red phenomenology that is not red

A and B are judgements, and involve at least an apparent mistake, but are not incoherent. C is

an incoherent judgement, but is more akin to the tongue protruding case, and I shall argue that

it does not motivate the doubt Schwitzgebel is aiming at. D is incoherent, but I would argue

that this means nothing as regards our dreaming judgements, as it is not a judgement. Its

incoherence lies in the fact that it is impossible.

In A, what is going on is that the dreamer is having a red phenomenology that they

judge has been caused by a carpet that is not red. The dreamer may do this for many reasons:

because she believes she is subject to an illusion, because she believes the lighting is poor, and

so forth—all the reasons why she might doubt a genuine sensory experience, along with a few

others such as that she believes an evil witch has swopped out her eyes for magic ones that

deliver false reports about the world. In none of these cases, though, is her introspection

faulty. She judges that she is having a red phenomenology, and she is correct. She believes

that it was caused by a carpet that is not actually red, but that is irrelevant to the quality of her

judgement about her introspected experience.

B is simply the flip side of A. You judge that the carpet you ‗see‘ is actually red, even

though your phenomenal experience is not red. In other words, you believe that you are

subject to an illusion or a witch‘s prank, and although the carpet appears blue to you, you

think your experience was caused by an object that was actually red. You are not wrong about

your introspective experience of blueness.

C is more worrying. Something cannot be both P and not-P, and if I am judging that

something is both red and not red I would appear to be judging contrary to the laws of logic.

This could be akin to the tongue example, in that I might be mistaking what the laws of the

universe allow. I judge that I am having a phenomenology as of that which would be caused

Page 77: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

77

by a red carpet, yet somehow that phenomenology is also not red. This would again seem to

me to be a mistake about the laws of the wider universe, not of introspection. I grant that it

does not bode well for our powers of reasoning when asleep if we make judgements that

contradict the laws of logic, but it does not indicate that we are wrong about our

phenomenology. I do not see how, even in a dream, we could understand a person to be seeing

something that is both red and not red, unless we are either saying that they really do have a

phenomenology that is both red and not red, or they have a phenomenology that is red, and

they believe that one can (and they do) have a red phenomenology that is also not red45

.

The first seems to me to be an obvious impossibility, and, if it is not, then the person is

not wrong—it would have to be the case that somehow, when asleep, we could have

phenomenologies that are impossible to us when awake. In the second, it is as with the

protruding tongue: they are not wrong about the phenomenology, they just also think that it is

possible to have a red phenomenology that is also not red. The phenomenology they would in

fact have would still be of red, they just somehow believe that the meaning of ‗red

phenomenology‘ or ‗red experience‘ can include phenomenologies that are not red, even not-

red-at-the-same-time-as-presenting-as-red. Introspection is not delivering to us a

phenomenology of both-red-and-not-red—it could not—but we may judge that it is because

we are understanding the meaning of ‗phenomenology‘ somewhat differently in the dream.

This may not be obvious. It may seem that I am simply insisting that one cannot make

a mistaken judgement about the content of one‘s experience concerning bright red colours. In

a sense this is true, it seems to me that I cannot really distinguish between my experiencing a

red phenomenology and believing that I see red. However, I do not think it counts as a

judgement, as there is no inference. To see red is simply to believe that I see red.

There is a secondary linguistic point, which I believe both supports this, and survives

even if one is not convinced of it, which is this: it is not clear how I can be making a

judgement that the content of my experience is ‗red‘ unless ‗red‘ is bound to a distinctive

phenomenology. Furthermore, if the dream me is judging that she is experiencing something

as red that is not an experience of red and using ‗red‘ in such a way that is not tied to a

45 Or the corollary: they have a phenomenology that is not red, but they believe that one can (and they do) have a

not red phenomenology that is also red

Page 78: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

78

particular phenomenology, then we revert back to the more basic linguistic point that she has

ceased to use the word ‗red‘ in the manner we commonly do in English.

Following on from this discussion, it should be obvious that I concede D‘s

incoherence. I am sure, though, that this is not what Schwitzgebel meant by ‗I think I see a red

carpet that‘s not red‘. He is seeking to undermine judgements made on the basis of

introspection, rather than suggesting that we actually have impossible phenomenologies in

dreams. However, I think it is the obvious incoherence of this from which the suggestion that

‗I think I see a red carpet that‘s not red‘ gains its power to undermine our introspective

judgements about visual experience. It would be impossible for introspection to deliver an

awareness of both red and not red, yet this says nothing about any judgement that could be

meant by ‗I think I see a red carpet that‘s not red‘.

3.4.4 Introspection, Introspective Judgements, and Neurosurgeons from

Alpha Centauri

If what I say above is correct, it is not the deliveries of introspection that generate incoherent

beliefs about dreams. It is not about the phenomenology that we are wrong. I think the

confusion here stems from a slide in Schwitzgebel from talking about introspection as ‗a

species of attention to currently ongoing conscious experience‘ or ‗the primary method by

which we normally reach judgments about our experience‘(Schwitzgebel 2008: 248), to

talking about ‗introspective judgements‘. These are judgements that contain an introspective

element, but, if what I have said above is correct, it is not solely on the basis of introspection

that the judgement is formed, and it is not the introspective element that has gone wrong.

One might suppose that the dreaming example is misleading. Whatever else they may

be, dreams are natural occurrences, and maybe elements of the way in which we form

introspective judgements are left untouched by dreams that could be overwhelmed by artificial

interference. Schwitzgebel (2008: 253) also considers the possibility that ‗neurosurgeons from

Alpha Centauri [might] message and stroke our brains‘ to create the judgement that something

is red when it is not.

I think the analysis will go down the same. The reason for this is, as suggested above,

that the phenomenology and awareness of basic things, such as bright colours, do not come

apart. To have the phenomenology of red is to be aware of redness (at least when one is

Page 79: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

79

attending to the redness, as Schwitzgebel suggests we are in introspection). It seems to me that

what is different about introspection is perhaps what makes it different from straightforward

judgement. To be aware of redness is just to believe that one is experiencing redness. It is non-

inferential, and, in that sense, is not a judgement in the straightforward sense of being

something that one judges to be true based on evidence. There is evidence of the experience of

red, and it is as a result of that evidence that one forms the belief that one is experiencing red,

but it is not judged in a way such that the poor reasoning of dreams or the messaging of

neurosurgeons could interfere with it. The neurosurgeons can cause me to report that I am

having an experience of red when I am not, but to make me believe that it is red, they will

either have to change what I take the meaning of ‗red‘ to be; or they will have to give me a

phenomenology that is different to what should be given by what I am looking at; or they will

have to make me believe that I have discovered some hitherto unknown aspect of the way the

world is, such that in some unfathomable different aspect, red and (for example) blue can be

the same, but this would be a linguistic mistake or a mistake about the world, not about my

phenomenology.

Schwitzgebel also suggests that the neuroscientists might ‗suppress‘ the

phenomenology, whilst creating the judgement. He states that supposing that this is possible

does not require that the phenomenology and the judgement be distinct existences, merely that

the one is possible without the other. It is puzzling, then, in what sense they are not distinct, if

they can exist without one another. This term ‗suppressing‘ seems to be key, but needs

fleshing out. It sounds more as though the suggestion is that the judgement could be

‗messaged‘ into us, and yet the alien neurosurgeons would block the phenomenology that

would usually accompany anything that would cause that judgement. This does not undermine

introspection directly—indeed, in this case, I might introspect (assuming I am not being forced

to say what I do not believe) and report that I had no red phenomenology, yet firmly believe

that I was seeing red. Yet it seems to me that if phenomenology and belief are not distinct

existences, if, as I say above, to be aware of one‘s phenomenology is to have beliefs about it,

one could not create the belief that I have a red phenomenology right now, if the

phenomenology were suppressed. One would be aware of what phenomenology one did or did

not have, and thus one would have beliefs about that. This example alone is not enough to

drive a wedge between experiencing red phenomenology and believing that one does.

Page 80: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

80

3.4.5 Blindsight

An important point should be made to distinguish these issues from what is known as

‗blindsight‘46

, whereby a person reports the absence of the phenomenology of something, yet

they behave in other ways that suggest that in some sense they really do see the object.

Perhaps some case of blindsight could arise wherein the sufferer reports that they do not see a

red carpet as distinctly coloured, or claim that they could not say what colour the carpet is, yet

they also deliver some suitable answer to a question as to whether my clothes match the

carpet. This would be a case of blindsight, but it does not seem to me that it would be

blindsight about introspection. My retina may be responding as normal to redness, and

affecting that part of my brain that identifies what matches what (let us suppose), and the

aliens may be suppressing my phenomenology of redness. In this case, though, I am right that

I have no phenomenology of redness. It is just that it so happens that some other part of my

brain is able to continue to operate coherently and produce red-appropriate behaviours that can

be exhibited in the absence of red phenomenology. Blindsight is revealing as to how

phenomenology can come apart from other brain operations that rely on perception, but it does

not tell us anything about the reliability of introspection in reporting phenomenology.

For these reasons, I do not think Schwitzgebel is right to suggest that the sceptical

hypotheses of dreaming and brain massaging provide us with reason to doubt our introspection

of our experiences concerning bright colours. I concede that reasoning may well go wrong in

dreams, and that this may be for a whole variety of reasons, but they are not reasons that relate

to our ability to tell accurately what the phenomenal contents of our experiences in these cases

are.

3.5 Peripheral and Foveal Vision

I now turn to the issue of clarity in our visual phenomenology in general. Various examples

purport to show that we do not have as clear a presentation of our visual phenomenology as

we generally take ourselves to have. Dennett (1991: 53–4) gives an example wherein one

takes a playing card, holds it out to the periphery of one‘s vision, and then slowly moves it

46 For a detailed account of blindsight, see Weiskrantz (1986).

Page 81: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

81

around towards the centre. He suggests the reader will be surprised at how close to the centre

the card must be in order for us to distinguish its colour, suit, and value.

However, though it may be unexpected to the individual, much of what we know about

how vision works should make this unsurprising. Our eyes saccade about an image or area of

attention, focusing on various spots and presenting a composite; we do not simply see a

detailed three dimensional picture of the world we inhabit. This results in other familiar

oddities, such as ‗change blindness‘47

, wherein we remain oblivious to changes if they occur

during an eye saccade, at places other than those at which our foveal attention is directed. It

should be of no real surprise to us that very little is as clear as we commonly take it to be

outside of points of foveal attention.

Although one‘s phenomenal experience may be formed piecemeal and patchwork, this

does not mean that the phenomenal experience is not of a (relatively) detailed three

dimensional visual field. We are blind to change because our mind is ‗filling in the gaps‘ with

previously accurate data to form a cohesive image. As I look at my screen now, it is clear to

me that the mouse mat on my right is red in colour, even if, in Dennett‘s experiment, I might

not be able to tell the colour of the card until it is within the area of my foveal attention.

Similarly, I can say the same for the bright red bottle-cap on my left—the result does not seem

to be simply a matter of size. Plausibly, then, I am not wrong in thinking that what is

introspectively present to me is a relatively rich three-dimensional image. It is just that this

image is a construct of my current perception and extrapolations from this and the recent past.

This is not to deny that the experience may be increasingly blurry towards the edges of

my vision, nor that, when called to consider the content of my current visual experience, I may

find that I am not nearly so sure about a great many things that I took myself to be sure of

before. When called to attend to the periphery of the visual field, the brain may seek new

information in preference to extrapolations from previous data and will thus replace the inner

impression of completeness with something much vaguer, based more strongly on visual

experience had right now. None of this is an indictment of my ability to correctly assess what

47 Dretske (2004: 3) notes that ‗change‘ blindness might more properly be termed ‗difference‘ blindness, as part

of the set-up of these examples often necessitate that we specifically do not see the change. If the change were

given to us as a part of the visual field, we would note it (not least because our eyes are drawn to movement).

However, he does also concede that we can fail to notice changes when they happen at the certain points during

the eye saccade.

Page 82: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

82

is introspectively available to me, or to form beliefs about the content of my introspected

experience.

When Schwitzgebel considers this example he seems to concede this point. For he

writes:

[I]t‘s one thing to mistake one‘s abilities and quite another to misconstrue

phenomenology. Our visual experience depends on the recent past, on general

knowledge, on what we hear, think, and infer, as well as on immediate visual input—or

so it‘s plausible to suppose. Background knowledge could thus fill in and sharpen our

experience beyond the narrow foveal center. (Schwitzgebel 2008: 255)

Yet he goes on to argue that when we prize apart foveation from introspective attention by

fixing our eyes on a spot and drawing our attention to something on the periphery, most

people confess that they have very little clarity beyond the centre of foveation. This, he claims,

demonstrates that ‗visual experience does not consist of a broad, stable field, flush with

precise detail, hazy only at the borders‘ (Schwitzgebel 2008: 256). He notes that ‗My

interlocutors—most of them—confess to error in having originally thought otherwise‘ (ibid.);

and based on this he concludes: ‗most naive introspectors are badly mistaken about their visual

phenomenology‘ (ibid.). However, this simply does not follow—Schwitzgebel has overstated

his case.

As I have argued above, we can grant that upon directing our attention in the manner

Schwitzgebel describes it becomes clear that one only has clarity for a few degrees out from

the centre of foveation. Equally, I am sure interlocutors may be easily brought to confess that,

assuming the experience of attending away from foveation delivers the same phenomenal

experience as naïve introspection, they were in error in their original assessment of their

introspective experience as rich, clear, and three-dimensional. However, it is not clear that we

must accept that their ordinary introspection, filled out with the memory and extrapolation

from previous eye saccades, delivers the same results as this artificially constrained case,

where it is perfectly reasonable to suppose that because you are trying to see what you can see

based only on the present sensory experience when the eye is completely still, the introspective

experience is different to the usual case. These are two very different cases, and one simply

cannot conclude that ‗most naive introspectors are badly mistaken about their visual

Page 83: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

83

phenomenology‘ when asking them to consider whether their normal visual phenomenology is

at all like this special case under very specific and unusual conditions.

Two doubts can be raised against this. Firstly: regardless of whether the conclusion is

correct, it is plausible that Schwitzgebel may have convinced his interlocutors that their

original introspective beliefs were wrong. If we can be so easily convinced that we are wrong

about the nature of our naïve introspection, then it may seem dubious to say that we were that

confident in the first place, and it would seem that we are still easily convinced of things that

are not true of the contents of our ever day introspection. Secondly, when one‘s target is a

sceptic, stating that ‗it is perfectly reasonable to suppose…‘ simply is not strong enough. The

sceptic doubts many things that we prima facie take to be ‗perfectly reasonable to suppose‘, so

why should she not reject my supposition that there is, in fact, a difference between ordinary,

‗rich‘ visual experience, and the visual experience one finds when one introspects having

deliberately divorced attention from foveation?

On this point I concede. However, I do not think it is a very large victory for the

sceptic. I do not think conceding that (outside the foveal centre) my visual experience is hazier

than I naïvely take it to be shows that I was ‗badly mistaken‘ about my visual phenomenology,

and, more importantly, I do not think it endangers anything any STA I can think of would be

likely to rely on. The clarity of my non-foveal vision does not seem to be of any great

significance. Moreover, that non-foveal vision becomes blurry when I hold my eye completely

still and attend away from foveation does not undercut the great deal of similarlities that

persist in what one took to be introspectively available before undertaking this exercise:

objects appear to be similarly located, or the same size and shape, and even of the same colour

(if one has seen then before—Dennett‘s example relies upon the presence of a novel object).

There is a great deal at quite a high level of complexity that remains unchallenged by these

cases.

3.6 The Phenomenology of Thought

A similar point can be made regarding Schwitzgebel‘s arguments concerning the

phenomenology of thought. He points out that there is widespread disagreement on whether

there is a distinctive phenomenology of thought separate from the imagery that accompanies

thought. Citing both the Chalmers and Hoy (2002) seminar for philosophers of mind at Santa

Page 84: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

84

Cruz, as well as disagreement in the literature, he notes that even those of us who have

reflected carefully on such things and engaged in research cannot come to an agreement about

something as basic as the intentionality of thought. However, I do think the way he puts the

case to us is misleading.

Schwitzgebel (2008: 258) asks: ‗the introspection of current conscious experience—

that‘s supposed to be easy, right?‘ Well… yes and no. Certainly, if we assume a Cartesian

ideal in which introspection of any aspect of conscious experience is supposed to be easy, then

yes, we are likely to fail on a number of issues. Failure of obscure aspects of our conscious

experience is cheap, however. As Schwitzgebel himself notes, it is hard to separate our

thoughts from accompanying imagery, so why would it be easy to extrapolate whether there is

a phenomenology distinctive to thought over and above any imagery that accompanies our

thoughts? Surely any phenomenology of thought would be quite subtle in comparison to the

rich and overlapping imageries that accompany thought; if it exists, we should not be surprised

if it were overpowered by these others.

This is no very significant point in the overall attempt to discredit introspection, and

having ‗a distinctive phenomenology of thought‘ is unlikely to be the kind of content an STA

is looking for to provide its mental premise.

3.7 The General Argument

In addition to questioning specific aspects of our introspective capacities, some philosophers

seek to form a gestalt argument from these instances, to a general sense of the unreliability of

introspection. Schwitzgebel concludes on the basis of the doubts he raises, that ‗The

introspection of current conscious experience, far from being secure, nearly infallible, is

faulty, untrustworthy, and misleading—not just possibly mistaken, but massively and

pervasively‘ (Schwitzgebel 2008: 259). I think this sets up a false dichotomy. We do not need

to demonstrate infallibility for all our introspective beliefs in order to show that we are not

massively and pervasively mistaken.

There are specific features of our conscious experience about which we take ourselves

to introspect regularly and accurately. There are other aspects of our conscious experience

about which only philosophers of mind commonly make much attempt to introspect, and for

which the deliveries of introspection are much less clear. I do not think it is surprising that

Page 85: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

85

these areas should prove less secure than the simpler, more common ones, and I do not think

our failures in these areas do anything to knock our confidence about the paradigm cases of

introspection.

I have shown that Schwitzgebel‘s arguments against the paradigmatic case of bright

foveal colour do not succeed, and his arguments against our knowledge of the phenomenology

of peripheral vision are weak. He also considers pain as a paradigmatic case of introspection,

and tries to throw doubt on this, by noting that we sometimes have trouble distinguishing mild

pains from itches, but this is unconvincing (see Schwitzgebel 2008: 259–60). Do I sometimes

have trouble explaining to my doctor exactly what it is that I am feeling (i.e. a pain, an itch, an

ache; whether it‘s a ‗3‘ or a ‗4‘ on a scale of 1–10)? Sure, of course, but this is a linguistic

issue. It is a question of whether I have correctly described what I am feeling, so that the

doctor will know how to treat me. That does not mean I do not know what it feels like. I know

exactly what it feels like, even if, because of the vagueness of the concepts of pains and itches,

I am unsure how to respond when my doctor asks me ‗Is it more of a pain, or an itch?‘

The arguments against the paradigmatic cases are thus weak. Moreover, even if I

remain unsure as to which experience, thought, or belief I am enjoying, no argument has been

presented that I am wrong about my having beliefs, thoughts, experiences in general. Indeed,

this generally seems to be the case. The content of my thought or experience is rarely deemed

as significant as that I have them at all. Or, at most, it is required that I have a certain sort of

content: that my thoughts concern objective particulars, perhaps (see Strawson 1987). I do not

think that Schwitzgebel‘s general argument from the failure of specific (and often the least

secure) elements of our conscious experience has the effect he desires on our general security

about naïve introspection. It certainly does not undermine the security needed by STAs about

certain minimal, paradigm cases.

The foregoing sections constitute a defence against attacks on our introspective

reliability. I now turn towards providing a positive argument for the claim that I do have just

those beliefs I believe myself to have.

3.8 Cartesian Infallibility vs Incorrigibility

Few philosophers these days would argue for the full complement of what might be termed

‗Cartesian infallibility‘—the exact definition of the Cartesian theory of mind varies slightly

Page 86: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

86

from account to account, and it is debatable which aspects of it could truly be to attributed to

Descartes, but for our purposes, I shall consider Cartesian infallibility to include at least these

two theses: that the mind is ‗transparent‘, in the sense that I have access to all my thoughts and

experiences; and that this access is such that I am able to know and correctly report on all my

thoughts and experiences.

The widespread acceptance of theories of unconscious and subconscious thought have

rendered Cartesian infallibility deeply implausible in most circles, but this alone does not

suggest that we have no special authority to make knowledge claims about our own thoughts

and experiences. Furthermore, as Stoneham notes in his 2004 paper ‗Self-Knowledge‘, even

Descartes conceded a more subtle form of fallibility that should not be neglected:

[M]any people do not know what they believe, since believing something and knowing

that one believes it are different acts of thinking, and the one often occurs without the

other. (Descartes, Discourse on Method iii (AT VI.23), quoted in Stoneham 2004: 659)

We can understand Descartes as meaning that there are likely many propositions that I believe

that I have never taken the trouble to reflect on and hence come to know that I believe. The

belief is merely the act of holding the proposition true, whilst knowing that one believes

something is a second order thought that has the belief as its subject.

So, we must add the concession that to have a belief does not automatically entail that

one knows that one has a belief. However, it does not follow from this concession that all

sense of authority concerning our own thoughts is lost. Stoneham (2004: 659), following

Williams (1978: Apendix 1) and Dennett (1978: 226), suggests that we consider

‗incorrigibility‘ instead. ‗Incorrigibility‘ can be defined as: necessarily, if you believe that you

have an attitude, A, to a proposition, p, then you do have that attitude to that proposition (BAp

→ Ap). This moves the debate away from the thorny issue of transparency—there is no

requirement that I know what all my thoughts and beliefs are at all times. The debate now

shifts to the more interesting question of whether, if I believe myself (B) to possess an attitude

(A) to a proposition (p) (for example, the attitude of holding p true) I could possibly be wrong

in my belief that I hold A to p.

The denial of the incorrigibility claim is ‗it‘s possible for me to believe that I have

attitude A to p, and not have attitude A to p‘:

Page 87: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

87

◊(BAp & ¬Ap)

This is the claim I must defend against.

3.9 The Argument for Incorrigibility

Tom Stoneham presents the following argument for incorrigibility.

The argument has two stages. The first starts from the Davidsonian premise that: one

cannot believe that anyone believes that p unless one also takes them to grasp the proposition

that p (and, indeed, one must grasp the proposition as well oneself, although in the first-person

case the point is the same). Second, anything that is a necessary conceptual precondition for

having a propositional attitude towards p will also be a condition upon believing that one has

that attitude towards p. Third, anything that is a consequence of believing that p will also be a

consequence of believing that one believes that p. It follows from this that any self-attribution

of belief has ‗at least all the consequences and commitments of the mental state attributed‘ (Stoneham, 2004: 663).

Stoneham does add a clarificatory comment on premise three to the effect that the

relevant consequences will be in the form of inferences and actions, and they will be

normative in nature. That is, if I believe that p, and I believe that p entails q, I should believe

that q as a consequence. However, I am not perfectly rational, and I may fail to do this.

Stoneham notes this fact, but points out that although some non-conformity must be allowed

for, we would surely admit that sufficient lack of conformity to the consequences of the state

in question would be taken as evidence that I was not actually in the state after all. This

argument does not require that I be perfectly rational, merely that, if I attribute a belief to

myself I must demonstrate at least the consequences of holding that belief that I would if I did

indeed hold the belief.

In support of premise three, Stoneham gives the following argument:

i. To be committed to believing that p is to think and act as if p were true

ii. So, if one believes that p one may infer anything that follows from p and act in any

way that would help achieve one‘s goals if p were true, and one may not infer anything

that is inconsistent with p

Page 88: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

88

It is interesting that Stoneham has shifted from talk of what one ‗ought‘ to do to talk of what

one ‗may‘ do. I presume this is to reflect the permissibility of not inferring all the propositions

that follow from p. He then goes on to argue:

iii. If one believed that one believed that p a rational believer would be equally prohibited

from inferring anything inconsistent with p or ‗acting in any way that will only achieve

her goals if not-p‘, and ‗similarly for all other constraints‘ (ibid.)

iv. So, if one believes that one believes that p, one is committed to think and act as if p

were true

I.e. one is committed to at least all the consequences of possessing the mental state.

The second stage of the argument is what Stoneham calls the ‗Containment Claim‘. This

assumes a ‗mild functionalism‘:

v. ‗If a thinker is in a state which meets all the conditions of conceptual grasp and

involvement or activation for believing that p, [nothing] more could be required for it

to be the case that she believes that p‘ (ibid.)

vi. Having a higher-order thought to the effect that ‗I believe that p‘ is just such a state

vii. Therefore, having the higher-order thought that ‗I believe that p‘ ‗involves or contains

the state of believing that p‘ (ibid.)—i.e. it entails that I do believe that p

So, this is good—this looks like it gets me what I want: necessarily, if I believe that I believe

that p, I believe that p. This is the Incorrigibility claim.

However, one might worry that there is a difference between believing that not-p and

not believing that p: A¬p and ¬Ap. Incorrigibility requires that I not only not have a

contradictory belief, I must also not lack any belief at all about p in those cases where I

believe that I believe that p. The difficulty with Stoneham‘s argument from this point of view

lies in premises two and three of the subsidiary argument for stage one, which read:

Page 89: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

89

ii. So, if one believes that p one may infer anything that follows from p and act in any

way that would help achieve one‘s goals if p were true, and one may not infer anything

that is inconsistent with p

iii. If one believed that one believed that p a rational believer would be equally prohibited

from inferring anything inconsistent with p or ‗acting in any way that will only achieve

her goals if not-p‘, and ‗similarly for all other constraints‘ (ibid.)

What if one were to act and infer in ways that were not inconsistent with p, but were also

consistent with having no opinion about p? One would not act as though one believed that not-

p or infer in ways that supposed the falsity of p. But premise ii only states that one may infer

anything that follows from p, not that one must. If one should fail to infer things that one ought

to if one really did believe that p this is presumably OK. Recall that I supposed that the change

from ‗should‘ to ‗may‘ here was perhaps in consequence of the clarification that was added to

the effect that it must be expected that we will sometimes fail to conform to the requirements

on thought and action, as we are not perfectly rational beings. From this point of view it may

have seemed that saying that we should always reason in line with the inferences we ought to

draw if we did believe that p was too restrictive. But switching to ‗may‘ seems too permissive.

Stoneham does also state that ‗talk of the commitments of specific beliefs does not commit

one to the thought that these commitments are specifiable in advance, that they are not

codifiable‘ (ibid.)—i.e. we should only speak in generalities—but I worry that this leaves too

much room for the sceptic.

Plausibly, a reply to this point might be made that although some failures to reason in

conformity with believing that p would be permissible, if I were completely indifferent to the

truth or falsity of p then overall I would generally not be reasoning in conformity with

believing that p, and would no longer be able to honestly assent to the higher-order thought

that I believe that p. But what if I so happen to never be in situations where my lack of belief

is revealed?

3.10 The Superstitious Man

Consider the following example: a man in 1762 might have heard that the Mayans predicted

the end of the world in 2012. He may be of a superstitious bent, loving to collect old sayings

Page 90: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

90

and mythology and claim them as beliefs, though he in actual fact believes very little of it, as

may be noted by the fact that he behaves in an ordinary fashion most of the time. Plausibly, he

will never have to engage in reasoning or actions based on the truth of a belief that the world

is ending in 250 years‘ time. The date is too far off to have any significance to his present

actions and thoughts. In truth, he neither believes, nor disbelieves it, but if you asked him

about it he would claim it as a belief and he might even reflect on it in his own mind,

wondering: ‗Do I really believe that the world will end in 2012?‘ and mentally responding:

‗Oh yes, of course I do!‘ with no thought of the consequences of that remark.

Now, it might be that if someone were to engage him in thorough questioning upon the

matter, demanding that he examine the consequences of his beliefs, he would discover that he

was really unsure what conclusions he should draw, and this would reveal his lack of any real

belief. But until such a time it seems that he would retain his belief that he believed the world

would end in 2012, and a sceptic could point to an example such as this as evidence that

incorrigibility has not been established.

We should be suspicious of this example, however, and of any example that stems

from similar motivations. For it looks very much as though what the Superstitious Man calls

‗beliefs‘ are not standardly what we would call so. It is not simply that he does not act on his

belief about the Mayan end of the world; he has no intention of doing so. He may call it a

‗belief‘, but he seems to be using the word very differently to most people. Beliefs are not

collected for their novelty, but possessed for the attribution of their truth. We might call

instead this attitude an ‗affectation‘, understood as something that causes one to expound its

truth (perhaps with a certain amount of theatricality), but not be prompted to any further

substantial action by it. His goal in claiming it as a belief is not to act upon any goals relating

to goals one might have if one possessed such a belief; his goals relating to the proposition are

concerned with things like gaining attention, feeling knowledgeable, seeming mystical. His

goals in relation to espousing it as a belief are not the sort of goals one would have if one

believed that one held that proposition true not because he genuinely believes that he holds a

belief he does not actually hold, but because in saying he believes that he believes it he is not

aiming at a truth that would guide his action in ways that relate to the content of the

proposition, rather, he is aiming at evoking an emotional response from his listeners (himself

included).

Page 91: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

91

Recall that one of the requirements for attitude attribution was a proper understanding

of what was being attributed. The Superstitious Man is either knowingly not using the word

‗belief‘ as other people do, or he has such a fuzzy understanding of what counts as a belief that

he cannot be said to successfully attribute it, for he does not know what it is he attributes. No

case along these lines can be used to undermine the argument.

3.11 Capgras Syndrome

A more concrete counter-example can be drawn from patients suffering from Capgras

syndrome. These are people who maintain that someone close to them is an imposter. In the

case of patient DS, interviewed by Hirstein and Ramachandran (1997), it was his parents. DS

did not otherwise act as one might expect from a person who believed their parents to be

imposters. He did not report the ‗imposters‘ to the police or file a missing persons report. He

did not attempt to flee, or react violently towards these imposters. Gregory Currie and Jon

Jureidini have looked to explain Capgras syndrome on the basis that it, and similar delusions,

are cases where one misidentifies an imagining as a belief: ‗The deluded subject fails to

monitor the self-generatedness of her imagining that P‘ so treats it ‗as if it were a belief, when

in fact it is not one‘ (Currie and Jureidini 2001: 160).

Two worries arise from this: 1) DS attributes to himself the belief that his parents are

imposters, but he does not act as though he believes that his parents are imposters; 2) if Currie

and Jereidini are right, we can mistake imaginings for beliefs, and attribute a belief to

ourselves when what we really have is an imagining.

With regard to point 1, it is important to note that although the characterisation of

Capgras syndrome given above is typical of how the case is presented when discussed by

philosophers, it is not typical of Capgras syndrome itself. Thus, Rose, Buckwalter, and Turri

generalise DS‘s passivity to the matter and note, ‗Capgras patients typically continue to share

their lives with the purported impostors… [DS] does not run away from these impostors; he

does not call the police; he does not seek out lost loved ones‘ (2014: 684). The generalisation

from DS does not really reflect the evidence, though. Not all those diagnosed with Capgras

syndrome show this apparent divide between professed belief and other action. Thus, Passer

and Warnock report the case of Mrs D, who believed her husband to be an imposter, and who

took specific and intelligible actions to protect herself from the intruder in her life:

Page 92: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

92

She refused to sleep with the impostor, locked her bedroom and door at night, asked

her son for a gun, and finally fought with the police when attempts were made to

hospitalise her. (Passer and Warnock 1991: 446)

Moreover, Hirtsein writes in a more recent paper: ‗The majority of Capgras‘ patients are

suspicious of the ―impostor‖ at the very least. Many are paranoid about the ―impostor‖, and

attribute intent to harm to him‘ (2010: 237).

Nevertheless, it may be thought that even one such case lends plausibility to what

might otherwise have seemed implausible: that one might have a belief, but fail to act in

accordance with possession of that belief. So then the question becomes: is it a good

explanation of DS that he has the higher-order belief that he believes his parents to be

imposters, but lacks the actual belief that he does?

Currie and Jureidini‘s account of delusions as imaginings that have been misidentified

as beliefs is based on the supposition that imaginings are both relevantly like beliefs, and that

they are different in ways that account for the oddities of cases like Capgras syndrome. On

their account, imaginings are like beliefs in that they mirror the ‗inferential characteristics‘ of

beliefs (Currie and Jureidini 2001: 159); thus, a reader may extrapolate causes and effects

within the narrative, based on both the imaginings and actual beliefs. Thus, in a murder

mystery, I work out ‗who done it‘ based on what I have imagined about various characters,

their access to weapons, their movements about an imagined place, as well as my knowledge

of how real humans behave, what can kill them, and so forth. Imaginings differ from beliefs,

they argue, in that they are ‗much more easily triggered by perception‘, and that it is common

for a rational agent to imagine all sorts of ‗wild hypotheses‘ in response to odd experiences,

but they are far less likely to adopt wild beliefs on such prompting. Imaginings are also not apt

to be revised in the light of new evidence or contrasting beliefs, rather ‗beliefs inconsistent

with the imagining move temporarily into the background‘ (Currie and Jureidini 2001: 160).

Thus, they claim, imaginings provide a good explanation of delusions because it is in their

nature to ‗coexist‘ with contradictory beliefs and be resistant to revision on the basis of

evidence.

Currie and Jureidini then appeal to Stone and Young‘s (1997) analysis that what is

happening in Capgras cases is that the aspects of vision for overt recognition and for affective

significance come apart. This means (the thought goes) that the sufferer may recognise that a

Page 93: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

93

person looks the same without the accompanying ‗cognitive significance‘—the sense of a

person‘s identity. Currie and Jureidini (2001: 161) interpret this as a reason to suppose that the

sense of conviction a person feels when they have a belief can occur without the usual guide to

action that accompanies a belief. However, it is not clear how the coming apart of the sense of

conviction that I have a belief from that belief‘s guide to action follows from the thought that

overt recognition and affective significance come apart. Moreover, this is not how Stone and

Young see it themselves. They conclude that there is no compelling argument that deluded

individuals do not believe their delusions (Stone and Young 1997: 360). The effect of the

affective part of face recognition being damaged in changing emotional response, they argue,

is because the person they see looks like their loved one, but without the accompanying sense

of recognition. From which, they conclude, it is a perfectly rational response to the anomalous

experience to conclude that although the person looks like their loved one, they are not that

person.

Besides this point, there is good reason to think that Stone and Young‘s account is not

the best explanation for Capgras. Firstly, over-reliance on a biological account of visual

systems means that this account cannot explain the existence of Capgras in blind patients, such

as that detailed in Rojo, Caballero, Iruela, and Baca, (1991). Hirstein, who originally

interviewed the philosophically problematic patient, DS, has provided a different analysis in

his more recent work, which better fits the symptoms of Capgras and other related disorders

more generally. He argues that the damage that precipitates Capgras syndrome is to the part of

the brain that understands and predicts the behaviour of others. It does so by constructing

‗individualised egocentric representations of her mind‘ (Hirstein 2010: 243). These are

constructed for specific, well-known people, based strongly off their actual behaviours, as

opposed to the generic representations that allow us to get by with people we do not know

particularly well. ‗Capgras‘ syndrome occurs when egocentric representations of a particular

person are damaged or inaccessible and are replaced by other, incorrect representations‘

(Hirstein 2010: 243). This explains why Capgras delusions affect our (apparent) beliefs about

loved ones, and not casual acquaintances, and are distinguished from general paranoid beliefs

about all humans one encounters. However, Capgras syndrome does not affect our ability to

recognise the person in other ways, ‗This creates the appearance of a familiar body and face,

but without the familiar personality, beliefs, and thoughts‘ (Hirstein 2010: 233). The key is:

Capgras patients only fail to know their loved ones in certain ways.

Page 94: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

94

A Capgras patient is able to function in limited ways as though they knew the person in

question—they recognise the face/body, and may interact with them in some ways much as

they would before—but in others (including asserting that they know them) they do not. This

is because the belief that you know someone, or that ‗He is my father‘, is complex, and made

up of other beliefs—beliefs about what your father is like, how he behaves, what he looks like,

etc. It is not the case that DS believes his father to be an imposter but acts as though this belief

is false. DS believes his father to be in an imposter because the man no longer matches the

individualised egocentric representation DS associates with his father—he no longer

recognises his father in the specific sense by which he identifies his father. And he acts just as

though he no longer believes the man to be his father in that sense by saying the man does not

feel familiar and is not his father. But any other beliefs he might have had about the man that

might cause him to behave as though he were his father in other ways could well persist.

What we have here are competing explanations of a phenomenon that might provide a

counter-example to the argument for incorrigibility if the explanation for certain observed

behaviours is that delusions are not beliefs, but can be misidentified as such. It is only a

counter-example on that explanation. As we have seen, there are other explanations, ones that

fit better with empirical evidence at this time. That might change in the future—the correct

explanation for Capgras syndrome is not something that can be settled a priori. What is clear is

that the sceptic cannot help herself to the assumption that Capgras syndrome is to be explained

in this way and therefore constitutes a counter-example. The burden of proof is upon her.

Moreover, if ‗My parents are imposters‘ is an imagining I have incorrectly identified as

a belief, as evidenced by my lack of action in accordance with that belief, then one can ask

whether I truly believe that I believe it. If the only way in which I act as though I believe that I

believe it is to assent to the assertion that ‗My parents are imposters‘, then I am failing to fulfil

the rational requirements of someone who believes that she believes something. It looks like I

am either failing to understand what it is to believe something, or my rationality has been

sufficiently affected by my mental illness to prevent me from drawing inferences where I

should. However, if my very inferential capacities are brought into doubt, then I must also

question the inferences drawn from the apparent possibility of sceptical scenarios (that I might

be a victim of something like Capgras syndrome, that I could be imagining all this, etc. etc.).

This is not a path my sceptic can intelligibly go down.

Page 95: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

95

For these reasons, I do not think my sceptic has reason to doubt incorrigibility based on

the case of Capgras syndrome.

3.12 Conclusion

I have shown that, although Cartesian infallibility cannot be claimed, this is not reason to

suppose all our beliefs about mental states to be as dubiously justified as our perceptual

beliefs. Where the mental state is vaguely delimited, not very intense, and where the words we

use to label it are broadly defined, I concede that it can be difficult to know whether I am in

that state or not. However, intense, clearly defined experiences, such as being in agony, do not

seem possible to doubt. The phenomenal experience of bright, foveal colour also remains

untouched by introspective sceptical arguments. And where I believe that I believe something,

so long as I do properly understand the proposition I claim to believe, it is necessarily the case

that I do believe it. I can therefore know that I have the beliefs I have, where I believe myself

to have them.

Knowing solely that I have beliefs is enough to justify the first premise of the

Davidsonian triangulation transcendental argument: that I have beliefs. In addition to knowing

that I have beliefs, there seem to be at least some cases in which I know that the content of

those beliefs is true (bright, foveal colour; pain). The above is not intended to be a complete

catalogue of such beliefs, but should be enough to show that at least some aspects of the

phenomenology of our experience can be certainly known.

Page 96: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

96

Chapter 4: Mind in World—Strong Transcendental Arguments

Without A Chasm of Necessity

In chapter two I outlined a number of different ways in which transcendental arguments may

be defined, and how these arguments have been used to either rebut or dismiss the sceptic. I

noted that a defining attribute of transcendental arguments is that they start from a premise

concerning thought or experience and move towards a conclusion that some proposition must

be true because it is a necessary condition of that premise. That the first premise should

concern something mental—thought or experience—is important because we commonly take

ourselves to have better justification for our beliefs concerning the mental than we do beliefs

concerning the extra-mental. This is particularly important in seeking to combat scepticism

because such a premise ought to be something that the sceptic accepts, and by showing the

truth of the conclusion to be a necessary condition of the truth of the first premise, the sceptic

may thereby be forced to accept something she initially held in doubt. In chapter three I

defended the assertion that at least some propositions concerning the mental are immune from

doubt by the type of sceptic that interests me, and are therefore available for use in the first

premise of a transcendental argument. The advantage of using transcendental arguments

against the sceptic, then, is that they start from a premise the sceptic accepts.

Where transcendental arguments diverge in type is in the type of proposition they

claim to be a necessary condition of the truth of the first, mental premise. Since Stroud‘s 1968

article, ‗Transcendental Arguments‘, and the development of his criticisms since then, most

transcendental theorists have focused their attention on weak transcendental arguments—

arguments that aim to show us that it is a necessary condition of some the truth of some mental

proposition that some other mental proposition be true. I have argued that these are ineffectual

in dealing with my sceptic, and even if they could be made to work, it would be in such a way

whereby the situation would be even worse that the sceptic feared.

I therefore advocate for the use of strong transcendental arguments in offering the kind

of robust response to the sceptic I have argued we have reason to want to give. Yet, strong

transcendental arguments have fallen out of favour due to criticisms raised by Stroud. It will

be my task in this chapter to defend the plausibility of strong transcendental arguments against

these criticisms. I argue that these criticisms rest illicitly on the assumption of a metaphysical

Page 97: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

97

picture that the sceptic explicitly does not assume: her position is one of doubt as regards the

nature of reality. I then move on to make a positive argument for the plausibility of a

metaphysical picture upon which a strong transcendental argument could be formed. I stress

that I do not argue directly for such a metaphysical picture, as if this could be achieved it

would negate the point of giving a transcendental argument. Rather, I substantiate the claim

that Stroud‘s assumption of a different metaphysical picture is implausible, as a plausible

picture exists upon which a successful strong transcendental argument could be found.

4.1 Stroud, Transcendental Arguments, and the Verification Principle

In his 1968 paper, Stroud (2000a: 13–20) analyses a number of transcendental arguments and

diagnoses them as either containing a suppressed verification principle, or requiring one for

validity. I.e. what they need, but (at least on the surface) lack is a premise that asserts the

meaningfulness of a non-analytic sentence be dependent on its empirical verifiability. Thus,

for Strawson‘s arguments in Individuals, Stroud claims that the missing premise is: ‗if the

notion of objective particulars makes sense to us, then we can sometimes know certain

conditions to be fulfilled, the fulfilment of which logically implies either that objects continue

to exist unperceived or that they do not‘ (Stroud 2000a: 15–16). As Stroud points out, the

arguments would thus be dealing with the conditions of meaningfulness, not knowledge. As

such, they leave the sceptic free to simply say that talk of that which is in question simply is

not meaningful: ‗it is always open to the sceptic to accept the arguments and conclude that talk

about, say, the continued existence of unperceived objects really doesn‘t make sense to us‘

(Stroud 2000a: 20). This, Stroud says, would only make scepticism stronger—not only can we

not know whether these propositions are true, we would not even understand them. On this

basis, Stroud argues that a successful anti-sceptical argument would have to be completely

general, and deal with the necessary conditions of anything‘s making sense.

Thus, Stroud suggests that transcendental arguments must be such that they aim to

show that the truth of their conclusion is a necessary condition of there being any experience

or thought at all. They would thus be especially powerful against the sceptic: ‗If the

conclusion were true, there could be no experience to falsify it‘ (Stroud 2000a: 21). He

therefore supposes that transcendental arguments will need to make use of a premise that

asserts that the proposition which the sceptic doubts is a member of a privileged class of

Page 98: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

98

propositions. These propositions are such that to be mentioned at all (as they are when

doubted) guarantees their truth.

Stroud is doubtful that we shall actually find that that any of the propositions which are

members of this ‗privileged class‘ actually are the very same propositions that the sceptic

doubts. He concedes that it seems difficult to demonstrate that there is no such proposition, but

adds in favour of its unlikelihood the thought that the sceptic can always just say that it is

enough to make talk of such things possible if we believe the proposition to be true (ibid.). He

further asserts that any attempt to refute the sceptic on this point would involve a retreat to the

verification principle, again, and if we can establish the verification principle, then we do not

need the apparatus of transcendental argument to combat the sceptic anyway.

This does seem to be a necessary consequence. True, one might retreat to a verification

principle at this point, and it may be that we can say of a number of transcendental arguments

that this is what they (covertly) have done. Surely, though, on Stroud‘s definition, these are

not really transcendental arguments after all. They aimed to show that x was the case because

it is a necessary condition of y, but if they actually retreat to a verification principle, they are

no longer offering a transcendental argument. As Stroud says, the verification principle could

then do the job without the more complicated transcendental apparatus at its disposal.

However, if one really were committed to arguing for x on a transcendental basis, one‘s reply

to a sceptic who maintained that it was sufficient for y that one believe that x, would not be

that a belief that x is only meaningful if it can be shown whether or not x is true, but rather that

the belief that x requires that x be true.

Moreover, Stroud has artificially limited the scope of transcendental arguments to what

I have called ‗very strong‘ transcendental arguments—those where the very proposition

doubted is shown to have as a necessary condition something which the sceptic must assume

in justifying her doubt (i.e. something very general, such as that I have any beliefs at all).

True, the first proposition of a transcendental argument will need to be something the sceptic

cannot weasel out of accepting. However, I have shown that the sceptic can be motivated to

agree that certain claims about the mental must be true without necessitating that the first

premise be completely general.

Here, Stroud will step in with what, if successful, will be a more substantial criticism:

that no strong transcendental argument can succeed, because it is not possible to cross the

Page 99: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

99

‗bridge of necessity‘ (2000b: 159) from psychological premises to non-psychological

conclusions.

4.2 The Bridge of Necessity

I find this somewhat puzzling, as a criticism. It is difficult to see what the basis for the thought

that we cannot move from psychological premises to non-psychological conclusions is,

beyond mere incredulity. The case is not helped by the emotive terms Stroud uses when he

discusses it. The phrase ‗bridge of necessity‘ implies a yawning gap between ‗psychological‘

and ‗non-psychological‘ facts, and he says that its achievement would be a ‗truly remarkable

feat‘ (ibid.), calling such a feat a ‗truly remarkable bridge of necessity‘ (2000b: 162).

However, although these phrases express quite clearly Stroud‘s incredulity, they do nothing to

explain why it is thought to be so very implausible. It is tempting to think that there is nothing

more to it than a strong intuition on Stroud‘s part.

Stroud (2000b: 156–7) is quick to stress that he is not meaning to challenge that there

might be a causal connection between our thought/experience/concepts etc. and the world—

the physical activities of the brain and so forth. However, this is not the sort of connection we

are looking for, and which he is dubious could exist; this appears to be a contingent

connection, and we are looking for necessity. However, saying what will not be a solution is

not the same as saying why no solution will be possible.

Stroud asks:

Even if we allow that we can come to see how our thinking in certain ways necessarily

requires that we also think in certain other ways… how can truths about the world

which appear to say or imply nothing about human thought or experience be shown to

be genuinely necessary conditions of such psychological facts as that we think and

experience things in certain ways. (Stroud 2000b: 158–9)

But again, this is not a reason. Stroud asks a rhetorical question, in response to which we are

presumed to share his incredulity, but something more substantial is needed than this.

He indicates that these truths about the world are such as to appear to imply nothing

about human thought or experience, but it is hardly a novel philosophical trait for it to not be

obvious at first that one thing implies another. This alone cannot make it ‗truly remarkable‘

Page 100: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

100

that a truth that seems on the surface to imply nothing about human thought or experience

should do so anyway.

4.3 True of the Mind vs True of the World

In ‗The Goal of Transcendental Arguments‘, Stroud (2000d: 210) notes that we can move

from ‗psychological‘ statements to ‗non-psychological‘ ones under special circumstances. For

instance, if ‗Jed knows that the cat is on the mat‘ then it is true that ‗The cat is on the mat‘.

However, as Stroud points out, ‗if would-be transcendental reflection is allowed to start from

the fact that we know certain things, there would be no need for further enquiry‘. Stroud does

not go into details as to why, but we can surmise that, even though he concedes that the verb

‗to know‘ is a psychological term, it is impurely so. If you know something you do not just

believe it, you are correct in that belief. We have smuggled in the truth of some proposition

about the world in such cases.

A question arises here: does Stroud forbid all uses of the word ‗know‘ in

transcendental arguments? What about the purely psychological premises along the lines of: ‗I

have experiences‘, ‗I have x experience‘, ‗I have concepts‘, ‗I have x concept‘, ‗I have beliefs‘

and so on. Presumably Stroud is willing to concede that the reason transcendental arguments

start from such premises is that they are ones about which we do find ourselves able to speak

with some authority. The truth of such premises cannot pass on to any conclusion if we cannot

concede that they are true to begin with. Stroud does not want to forbid all arguments from

psychological premises, just those that move from psychological premises to non-

psychological conclusions. Does he mean to say that we can only have conditional premises of

a psychological form, e.g. ‗If I have experiences, then I must believe that y (although it is by

no means certain that I have experiences)‘?

Stroud would not seem to be saying this. Recall from section 2.7.4 that in proposing a

weak interpretation of Davidson‘s argument from triangulation, Stroud wrote:

The possibility from which the sceptical line of thinking begins is therefore not one

which anyone could consistently find to be actual. It involves the presence of certain

specific beliefs, but attribution of those beliefs requires our finding them to be largely

true. Believing a certain set of propositions to be all or mostly false precludes our

Page 101: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

101

assigning them as contents of the beliefs of any people we find to have beliefs. (Stroud

2000c: 198)

We cannot get to the conclusion that we must believe that they and we are largely correct if

there is not an additional premise to the effect that we do ascribe belief. This cannot be

hypothetical, if it is to bite, it must be a truth or knowledge claim.

Here we reveal the problem with Stroud‘s somewhat nebulous categories of

‗psychological‘ and ‗non-psychological‘. He seems to be drawing the distinction between ‗true

of the world‘ and ‗about the mind‘; but if he wants to motivate any argument, he must concede

that his so-called ‗psychological‘ premises are not just ‗about the mind‘, they are ‗true of the

mind‘. To say that anything is true is to say that it is a fact, and facts concern the world. Here

is how we motivate the thought that the mind is a part of the world without relying on some

contingent causal claim: to say that the mind is a part of the world is not to assume that it is

physical, that it supervenes on the physical, that it reduces to the physical, that it is caused by

the physical, or that its experiences or thoughts are caused by the physical after some

fashion—none of this is assumed. The world is that which exists, that which things are true of.

Stroud must concede this for his weak transcendental argument to go through. If he

does so, though, his criticism of strong transcendental arguments collapses. There is nothing

‗truly remarkable‘ in saying that one truth about the world entails another. The fact that the

one truth is psychological and the other not can have no impact if this is no longer seen as a

dichotomy, as an either/or situation. Just as Jed‘s knowing that the cat is on the mat entails

something about the world because it is already saying something about the world, my

knowing that I believe or doubt something about the world entails something about the world

also, namely, that I believe or doubt that thing.

To summarize: Strong transcendental arguments aim to refute the sceptic by showing

that an extra-mental proposition is a necessary condition of thought or experience: some

aspect of thought or experience that the sceptic does not doubt. Weak transcendental

arguments aim not to refute the sceptic, but to show that the doubted proposition is

invulnerable in the sense that we could never find it to be false. Stroud urges that weak

transcendental arguments are to be preferred because strong transcendental arguments are

always open to the criticism that it is enough that we believe them to be true (thus requiring a

verification principle to move from the thought that it is meaningful to assert this to the

Page 102: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

102

conclusion that it is true). There is no direct evidence that all strong transcendental arguments

must be open to this criticism, but Stroud argues that we have reason to think that they are

because it is simply so implausible that one can move from psychological premises to non-

psychological premises about the world. Not only is Stroud‘s incredulity insufficient reason to

reject strong transcendental arguments, but his distinction between psychological and non-

psychological propositions is, in fact, artificial. Any assertion of a psychological proposition is

an assertion of a truth about the world.

4.4 An Objection: the Psychological and Non-Psychological are Different

Categories of Fact

Keith Allen has raised an objection to this point that even if we concede that the world is the

totality of that which things are true of, this does not entail that there are not different

categories of facts48

. It could be argued that a truth of economics just does not seem to be a

truth of physics. Similarly, although truths about the mind may be truths about the world in

some sense, but this does not mean that we can move from truths about the mind to other, non-

psychological truths about the world.

However, I think this misunderstands the relationship between different categories of

fact. In the case of the relationship between the mental and non-mental, conditions are

imposed on the mind by the world, and it is in virtue of this that we can deduce that, as the

mind is x, the world must be y. Furthermore, I do not think that categories of facts can be as

exclusive as the objection suggests. Rather, what we have are overlapping filters. Physical

facts can influence economic facts. Facts about the location of a country, its size, the

molecular makeup of the different products available for sale there—these facts, even if they

are not economic facts themselves, undoubtedly have an impact upon economic facts. So, even

if we grant that mental and non-mental facts are of different categories, this does not mean that

the one cannot be deduced from the other.

48 Raised in conversation, 2009.

Page 103: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

103

4.5 Mind in World

What does it mean to say that the mind is a part of the world, and that, therefore, there is no

chasm of necessity to be bridged? In a trivial sense, even Descartes would accept that the mind

is a part of the world. If the world is just the totality of existents, then if even a single,

immaterial mind is instantiated, then that mind is a part of the world.

I do think there are some pictures of mind and world on which reasoning from

premises concerning the mind to premises concerning the extra-mental would be problematic.

However, I shall argue that these pictures of the relationship between the mind and the rest of

the world are not the only ones available, nor the most palatable. Stroud is not free to assume

that these are the case.

I will argue that it must be a picture in which the mind and the extra-mental world are

not seen as conceptually and essentially distinct in the manner of Cartesian dualism. I will also

argue that idealism is neither desirable for the strong transcendental theorist, nor strong

transcendental arguments desirable for the idealist. I will conclude from this that what I need

to defend is some non-idealist, monist picture of mind and world. I will argue that such a

picture is physicalism, and furthermore, that supervenience physicalism can explain the

picture of entailments from different categories of fact suggested above. If such a picture can

be shown to be plausible, I maintain, the possibility that we may find some strong

transcendental argument becomes equally plausible. Hence, I will therefore defend

supervenience physicalism as a picture of the relationship between mind and world that is both

coherent and plausible. This is not a proof of physicalism, which would negate the need for a

strong transcendental argument. Rather, in defending the plausibility of a picture of the world

that would allow for a strong transcendental argument to be constructed, I show that Stroud

cannot assume a picture of the world upon which reasoning from premises about the mental to

a conclusion about the extra-mental is implausible.

4.6 Substance Dualism

If substance dualism is true, I concede that we shall be hard pressed to claim knowledge of the

physical substance by transcendental means.

Page 104: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

104

A substance, as characterised canonically by Descartes, is something that can be

understood as completely and essentially distinct from other substances. For Descartes, we

know that mind and body are distinct substances because they can be clearly and distinctly

conceived of as separate, and this separateness is founded in the essence of each entirely

excluding the other. When I consider mental substance, he argues, I can see that all that

belongs to it is thought, for I can conceive of it completely without reference to such material

concepts as body or extension. Thus, he writes:

[O]n the one hand, I have a clear and distinct idea of myself, in as far as I am only a

thinking and unextended thing, and as, on the other hand, I possess a distinct idea of

body, in so far as this is simply an extended, non-thinking thing. (Descartes

Meditations: VI.9)

The clear distinctness of these conceptions is taken to be demonstrated by Descartes‘s ability

to conceive of himself (as a thinking thing) in entirety, without conceiving of his body; and his

ability to conceive of his body entirely without conceiving of it as thinking. The ability to

conceive of himself entirely as a thinking thing, and nothing else, is supposed to show that he

is essentially a thinking thing, and nothing else. This is taken to be demonstrated by

Descartes‘s ability to conceive of himself as existing when all he knows of himself is that he

thinks : ‗simply by knowing that I exist, and seeing at the same time that absolutely nothing

else belongs to my nature or essence except that I am a thinking thing‘ (ibid.). Similarly, when

one considers material substance, Descartes argues, one can understand it completely as ‗an

extended, non-thinking thing‘ (ibid.).

Of course, if this is accepted, we shall not be able to argue from facts about the mind to

facts about the material world; the two will be mutually exclusive, as they will be known to be

different substances based on their fundamental conceptual exclusivity. We would have to, as

Stroud suggests, employ some verificationist principle, such as that God guarantees the truth

of our clear and distinct ideas, that: ‗he is no deceiver, and thence… all which I clearly and

distinctly perceive is of necessity true‘ (Descartes, Meditations: V.15). Further, even

supposing this, we would need to have some clear and distinct ideas about the physical world.

It is not at all clear that we have such ideas, nor that an argument can be made in favour of a

guarantor, like God, without begging the question against the sceptic.

Page 105: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

105

So be it. If substance dualism is true, then we will not be able to construct a strong

transcendental argument that does not rely upon a suppressed verification principle. However,

the mere fact that there is some picture of the relationship between mind and non-mental

world upon the truth of which it would not be possible to construct a strong transcendental

argument does not show that no such argument is possible. Stroud‘s argument is that it is

implausible that a strong transcendental argument might reason from a mental premise to an

extra-mental conclusion. But substance dualism itself is held to be implausible in many

quarters. If some other account of mind and world can be offered on which it is possible to

reason from mental premises to a non-mental conclusion, this will be enough.

4.7 Monism and Idealism

From the discussion above, it seems to me that what follows from Stroud‘s objection is not

that strong transcendental arguments are not possible, but rather that for a strong

transcendental argument to be true, some form of monism must hold, at least in the sense that

the entities which exist must be of a sort such that they are not conceptually exclusive in the

manner of Cartesian substances. Such a monism could, theoretically, be idealism—arguing

that the mind‘s being a certain way is dependent on the world‘s being a certain way is trivial,

once it is granted that everything is mental. Yet, this is precisely why monist idealism and

strong transcendental arguments can have no use for each other.

An immaterialist idealist, such as Berkeley, dismisses the sceptic on the basis that the

existence of non-minded things simply consists in their being perceived—there is no question

of whether they resemble real things existing independently of the mind, so no transcendental

argument is needed. It is monist, in that ‗there is not any other substance than spirit, or that

which perceives‘ (PHK: I.749

), but this is argued for on the basis that ideas cannot exist apart

form the thing which has them: ‗for an idea to exist in an unperceiving thing, is a manifest

contradiction‘ (ibid.). For ‗sensible ideas‘ (‗colour, figure, motion, smell, taste, and such like‘

(ibid.)) to exist is to be perceived, and he argues that nothing can be like an idea except an

49 I refer to the 1998 edition of A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, edited by Jonathan

Dancy, using the abbreviation ‗PHK‘.

Page 106: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

106

idea. How can colour be like something invisible? How can hardness be like something

intangible? (PHK: 1.8).

An idealist in Berkeley‘s sense feels no need for a strong transcendental argument

because he maintains that the picture of mind and world which generates the sort of scepticism

which concerns me is nonsensical. He does not seek to move from premises about the mental

to premises about the non-mental, as it is his contention that all entities are mental entities.

It may then seem to be a difficulty for me, if this idealist conception of mind and world

is true. We could not argue from the mental to the non-mental, because there will be no non-

mental (no non-spiritual). However, I do not see this as a very significant problem. That I

might be a Berkeleyan solipsistic consciousness is precisely the kind of thing the sceptic

worries might be true, but she cannot assume this. Her point is that we do not know whether

this is the case. No case has been made for the truth of this situation and it is not widely held

as a particularly plausible thesis.

4.8 Transcendental Idealism

Something similar goes for the transcendental idealist. The transcendental idealist may accept

that the noumenal, at least, is extra-mental, but he will assert that the chasm between the

mental and the noumenal is too wide to ever be breached. It cannot be known, as what we can

know is limited to the way in which we, as limited beings, must organise the manifold of

intuitions so as to make it intelligible.

For the transcendental idealist this is not a worrying prospect, for everything the are

interested in establishing is of the phenomenal realm. We can reason between the mental and

the phenomenal because the structure of the phenomenal is imposed by the mental. For our

sceptic, it is rather more of a concern that we can never know about things as they are in

themselves, but by the same token, this is not something the sceptic can assume, and

transcendental idealism is hardly so popular a position that all others are deemed implausible.

If another suitably plausible position it will not be enough for Stroud to point to transcendental

idealism and say that ‗Well, if transcendental idealism is true, we can never reason from

premises about the mental to a conclusion about the noumenal‘.

Page 107: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

107

4.9 Physicalism

What follows from the above is that if I wish to claim that it is plausible that some STA can be

found, I should argue that some picture of mind and world is plausible which is neither idealist

nor dualist. It should defend the plausibility of a claim that the mind is made of the same kind

of ‗stuff‘ as the world, without resorting to the claim that all stuff is mind stuff. For the rest of

this chapter, therefore, I shall defend the plausibility of a (at least a certain kind of)

physicalism.

Note that it is not my purpose to argue that physicalism must be known to be true in

order for some strong transcendental argument to be successful. Rather, I merely wish to make

the case that if physicalism is true, it could well be possible that some strong transcendental

argument can be made. I do not need to prove physicalism, for my purposes (that would

negate the necessity for a strong transcendental argument), I merely need to show that the

position is intelligible, and clarify how it would make a strong transcendental argument

feasible.

4.9.1 Defining Physicalism

However, it has been argued by Crane and Mellor that physicalism is highly problematic.

They characterise physicalism as the belief that ‗everything is physical‘ (Crane and Mellor

1990: 185), or that there are no entities that are not physical entities, and, in particular, that all

mental entities are really physical. Their thesis is that this position cannot be defined in any

way that is clear, credible, and non-vacuous (ibid.). They point out that although physicalism

is, historically, a descendent of materialism, we cannot make any appeal to matter. This is

because the original advocates of materialism defined matter in an a priori way that has turned

out not to reflect the facts of modern physics. Crane and Mellor take the seventeenth century

definition of matter to be: ‗solid, inert, impenetrable and conserved, and to interact

deterministically and only on contact‘ (p.186). They note that: ‗the "matter" of modern physics

is not at all solid, or inert, or impenetrable, or conserved; and it interacts indeterministically

and arguably sometimes at a distance‘ (ibid.). So, if this were the definition of what it is to be

physical, it would be simply false that all objects are physical objects.

I think one may still say that the physicalist thesis contains an assertion that non-

mental objects exist, and that the mind is made of the same basic ‗stuff‘ as these. However, it

Page 108: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

108

may be thought that to take this thought as a rebuttal is to miss the point of Crane and Mellor‘s

paper. The title of the paper is ‗There is No Question of Physicalism‘, and we can see them as

not so much rejecting physicalism as arguing that it is a theory in response to a question that is

no longer relevant. If materialism has been shown to be false, then we shall lose the

motivations materialists held, and we are faced with a challenge as to why we should want to

argue that all is physical. Crane and Mellor do not simply doubt that it can be done, they think

the attempt cannot be coherently made, and see no need to try. That which is studied by

physics may be such that we cannot offer an a priori definition for it. If this is the case, how

could it make sense to pick the ‗physical‘ as somehow fundamental.

From my perspective, the motivation stems from the thought that it should be coherent

to assert that the non-mental both exists and that the mental is not of a significantly different

sort of stuff such that one could say that a mental fact could not entail a physical fact, for the

reason that in some sense they are not different kinds of facts. In order to support this, I need

to be able to define the sense in which they are not different kinds of facts. I believe that

supervenience physicalism intelligibly captures this sense.

The objection from section 4.4 was that we could at least understand the mental and

the physical as different categories of facts in the same way that facts of economics might be

said to be of a different category to facts of physics, and that we might consider mental and

physical facts to be exclusive in this weaker sense. However, I wish to argue that in this

weaker form, categories of facts can overlay one another—like coloured filters on the world.

Later in this chapter I will go on to clarify how supervenience physicalism cashes out this

metaphor so as to rebut Allen‘s criticism. However, first I must defend supervenience

physicalism against Crane and Mellor‘s attack.

4.9.2 Defending Supervenience Physicalism: Differing Mentally Whilst Not

Differing Physically

Crane and Mellor attribute to physicalists who have given up on the idea of an a priori

definition the claim that the empirical world contains all and only what a ‗true complete

physical science‘ would say it contains (Crane and Mellor 1990: 186). The problem then, is:

how do we provide a definition of what it is for something to be a physical science in a way

that avoids making the physicalist thesis trivially true, without restricting it such that it is

Page 109: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

109

obviously false? We cannot simply state that the subject matter of current physics will be the

subject matter of a true, complete physics: this was the mistake of seventeenth century

thinkers, and is obviously false, as much is still unknown, and we have good reason, from

precedent, to suppose that some aspects of the doctrines of current physical sciences will turn

out to be false. However, we also cannot simply include anything empirical. If psychology is

included amongst the physical sciences, then physicalism will be vacuous. Or so the thought

goes.

Crane and Mellor then examine and reject a number of possible answers to this

challenge. As I am concerned primarily with supervenience physicalism, I shall focus on their

objections to that. They characterise supervenience physicalism as the thesis that: ‗Two things

will never change or differ in any way without also changing or differing in some non-mental

way‘ (Crane and Mellor 1990: 203); thus, they say the physical excludes the mental by being

that upon which everything supervenes. Supervenience does not face the problems of

reductionism in saying what the ‗real‘ physical things are that everything can be in principle

reduced to. However, they still find supervenience to be doubtful.

Crane and Mellor‘s argument against supervenience is made on the principle that two

thinkers could be alike in non-mental properties, and still have different beliefs. They argue

for this based on a Putnam-like Twin Earth example (see Putnam 1973). My twin and I are

‗intrinsically‘ identical, yet when she thinks ‗Water is wet‘ she has a belief concerning XYZ,

and when I think ‗Water is wet‘ I have a belief concerning H2O. Crane and Mellor argue that

she and I have the same intrinsic properties in this case in as much as we have the same

‗properties, same relations, same properties of the thing thought about‘ (Crane and Mellor

1990: 204). However, this is simply false. Quite clearly, my relations have all been to water,

up until now, and my twin, prior to this point, only had experience of twater (twin-

water/XYZ).

Crane and Mellor (ibid.) anticipate that the supervenience theorist may say that

thoughts supervene not just on the thinker‘s intrinsic properties, but on her relations to other

things. However, they do not think this is an effective response, based on the ways in which

speakers can make mistakes. They suppose that my twin and I might look at the same tree, and

she might think ‗That‘s an oak‘ where I would think ‗That‘s an elm‘—we would be relating to

the same object, but having different thoughts. Again, though, this seems to be simply false. In

one relation, the relation to the tree before us, we may be exactly the same (or as near to as

Page 110: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

110

should make no significant difference), but we have had countless relations in the past with

other trees that have been different. In learning the names of trees she must have been shown

different trees to the ones I was when we were introduced to oaks, just as my twin was relating

to XYZ and not H2O when she was taught the word ‗water‘.

Crane and Mellor (1990: 205) anticipate this response: ‗past experiences do have

present effects‘. However, again they import the language of intrinsic properties into the

supervenience theorist‘s defence, which seems unnecessary to me. They suppose that the

supervenience theorist will say that, as these past experiences are at a temporal distance, they

cannot have their effects immediately, and hence must be mediated by some present intrinsic

properties of myself and my twin. Presumably what they mean by this is that there must be

significant changes in my brain states that act as causal surrogates to the change in meaning

caused by the way I was introduced to trees. However, this seems to be a very odd lesson to

learn from Putnam. Surely the point was that not all meanings are ‗in the head‘ (see Putnam

1973: 704).

Burge argues for this point in ‗Individualism and Psychology‘:

Without the slightest conceptual discomfort we may individuate mental events so as to

allow distinct events (types or tokens) with indistinguishable chemistries, or even

physiologies, for the subject‘s body. Information from and about the environment is

transmitted only through proximal stimulations, but the information is individuated

partly by reference to the nature of normal distal stimuli. (Burge 1986: 17)

The causes for myself and my twin, locally, may be identical, but it does not follow from this

that the mental events will be the same, because the way in which the mental events are

individuated may rely on things in our environment, including events from our past. As Burge

would say, Crane and Mellor have conflated causation with individuation.

The supervenience theorist is committed to saying that mental facts supervene on

physical facts, not solely on ‗intrinsic‘ physical facts about my brain or body. She is free to

differentiate between facts about what is interacting causally with me locally and the facts that

make my mental items the sort of mental items they are, without denying that the latter are

facts about physical things. It seems perfectly comprehensible for me to say that it is a fact

about me right now that when I was introduced to trees I was introduced to trees that looked

such and such a way and told they were elms. (In fact, it seems plausible to me that the

Page 111: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

111

connection of a different sound to the identifying features of what I call elms might intelligibly

be recorded in minutely different ways in my brain than in the brain of someone who

connected those images with the noise for ‗oak‘, but even if it is insisted that my body has the

exact same physical positionings of its particles, it seems to me that it will still relate to

different events in the past to those of my twin.) My ‗intrinsic‘ properties may not have

changed, but there are still facts about me—physical facts—which have: precisely those facts

which determine what sort of mental state I am in.

4.9.3 Defending Supervenience Physicalism: Indeterminism

Crane and Mellor‘s next move is to say that mediating properties between past events and

their mental effects need not differ just because their mental effects do. This argument stems

from the thought that causation need not be deterministic, and, they say, ‗modern physics tells

us that often it is not‘ (Crane and Mellor 1990: 205). When causation is indeterministic, causes

and effects will not supervene on one another. Crane and Mellor anticipate that the

supervenience theorist will say that supervenience, unlike causation, is simultaneous, but they

do not regard this as important. They offer the following argument to motivate this.

Suppose a non-mental property, P, causes a mental property, M, indeterministically.

Suppose, further, that at t1 many people share all their non-mental properties, including P. As

the causation is indeterministic, many, but not all those who possessed P at t1, will possess M

at t2. They then suppose that a and b are two people such that at t2 a is M and b is not. Further,

they state that their non-mental properties at t2 may all be determined by their non-mental

properties at t1. This is presumably because, for some people, it might so happen that whilst

the non-mental property has, in this instance, been determined according to some probability

outlined by the laws of physics, the mental property has not been so determined, as causation

is fundamentally indeterministic. If this is the case, then it seems that we have a case of mental

properties differing whilst there is no difference in the non-mental properties.

However, there are a number of things wrong with this argument. Firstly, this point

about causation seems to have missed something fundamental about the supervenience thesis.

The supervenience physicalist does not say that such and such mental events will always be

caused when such and such physical events occur—supervenience relations are not causation

relations. This is not, as Crane and Mellor seem to take it, a point about supervenience being

Page 112: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

112

some special case of causation in which causes are simultaneous with their effects. Perhaps

some supervenience theorists will want to say this, but it is clear that many will not. As

Robinson (1991: 135–6) points out, Davidsonian anomalous monism will want to say that a

physical event can cause a mental event, but only in so far as the mental event is itself a

physical event, caused by other physical events (Davidson 1980: 223–4). Hence, we will not

get cases where indeterminism in causation means that a and b are physically identical at t2,

but differ mentally, because the physical events have followed the normal causal course, but

for one of them the mental events have not. If there is indeterminism mentally for one, there

will be indeterminism mentally for both, because for there to be indeterminism mentally will

be for there to be indeterminism physically.

We can see this also in Papineau‘s 1990 paper where he expresses the doctrine of

supervenience as being that ‗mental particulars have physical features as well as mental

features‘ (Papineau 1990: 66). He goes on to add that physical features determine those mental

features (but not vice versa—this is the asymmetrical element of supervenience), but this is

clearly not a causal determination, as the thesis so characterised is that the particular that has

mental features is the very same thing that has physical features (see Papineau 1990: 67). The

doctrine is consistent with token identity. It would also be consistent for a supervenience

physicalist to posit that the mental is a property of a physical object.

The other thing that seems odd about this is the appeal to indeterminism as an

explanation for our mistakes. It is true that modern physics tells us that, at the sub-atomic

level, there is a certain amount of indeterminacy, but to acknowledge this is not the same as to

acknowledge the rampant indeterminacy suggested by Crane and Mellor (1990: 205) where

they write: ‗Causation need not, after all, be deterministic, and modern physics tells us that it

often is not‘. Although causation would seem to often be non-deterministic at the sub-atomic

level, it does seem fairly reliable for many larger objects—my interactions with everyday,

medium-sized objects seem very much reliable. Moreover, indeterminacy seems entirely

irrelevant as an explanation of what goes wrong when we make mistakes. When my twin

mistakes an elm for an oak it does not seem that the correct explanation for this will make an

appeal to quantum indeterminacy. My twin thinks elms are oaks because she has a different

history to me, one which has determined that she thinks elms are oaks.

Page 113: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

113

Accepting indeterminacy of the non-mental does not entail accepting indeterminacy

between the physical and the mental, because the way in which the physical determines the

mental need not be a causal determinacy.

4.10 Supervenience, the Completeness of Physics, and Coloured Filters

For these reasons, I argue that Crane and Mellor‘s argument against supervenience

physicalism is ineffective. Furthermore, I think supervenience physicalism is, indeed, a very

good way of understanding how different categories of fact can interact and entail things of

one another. If supervenience physicalism were the case, then this would explain how it is that

one might reason from the mental to the physical because, in some sense, they are the same

kind of stuff, even though we can understand that stuff in different ways via different

categories of fact. This is illustrated by the argument which Papineau (1990) gives for

physicalism from the completeness of physics.

Papineau‘s argument goes like this: if physics is complete, then all physical effects are

entirely determined by the physical events that precede them (Papineau 1990: 67). What

follows from this is what Papineau calls the ‗principle of no independent causal powers‘

(NICP): ‗whenever any mental event causes another event, it does so entirely in virtue of its

physical features, in the sense that the context of the effect is fixed entirely by the physical

features of the mental cause‘. If this is the case, then any mental event that has a physical

effect must do so entirely by virtue of its physical features. Thus, although Eric Bristow‘s

desire to win a game of darts, or for his dart to hit a particular number on the board, may be a

good way of explaining his dart‘s hitting a double sixteen, the part that Eric Bristow‘s desire

plays in determining the dart‘s trajectory is done by virtue of the physical features of his

desire, the brain state that triggers his arm‘s movements perhaps. This must be true, or the

completeness of physics will be false.

If it is true, we shall have a good way of understanding the differences between physical and

mental facts. The mental facts may offer a good explanation of what happens. Indeed, in many

ways they will be more useful. It is certainly more handy to know that Eric Bristow‘s having

such-and-such desires tends to produce such-and-such actions. It is more predictively useful

than knowing that such and such a brain state is likely to bring about those arm movements.

This is in part because we do not have ready access to the map of his brain states; he is

unlikely to play darts whilst inside an fMRI scanner. It is also useful because it seems

Page 114: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

114

plausible that such desires are multiply realisable, both in Eric, and in other individuals, and

we may take our predictive knowledge of the causal productions of desires into broader

situations.

However, as Papineau (1990: 68) notes, the mental, unlike the physical is not

complete. Even supposing psychological laws of some kind, it must still be true that not all

mental events are determined by previous mental events. The pain caused by my stubbing my

toe does not follow from some infinite mental train, it follows from my toe being stubbed: a

physical event. Thus, we have reason to believe that although both mental events and physical

events form explanatory categories of facts, it does not make sense to say that the mental is

distinct from the physical. The mental ‗overlays‘ the physical in the manner of a coloured

filter. I.e. the same event can be differently presented, differently ‗coloured‘, by speaking of

its ‗physical‘ or ‗mental‘ features; but just as the shapes of things seen through a filter are

determined by the way the world is, mental effects are determined by the underlying physical

features of the world.

This also works, as I suggested in section 4.4, for other categories of facts. It is often

more useful to see certain events in terms of economic features—buyings, sellings,

recessions—but the causes and effects of economic events must be completely determined by

the physical features of those events, if physics is complete. It is more explanatorily helpful, to

talk of buyings and sellings and lendings and their effects on the recession, but these events all

have their effects by virtue of the physical features on which they supervene—the movements

of money, or the electrical signals which we also use to represent money when symbolised on

computers.

We can thus see how the different features (economic, mental, physical) are all

exhibited by virtue of the same thing, but they can also influence each other, just as coloured

filters interact to change the appearance of something, whilst still being an appearance of the

same thing. The economic event of paying bills causes the mental event of my worrying, and

the broader economic facts, whilst not being facts about my state of mind, can colour an

account of my state of mind so as to be more effective as an explanation of it. Thus, if it is a

fact about me that I care about financial security, we can explain my worrying by reference to

some facts about my financial situation. However, all these facts merely supervene on facts

about the physical world. The completeness of physics will entail that a complete description

of the physical features of my current situation will entail all the mental and economic effects.

Page 115: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

115

Economic events can have mental effects because they both supervene on the same basic stuff;

they both have the features they do by virtue of their physical features.

It may seem as though the above is missing an obvious problem, however. Namely: by

what right do we assume the completeness of physics? We have not said what physics is, let

alone what it will be for it to be complete. Will we not, then, fall into the same difficulties in

defining physicalism by reference to some future physics, whilst also excluding psychology?

4.11 What is ‘Physics’ and Why is it Complete?

This is the thought that Tim Crane (1991) raises in his response to Papineau. Papineau, he

notes, defines ‗physics‘ purely in terms of completeness. It will be the science of ‗whatever

properties are needed for a complete set of laws covering such effects as stones falling, darts

hitting boards etc.‘ (Papineau 1990: 70), and Crane labels this ‗PHYSICS‘ so as to distinguish

it from ‗physics‘, the science currently engaged in by modern university departments which

operate under that name. Crane (1991: 35) worries that if Papineau‘s argument rests on a claim

about the completeness of PHYSICS, it cannot rule out the mental in the sense it which it

needs to do to have any bite. PHYSICS will incorporate whatever laws and properties are

necessary for explaining archetypal physical occurrences, like the flying of darts, but that may

include mental features of desires, beliefs, and intentions that are not had solely in virtue of the

physical properties. If this is the case, however, the supervenience claim will be trivial, and

would not seem to capture what the physicalist is after at all.

However, this criticism entirely misses Papineau‘s point, as he explains in his (1991)

response to Crane. Of course it will be trivial if mental categories turn out to be a part of

PHYSICS, and difference in the mental will be difference in the physical, but Papineau does

not assume this, and, indeed, he thinks it unlikely. He concedes that it may be that PHYSICS

includes facts about the operation of telekinesis, or some analogue of Descartes‘s theory that

thought is involved in the directional determination of momentum in a way not accounted for

by the objects of physics (see Papineau 2004). If so, Papineau will concede the claim as trivial.

However, it is not trivial now, and, he thinks, based on empirical evidence (of for instance the

way theories such as Descartes‘s have been discounted by modern physics), that the inclusion

of such things this will be unlikely.

Page 116: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

116

Do I not need something stronger than Papineau‘s empirical claim, though, if I am in

the business of defeating the sceptic? No. What I need is for physicalism to be an intelligible

position, and it will be such regardless of whether the claims of physicalism are trivially true

in the unlikely sense that Papineau dismisses, or if it is true in the more substantial sense in

which the mental is not required to account for paradigmatically physical effects. If the mental

supervenes on the physical because it is the PHYSICAL there will be no problem with the

assertion that the mind is a part of the world in such a way that one can reason from facts

about the mind to facts about the world. It will have been established that the mental is not

distinct from the physical in the limiting way that substance dualism specified. If it supervenes

on the physical because it is determined by the PHYSICAL, but not PHYSICAL itself, it will

still be possible to argue from facts about the mind to facts about the extra-mental world.

However, to see this more clearly, we will need to get a bit clearer on in exactly what

sense are the mental is determined by the physical. If the physical (or the PHYSICAL) is

ontologically basic, and everything else supervenes on it, in what sense are these other things

‗real‘ in a way that is neither illusory, as the elimnitivist would have it, nor too substantial, as

the dualist would have it. In this, I take Frank Jackson‘s line of thought, and argue for entry by

entailment.

4.12 Supervenience via Entailment

Jackson (2000) looks to tackle what he calls the ‗location problem‘ via the concept of

entailment. The problem is that, if one wants to say that one category of things is ontologically

basic (e.g. the physical), yet avoid elimnitivist conclusions, there is then a problem as to where

we ‗locate‘ those things which supervene on that ontologically basic category. This is a

question not just for the mental. Jackson (2000: 3) gives the example of solidity. Science tells

a story about pens and chairs and rocks in terms of molecules in a ‗lattice-like array‘ held

together by inter-molecular forces, and this story does not mention solidity. However, it does

not follow from this that pens and chairs and rocks are not solid. Rather, a proper description

of the molecules and the forces that hold between them will include some account of their

excluding encroachment, and this story about excluding encroachment will, in fact, be

sufficient to entail those aspects of solidity not explicitly mentioned by the more basic

Page 117: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

117

characterisation. It will entail that toes are stubbed and cups supported by tables—in short: it

will entail all that we need from a concept like solidity.

This, Jackson says, is exactly how we should account for the physicalist‘s assertions

about the mental, too. What the physicalist‘s assertion about the mental amounts to is the

claim that a complete account of the physical will entail a complete account of the

psychological, and this is the sense in which the physical determines the mental. Jackson

cashes out this thesis in terms of possible worlds: ‗Any world which is a minimal physical

duplicate of our world is a duplicate simpliciter of our world‘ (Jackson 2000: 12). By ‗minimal

physical duplicate‘ he means a world that duplicates the physical aspects of our world, and no

more, so that this definition expresses the thought that if you account for all and only the

physical items of our world, you will have accounted for everything in our world, on the

physicalist thesis; for another world that duplicated all and only the physical aspects of our

world would be a duplicate of everything in our world—i.e. by duplicating only the physical

aspects, that world would have nothing ‗left out‘.

Let us call this thesis ‗M‘. We can see that M follows from physicalism because if M

were false, physicalism would be false. If something that were a minimal physical duplicate of

our world failed to contain something that our world contained (e.g. the mental), then it would

not be the case that accounting for the physical accounted for everything. Given this, Jackson

argues, it is easy to show that, if physicalism is true, then ‗the psychological account of our

world is entailed by the physical account of our world‘ (Jackson 2000: 24). The argument

goes like this: P is the (long and complex) proposition that provides a complete description of

the world in purely physical terms, and which is true of the actual world, and of minimal

physical duplicates, but false at all other worlds. Let Q be any proposition about the mental

that is true at the actual world, and false at any world that differs in mental terms from our

own. If M is true, any world at which P is true is a duplicate simpliciter of the actual world,

and it follows from this that it will be a psychological duplicate, also. However, if this is the

case, then every world at which P is true, Q is true. Hence: P entails Q.

It is worth noting that it does not entail that there is nothing over and above P. Dualism

might be true at some of these worlds. One may wonder again: do not I need something

stronger, otherwise, how will I know I am not in a dualistic world? Again: I do not know this.

This is not an argument that we are not at a dualistic world, it is merely intended to clarify

how we can understand the way in which the mental supervenes on the physical—it does so in

Page 118: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

118

the way that solidity supervenes on the lattice-like array of inter-molecular forces. Ultimately,

though, must I not argue that dualism must be false in order for an STA to be possible? Yes, at

least in as much as for dualisms understood so that one could not reason from the mental to the

physical.

Dualisms that allow for entailments between the mental and the physical will be fine,

but it seems to me that they will be the sort of dualism that will sit comfortably with the

‗substance‘ of mind being studied by ‗PHYSICS‘. Possibly not all of the mind substance

would be available to study via PHYSICS, and it might be that not all aspects of mind would

entail something about the extra-mental world. However, I only need for there to be some of

the right kind in order for an STA to go through. In any case, even if STAs are not possible via

dualisms that are included in this entry via entailment, all I need is that it be plausible that

there could be worlds at which the mental is entailed by the physical in this way.

4.13 Multiple Realiseability

If we accept the above, then it is quite clear how entailment relations may operate between

categories of facts, such that they may entail truths about other categories of facts, whilst still

remaining distinct. However, one might be worried that the entire point of a supervenience

relation is that it is one way: the physical situation entails the mental situation, but not vice

versa. The mental is multiply realisable. This seems highly plausible to me. However,

although I am willing to concede that the same thoughts I have may be realised by an

individual with a slightly different neural structure, or even by some arrangement of computer

chips, I do not think that my thoughts could possibly be realised by a shoe, or a cup of tea.

There are clearly some constraints. One must not forget that the point of a non-idealist

transcendental argument is not that the world must be a certain way because the mind is a

certain way, but rather that the mind must be a certain way because the world is a certain way,

and thus we may be able to reverse engineer the necessity constraints to see how the world

must be to apply such constraints on the mental. It may well be the case that, although the

same mental facts could be entailed by different physical facts, there is still a limitation on the

physical facts that could entail these mental facts. There is a reason why physical fact x entails

mental fact y, and not mental fact z. If the way the world is determines the way the mind is,

then there is an explanation for why our mind is the way it is that would depend for its

Page 119: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

119

explanatory power on the world being a certain way. If we could determine what the

constraints are for the sorts of world that could produce the minds we in fact have, then we can

know, on the basis of how our minds are, how the world is.

Perhaps a successful transcendental argument will deliver a range of different things

that might entail the actual mental facts, but it will be a limited range. A range determined by

the way the non-mental world must be, if the mental aspects of the world are such and such. If

the sort of supervenience physicalism I have described is plausible, then it is plausible to

suppose that the range of ways the world must be will include worlds where the extra-mental

exists. And if we are in such a world, it seems unlikely that the same sort of mind could be

produced by a world so different that it had no extra-mental entities. So it seems likely that the

sort of explanation for why our minds are as they are will be such as to exclude the non-

existence of the extra-mental, if we do exist in the sort of world the supervenience physicalist

describes. Hence, it is reasonable that people in such a world might be able to give some

strong transcendental argument for thinking that they are in the sort of world they are in fact

in. And, given that supervenience physicalism is plausible, it is plausible that we may be able

to find just such an argument

ourselves.

4.14 Conclusion

This, then, is how I cash out the relationship between mind and world such that it is not

implausible that there could be entailment relations between premises concerning the mind

and a conclusion concerning the extra-mental world. It is a monist, physicalist picture. The

physicalist picture so defined is not one rigidly specified a priori, but I hope to have shown

that physicalism does not need any such problematic conception to be intelligible. It is a

supervenience physicalist view in which the way in which the physical determines the mental

is via entry by entailment. Mental facts are entailed by physical facts such that a full

description of the physical facts would entail the mental facts. In a sense, there would be

nothing over and above the physical, but we can explain the ways in which we categorise facts

in relation to their explanatory efficiency and predictive effectiveness. Supervenience

physicalism is plausible. The sceptic is not in a position to insist upon an alternate picture of

the relation between the mind and the extra-mental world that would make reasoning in this

Page 120: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

120

manner implausible. Given this, it is reasonable to suppose that some strong transcendental

argument will be possible.

Page 121: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

121

Chapter 5: Metaphysical Necessity and the Laws of Nature

I have argued that a strong transcendental argument is needed to answer the sceptical doubt

that worries me. I have answered the criticisms from those who do not think such an argument

is even possible, and I have shown that there are some candidates to supply the first premise of

such an argument: mental premises not open to doubt by my sceptic.

Stroud‘s complaint was that strong transcendental arguments need to, but cannot,

provide a bridge from a premise concerning the mind to a conclusion concerning the world. I

have argued that no mind-world bridge is required, as there is no chasm—there is only one

world, sorted by interacting categories. Nevertheless, I must show how a premise concerning

the mental can give us a conclusion concerning the extra-mental. My sceptic will not be

satisfied with an answer that merely shows that such a picture of the world is coherent or

consistent with the evidence available to me from the first-personal perspective. I must show

how it could be demonstrated that such first-personal evidence would not be possible were the

extra-mental world not a certain way.

It will be my purpose in this chapter to argue that what is needed for an STA to

succeed against this sceptic is a metaphysically necessary psychophysical conditional that

posits a natural law. As any such conditional will be highly contentious, I shall need to not

only defend the possibility of giving such a conditional, but also how it could be that my

sceptic could ever acquiesce to such a premise. I do so by arguing that all natural laws are

metaphysically necessary, and that therefore whatever law governs the causation of the mental

states that sceptic prizes as known is the only possible law there could be. Therefore, it is not

possible that (as is the sceptic‘s contention) a sceptical hypothesis could equally well explain

these items of thought or experience. In which case, what the sceptic‘s claim amounts to is not

sufficient to justify the belief that such a proposition cannot be known. It merely reflects the

fact that science is not yet complete—a far less worrying prospect.

This is a substantive claim in support of scientific realism, but not, I shall show, an

unreasonable one. I start by arguing for the nature of this premise.

Page 122: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

122

5.1 The Second Premise

The second premise will need to be known independently of empirical evidence. What does

this mean? Primarily, it means it must be something that the sceptic would agree to, given her

concerns that I might have all the mental life I now have in the absence of anything extra-

mental. In this sense, ‗empirical‘ is understood not in the vague sense of being any kind of

evidence delivered via the senses—after all, it is my hope to show that many of our qualitative

experiences are ‗delivered‘ to us via a causal chain that starts with something extra-mental and

ends with a qualitative mental experience, via the extra-mental object‘s interaction with the

senses. The point is that I must avoid assuming such a causal chain, for if such a chain can be

assumed, then the purpose of giving a transcendental argument will be void, just as Stroud

argued.

Beyond that, it must be a conditional which states that if what the sceptic concedes

about the mental is true, then something concerning the extra mental must be true. In short,

what we are looking for is a psychophysical law—one that posits a law-like relation between

the mental and the extra-mental. My arguments of chapter four show that it is plausible that

there should be such law-like relations. Given that the premise is not supposed to contain

anything the sceptic does not concede to be directly knowable, this prima facie seems to be

something of a tall order. The sceptic will say that no such law-like relation can be known a

priori, and so no such premise is admissible to any counter-argument against her sceptical

doubts. It was for precisely this reason that Stroud supposed that some further premise would

be needed to explain how one could move from the mental to the extra mental.

It shall be the work of the remainder of this chapter to support the inclusion of such a

premise in a strong transcendental argument, showing that such a move can be made

consistent with the restrictions placed upon what can be directly knowable by the sceptic.

Showing that the content of the argument can all be known from the sceptic‘s position will

demonstrate that no naturalistic premise is needed to act as a bridge, as there will be no gap to

bridge. This defence will need to show that a psychophysical law can be metaphysically

necessary, such that there will be no worlds at which the antecedent (which the sceptic

concedes) is true but the consequent (which the sceptic doubts) is false. As such, I will need to

provide an account of why a law of this kind should be regarded as metaphysically necessary,

where it is often supposed that all natural laws are contingent.

Page 123: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

123

5.2 Laws of Nature and the Humean Dictum

One‘s position on necessity and its relation to the laws of nature will depend on one‘s position

as regards the Humean thesis that there is ‗There is no object, which implies the existence of

any other if we consider these objects in themselves‘ (Hume 1739: 1.3.6.1) and ‗no objects

have any discoverable connexion together‘ (Hume 1748: 1.10). This thought is often

expressed as there being: ‗no necessary connection between distinct existents‘50

. Hume is

traditionally taken to be arguing for this in both A Treatise of Human Nature and in An

Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. The object of his critique is causation: that we

can find no necessary connection between a cause and its effect, whether considered as events

or as the objects that are commonly thought to be related such that the presence of one brings

about the other or changes the other. Hume makes the case that neither relations of ideas nor

the evidence of sensory experience can reveal a necessary connection between cause and

effect, merely a ‗constant and regular conjunction‘ (ibid.) of the one event with the other.

It is in relation to this that he defines the laws of nature as being those for which our

assurance is of the ‗highest certainty‘ in virtue of the cause and effect ‗in all countries and all

ages, to have been constantly conjoined‘, and as being ‗a firm and unalterable experience… a

uniform experience [that] amounts to a proof‘ (Hume 1748: 10.12). Hume‘s thinking is that

we may place weighty trust in the laws of nature not because we have a proof in the modern

sense (of a deductively valid argument) that the laws of nature must hold necessarily, but

because all experience has shown that event A has always been followed by event B, and that

this is the most complete evidence we can hope for on the matter.

This is not a level of ‗certainty‘ that will satisfy my sceptic. Hume‘s contentment to

define the laws of nature with reference merely to constant and regular conjunction, in the

absence of necessary connection, offers no guarantee that cause will follow effect in the future

50 It should be noted that the interpretation of Hume as sceptical of causation involving a necessary connection

has been under debate. See, The New Hume Debate: Revised Edition, Read and Richman (2007). Some

philosophers, such as Galen Strawson, argue that Hume ‗believes in causal power, or ―natural necessity‖, or

―Causation‖‘ (Strawson 2007: 31). Others, such as Read (2007) and Jacobson (2007), take Hume to adopt such

positions for the sake of dialectical analysis without necessarily endorsing them. I take no bone in this particular

debate. For me, the important thing is the impact that the traditional reading of Hume has had upon our general

discussion of necessity, causation, and the laws of nature. The interpretation of Hume given here may thus be

read as ‗the traditional Hume‘.

Page 124: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

124

of this world, let alone for any other possible world, or for any possible world that may

(unbeknownst to us) be the actual world. It would therefore seem that any attempt to run a

strong transcendental argument incorporating metaphysical necessity between distinct

existents (as I have argued that any successful transcendental argument must do) will have to

be anti-Humean with regard to the laws of nature.

This is not that surprising. After all, Kant attributed his ‗Copernican turn‘ to being

inspired by, and reacting to, Hume‘s work on causation. Hume‘s argument was that necessary

connections could only be established via a priori reasoning, for:

When we look about us towards external objects, and consider the operation of causes,

we are never able, in a single instance, to discover any power or necessary connexion;

any quality, which binds the effect to the cause, and renders the one an infallible

consequence of the other. We only find, that the one does actually, in fact, follow the

other. (Hume, 1748: 7.6)

Hume‘s point is that there is nothing in the content of experience that could count as evidence

for a necessary connection—all that is present in experience is the experience of one event,

followed by another:

In reality, there is no part of matter, that does ever, by its sensible qualities, discover

any power or energy, or give us ground to imagine, that it could produce any thing, or

be followed by any other object, which we could denominate its effect… [T]he power

or force, which actuates the whole machine, is entirely concealed from us, and never

discovers itself in any of the sensible qualities of body. (Hume 1748: 7.8)

So, necessary connection is not to be found in those qualities of an object, or the conjunction

of objects, that can be sensed. It is equally, Hume argues, to not be found in the relations of

ideas (the analytic a priori). These are ‗either intuitively or demonstratively certain‘ (Hume

1748: 4.1). The intuitively certain are known because their contrary cannot be conceived (in

contrast to matters of fact/empirical knowledge). Hume argues (1748: 4.9–13) that because we

cannot predict what an entirely novel object (or event) will do on first encountering it—both

some possible action, and another that completely contradicts it, are conceivable—any truth

about how the object will react in conjunction with another must be due to its being a matter of

fact, and not a relation of ideas: ‗For the effect is totally different from the cause, and

consequently can never be discovered in it‘ (Hume 1748: 4.10). Given that no evidence of

Page 125: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

125

necessary connection is available in the empirical evidence that we have for matters of fact,

Hume can only conclude that:

[A]s we can have no idea of any thing, which never appeared to our outward sense or

inward sentiment, the necessary conclusion seems to be, that we have no idea of

connexion or power at all, and that these words are absolutely without any meaning.

(Hume 1748: 4.7)

Which is not strictly to say that no necessary connection exists, but rather that if it does, it is

not discoverable to our limited faculties of ‗outward sense or inward sentiment‘ (Hume 1748:

7.26). This, at first glance anyway, is all the sceptic needs. It is this epistemic constraint—that

any necessary connection must be discoverable on first encounter—that I reject.

Kant‘s transcendentalism (as outlined in chapter two) was designed to offer a third

alternative to the failed analytic a priori attempts and synthetic a posteriori attempts of Hume:

the synthetic a priori. It may, therefore, seem unsurprising that a strong transcendental

argument would also be underpinned by a rejection of Hume‘s dictum concerning necessary

connections between distinct existents (or the lack thereof). However, there are key

differences. Kant‘s answer to how there could be a synthetic a priori was to propose a

metaphysics in which the mind is directly involved in shaping the phenomenal realm, in which

space and time operate not as independently existing dimensions, but rather as forms that must

be imposed upon the manifold of intuitions in order for our human minds to make sense of

them. Kant does not extend the a priori knowledge he thinks we may have of ‗synthetic‘

matters to things as they are in themselves.

Our sceptic is unhappy with Kant on two fronts. Firstly, she finds the idea that we

cannot know anything about the existence of things as they are in themselves worrying. To

simply tell her that she should stop worrying because they definitively cannot be known will

be read as merely conceding her worst case scenario. Secondly, the idea that space and time

and the objects located within them are ‗merely‘ phenomenal objects, shaped themselves by

our minds, she finds deeply disturbing. It is her worry that we cannot know whether such is

the case, as opposed to the common belief in mind-independent objects, that motivates the

compulsion I have argued that many of us find to desire an answer opposed to this. The strong

transcendental theorist, in turn, finds these thoughts similarly disquieting, but asserts that we

can fend off the sceptic without resorting to transcendental idealism.

Page 126: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

126

As we discussed in chapter two, some philosophers, such as Strawson, have tried to

use Kantian arguments for the synthetic a priori in a way that avoids idealism. However, I

have argued that these arguments fall short of any goal that would satisfy my sceptic, being

placed to offer a weak transcendental argument at best. Which, given our concerns, is rather

more worrying than less.

Therefore, if there is a proposition known synthetic a priori suited to play a role in a

strong transcendental argument against my sceptic, it cannot be the synthetic a priori of Kant.

Either some new form of synthetic a priori must be proposed, or the strong transcendental

theorist must draw on something else all together.

5.3 Necessity, Analyticity, and the A Posteriori

Hume supposed that only analytic truths could be known a priori and only synthetic truths a

posteriori. Kant proposed a third option: the synthetic a priori. Saul Kripke moved further on

and has argued for a separation of necessity not only from analyticity, but from the a priori as

well (see Kripke 1981, especially 122–6); whilst Hilary Putnam has provided reason to think

that there might be an analytic a posteriori (see Putnam 1975 and 1981).

Kripke‘s thought was that for natural kinds, such as gold, there are a certain set of

properties for which, were they not possessed by an object, the object would not be of that

specific kind: ‗Any world in which we imagine a substance which does not have these

properties is a world in which we imagine a substance which is not gold‘ (Kripke 1981: 125).

Therefore, in terms of necessity:

[T]o the extent that such properties follow from the atomic structure of gold, they are

necessary properties of it, even though they unquestioningly are not part of the

meaning of ‗gold‘ and therefore not known with a priori certainty. (ibid.)

Kripke assumes that the analytic must be a priori, ‗such statements are not known a priori,

and hence not analytic‘ (Kripke 1981: 122) although he concedes: ‗If statements whose a

priori truth is known via fixing the reference are counted as analytic, then some analytic truths

are contingent‘. Kripke argues that natural kind terms have their reference fixed by rigid

designation, rather than definite description. As a community, we have agreed that, whatever

that kind of stuff is, all things that share the essential properties of that stuff will be gold; as

Page 127: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

127

opposed to a definite description, such as ‗gold is a yellow metal‘ (being yellow has turned out

not to be an essential property of gold, there are other metals that are yellow). Kripke is

hesitant to commit to contingent analyticity on this basis as he is distinguishing between

reference and sense (see Kripke 1981: 122–3, n. 63).

Putnam does not share Kripke‘s reticence. Rather, he argues for a ‗semantic

externalist‘ theory of meaning, which contends that (at least some) meaning is not ‗in the

head‘. Putnam proposes a thought experiment in which there is a twin of our Earth where

everything is exactly the same, except that the clear liquid that runs out of taps and down

rivers and fills the oceans and freezes at zero degrees centigrade at sea level and which is

called ‗water‘ by the people of Twin Earth is not H2O, but rather, XYZ. This shows that

meaning relies on external factors in that it seems intuitive to say that if I were transported to

Twin Earth and were introduced to the stuff they call ‗water‘ and I called it water, believing

that it was the same stuff as in my world (the stuff with the chemical composition H2O), I

would be mistaken. Because my use of the word is determined in relation to the sample with

which my reference to water was fixed and relative to the community of language users with

whom I grew up, learning to mean by ‗water‘ whatever it was that we, collectively,

desognated water.

This observation is interesting for our discussion because it means that the proposition

‗Water is H2O‘ is analytic, given Putnam‘s semantic externalism about meaning. It is part of

the meaning of the word ‗water‘ that it is ‗H2O‘, but, crucially, we could not have known this

a priori. We had to encounter water and conduct empirical investigations of it in order to

discover its chemical structure. Once we know that water is H2O we can know that water is

not XYZ, simply because XYZ is not H2O—it is analytic. But we would still need to conduct

an empirical investigation to discover that the stuff that the Twin Earthers drink is not the

same as what we call ‗water‘, because we simply cannot know the full meaning of the term a

priori.

Putnam does offer a transcendental argument against a certain form of scepticism:

brain-in-a-vat scepticism. This is sadly not of use for my purposes for a number of reasons: a)

Putnam‘s argument is targeted at a form of scepticism that does not doubt the existence of an

extra-mental world, it presupposes a physical brain and external influences upon one‘s

Page 128: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

128

perceptions; b) it is only effective against the recently envatted anyway51

; c) it only rules out a

scepticism of the kind that we can talk about, and not a state of reality like that of being a

brain-in-a-vat that we are unable to talk about, which in many ways is a more worrying

possibility52

(this is similar to the criticism of weak transcendental arguments offered in

chapter two); d) this reflects a general problem with transcendental arguments based on

semantic externalism, which limits them to weak transcendental arguments, i.e. they can only

entail what we are able to think or talk about, not what exists independently of us.

I therefore do not find fruit in Putnum‘s own style of transcendental argument.

However, the discussion of natural kinds in Kripke and Putnam opens other avenues of

thought.

5.4 Dispositional Essentialism and Scientific Realism

Reasoning along Kripkean and Putnumian lines has led some philosophers to think of natural

kinds as dispositionally essentialist. Brian Ellis, for instance, derives his ‗physical realism‘

from what he terms the ‗new essentialism‘(see Ellis 2006), by which he means the kind of

essentialism exhibited by Kripke, Putnam, and the like—which is to say that natural kinds

have an ‗essence‘ that remains constant across possible worlds. Ellis believes that

incorporation of new essentialism into scientific realism will allow us to avoid certain

problems he finds in the programme of scientific realism explored by philosophers such as

Stathis Psillos (see Psillos 1999).

In this section I will briefly articulate the scientific realist thesis, differentiate the

programme of scientific realism that Ellis is reacting to, articulate Ellis‘s physical realism and

the dispositional essentialism it incorporates, and explore how far this can help us towards our

purpose.

Finding an agreed definition of scientific realism is fraught, as noted by Anjan

Chakravartty: ‗It is perhaps only a slight exaggeration to say that scientific realism is

51 If someone wishes to argue that it applies to other brain-in-a-vat scenarios I wish them luck, but I take this

claim as relatively uncontroversial and it is not necessary for my thesis to defend this.

52 See Crispin Wright‘s arguments in Wright (1992).

Page 129: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

129

characterized differently by every author who discusses it‘ (Chakravartty 2011: 1.1). Psillos

(2006) identifies three theses:

The Metaphysical Thesis: The world has a definite and mind-independent structure.

The Semantic Thesis: Scientific theories should be taken at face value.

The Epistemic Thesis: Mature and predictably successful scientific theories are

(approximately) true of the world. The entities posited by them, or, at any rate, entities

very similar to those posited, inhabit the world. (Psillos 2006: 14)

The ‗epistemic‘ thesis reads rather confusingly metaphysical—surely an epistemic thesis

should concern itself with what we should believe there is or what we can know that there is,

rather than what entities inhabit the world. We can interpret it as epistemic in the sense that it

provides criteria for assessing truth—the success of predictions based on scientific theories.

The ‗metaphysical‘ thesis, on the other hand, seems much too vague. Surely many

theses about the structure of reality can be said to posit a mind-independent structure without

thereby being scientific in any special sense. Yet, Psillos is keen to distance his understanding

of scientific realism from any ‗deep metaphysical commitments‘—particularly physicalism

and non-Humean metaphysics (ibid.), so the minimal nature of what he takes to be the

metaphysical commitment of scientific realism should not surprise us.

Ellis, by contrast, takes the metaphysical aspect of scientific realism as central—‗It

is… a primarily metaphysical thesis‘ (Ellis 2006: 1). What, then, is the primarily metaphysical

thesis Ellis takes himself to share with Psillos and the other scientific realists with whom he

differs on methodology? I take it to be the ‗reality of the things and processes‘ described by

the ‗dominant theories of science‘—which is what Ellis takes to be the conclusion of the

Psillosian argument, though he holds the argument itself to be flawed (ibid.). This also fits

roughly with a combination of the theses Psillos identifies as the metaphysical and epistemic

aspects of scientific realism.

The programme of scientific realism that Ellis is reacting to, then, is one that privileges

the semantic thesis that scientific theories should be taken at face value. This programme is

understood as one that asserts that scientific theories are propositions made true by entities

matching a literal reading of those theories (see Psillos 2006: 30). Ellis‘s concern is that

asserting the truth of a literal reading of empirically successful scientific theories is

insufficiently discriminating with regard to the type of entities asserted to exist. The Psillosian

Page 130: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

130

programme of scientific realism argues from empirical success to the truth of the dominant

theories of science—the reality of those theories—and Ellis finds this flawed as there is no

‗adequate theory of truth to carry the metaphysical burden‘ (Ellis 2006: 1). Ellis‘s problem is

that the empirical success of individual theories cannot distinguish between real objects,

events, and processes, and useful fictions— theoretical entities such as the Platonic objects of

maths and geometry, idealised objects of model theories, Newtonian extrinsic forces. Nor can

it distinguish between fundamental laws and those which can be eliminated.

Instead, Ellis argues in favour of what he calls ‗physical realism‘. He posits a global

approach in which physical things are the only real things, but such things are categorised via

a hierarchical structure of natural kinds of objects/substances and events/processes. These

kinds ‗all have intrinsic physical properties in virtue of which they are things of the kinds they

are‘ (Ellis 2006: 5). This is the sense in which physical realism is dispositionally essentialist—

natural kinds are distinguished by virtue of intrinsic (essential) physical properties. The

properties essential to these kinds must include causal powers, rejecting the Humean picture of

logically independent events (see Ellis 2006: 5–6). It is the interconnectedness of theories,

kinds defined by their essential causal powers, that allows for an explanation of the ontology

of the scientific image. Theories are not addressed one by one, but compared with reference to

their cohesiveness and usefulness to the whole.

For example, Carnot‘s model of the heat engine is an ideal that could not exist in

reality, as it abstracts away from causes of inefficiency, such as friction; yet Ellis notes that

‗Carnot‘s theory is still the fundamental one in the area‘ (Ellis 2006: 7–8). Carnot‘s model of a

heat engine is empirically successful, but its abstraction away from the limitations of reality

provides good motivation for saying that it is not real—there are no actual Carnot engines.

The onotological distinction between theoretical and physical entities is not one that Psillosian

scientific realism is equipped to deal with. Yet it is a distinction worth preserving. The

scientific image as a whole—as described by multiple, interlocked, successful theories—

should be able to account for both the usefulness of the model and the fact that the real world

(which reflects the existence of friction and other inefficiencies) does not include Carnot

engines.

Similarly, Ellis notes that ‗Newtonian forces are always eliminable from physics‘ in

that, theoretically, ‗We need only combine the laws of their production with those of their

combination and action to obtain laws of distribution of their effects‘ (ibid.). Yet the

Page 131: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

131

postulation of Newtonian forces is empirically successful, as in practice it will not always be

possible to calculate effects based on constituent laws (due to the complexity of the factors

involved).

This is the advantage presented by Ellis‘s global approach. Physical things are the only real

things—the things whose intrinsic properties and essential causal relations can explain all real

things—but an approach that incorporates a hierarchical structure of natural kinds can explain

theoretical objects/events/processes in terms of supervenience. In this sense, Newtonian forces

are less real because they are eliminable—the laws that incorporate them supervene on other

laws which concern physical objects directly—but we may understand their role in successful

scientific theories as a shorthand for laws whose application may be too complex for us to

account for in practice. Similarly, although there may be, in reality, no Carnot machines, we

can again account for the usefulness of their supposition by seeing facts concerning these

machines as an extension of facts concerning less ideal machines in the world, and use that

supposition to discern facts about the real world machines as an extension of principles

concerning the ideal. The derivative nature of their reality—their supervenience on and

extension from physical facts—explains ontological distinctions that are valuable, and which

could not be accounted for by Psillosian scientific realism53

.

Ellis‘s hierarchical picture of categorically distinct kinds with interacting causal

powers, each a part of a global metaphysical picture, is very appealing. It closely fits my

supervenience physicalist picture in which categories overlap and affect one another, but

where categories can still be sorted hierarchically, with some (physical properties) being more

‗basic‘ than others, as they are those upon which other properties supervene.

Ellis even offers something that could be developed as a transcendental argument:

The emergence of this scientific image of the world really has only one plausible

explanation, viz. that the world is, in reality, structured more or less as it appears to be,

and, consequently, that the kinds distinguished in it… are natural kinds of one sort or

another, and that the causal powers they appear to have are genuine… The image is

clearly a human construct. But it is a stable and revealing image… that seems to be

indispensible. (Ellis, 2006: 12-13)

53 Psillos argues that they can be accounted for, of course, and the debate between Psillos and Ellis is interesting.

However, for my purposes it is sufficient merely to understand the motivation for Ellis‘s position, not to defend

all the arguments in its favour.

Page 132: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

132

Construed transcendentally, the argument goes like this. The scientific image is indispensible

to our understanding of the world. We do act successfully upon this image of the world. The

only plausible explanation of this is that the world is really structured more or less as it

appears to be, incorporating natural kinds with the genuine causal powers they seem to have.

Therefore, an adequate account of the scientific image we do in fact have is only possible if

the world is much as it appears to be.

Unfortunately for my purposes, this simply is not enough. It will not satisfy my

sceptic. The whole structure is built on empirical knowledge. Perhaps the scientific image of

the world is indispensible once we begin to conduct empirical investigations of the world, but

my sceptic does not trust us to carry out those empirical investigations for any meaningful

result.

Moreover, even if one could argue for the indispensability of the picture, one should pause

over the fact that Ellis calls the image a ‗human construct‘. I find his terms ambiguous; the

scientific image is ‗a stable and revealing image… that seems to be indispensible‘. ‗Revealing‘

might be intended to indicate revealing of reality, but it is not obvious that this follows. The

image ‗seems indispensible‘, but if it is a human construct, how do we know it is not merely

indispensible to humans? It might be merely that we must believe in such a construct, but then

this would be a weak transcendental argument, and open to the criticisms we made before—

that it is rather more disturbing than less if some beliefs might be ‗indispensible‘ to us,

regardless of whether they are actually true.

Here, we run up against the differences of aim between Ellis‘s work and mine. Ellis

states clearly: ‗I shall propose no concept of truth other than that of epistemic rightness‘

understood as: ‗[in assessing] whether a proposition is true or not, we have only to consider

whether the grounds for claiming it to be true are sufficient to justify the claim‘ (Ellis 2006: 1–

2). Epistemic rightness is ‗metaphysically neutral‘, and justification is relative to the type of

proposition in question. An empirical proposition, he maintains, can be decided on the basis of

empirical evidence. But our sceptic is explicitly unhappy with that. The very validity of

empirical evidence is what is in dispute.

This, in the end, will always be the problem of any appeal to the necessary or analytic

a posteriori: it will always be knowable only after empirical investigation, and therefore

cannot be of use to the strong transcendental theorist in her bid to defy Hume‘s dictum.

Page 133: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

133

However, I think there is another way.

5.5 Laws and properties

In his book, Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties, Alexander Bird defends a position in

which natural laws are metaphysically necessary by virtue of the fact that they supervene on

‗potencies‘—dispositionally essentialist properties. In this section I will outline the

relationship between the nature of laws and the nature of properties articulated by Bird. I

consider some reasons to think that Bird has oversimplified this relationship by examining the

relationship between properties and laws articulated by Ellis. Nevertheless, I support the

weaker claim that where at least some properties are dispositionally essentialist there will also

be at least some metaphysically necessary natural laws.

Bird (2007: 1–2) outlines three broad camps in the literature regarding natural laws:

1. the regularity view54

2. the nomic necessitation view55

3. the dispositional essentialist view56

The regularity view takes a (traditional) Humean position in which laws are merely

regularities in the relations of things and their properties: ‗laws are regularities that fit into or

may be derived from the optimal systematization of the facts concerning individual things‘

(Bird 2007: 1). In this sense, the regularity view represents a kind of supervenience: ‗laws

depend on the pattern of their instances and other matters of particular fact (things possessing

properties)‘ (ibid.); however, this Humean supervenience is of no use to me. There is nothing

about the supervenience of these laws on the facts of the world that guarantees the continued

operation of these regularities, or any necessity relation that allows us to deduce the presence

of B from the presence of A. On this view, a law does not even tell us that any regularity

which can be found between a mental truth and the truth of an extra-mental proposition must

continue to hold, merely that it has done in the past. The idea that one might reason from the

plausibility of some world where this happens to any other world, let alone all worlds in which

54 Attributed to Lewis (1973), although Bird notes an origin in Mill and Ramsay.

55 Attributed to Armstrong (1983), Tooley (1977), and Dretske (1977).

56 Origins attributed to Shoemaker (1984), developed by Swoyer (1982), Ellis (2001, 2002).

Page 134: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

134

the mental truth holds, would simply not be possible to substantiate. Moreover, such

regularities can only be known of via empirical investigation—investigation that relies on

sensory information about the extra-mental world, which is precisely what is in doubt. Clearly,

this understanding of natural laws is of no use to me.

The nomic necessitation view ascribes to natural laws a kind of law-like nature that is

more than mere regularity, but which acts only within a possible world. This lack of cross-

world, robust, metaphysical necessity will again not be satisfactory to our purposes. If natural

laws do not hold across possible worlds, and if I do not know whether I am in a world in

which an extra-mental fact, E, is nomically necessary if a mental fact, M, holds, then I cannot

defend any premise to the effect of ‗If M, then E‘ without first knowing precisely that which

the sceptic doubts: that I am not in a possible world for which there are no extra-mental facts,

E.

The third option, dispositional essentialism, holds that laws are robust metaphysical

relations such that, at any possible world, ‗If A, then B‘57

holds by virtue of the nature of the

properties A and B. Rather than laws imposing an order on properties, laws arise from the

properties. This is exactly what we want—a theory that can explain why possession of mental

property M necessitates the instantiation of property E, and which entails that it is true at all

possible worlds that where M, necessarily E.

What theory of natural laws one ascribes to is linked to one‘s view of properties. Bird

distinguishes three options here, also:

a) categoricalism

b) the mixed view

c) dispositional essentialism

Categoricalism is the view that properties are not distinguishable by any features that belong

to them; rather they are distinguished by how laws relate them to other properties. Property A

is thus only different to property B in virtue of the different ways it relates to other properties.

Dispositional essentialism is the view that properties are distinguished by virtue of their

potencies—i.e. qualities of the property such that it affects and responds to other properties in

specific ways. As this is definitional for what it is to be that property, the relations for that

57 It should be noted that this is a rough, provisional statement of the relations. Counter-examples from the

literature (known as ‗finks‘ and ‗antidotes‘) will force a clarification.

Page 135: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

135

property will hold at all possible worlds. Between these two poles is the ‗mixed view‘, which

holds that some properties are ‗potencies‘, distinguished via innate relations, whilst other

properties are ‗bare‘—distinguished only by their relations to other properties.

The Humean ‗regularity‘ view of laws is contingent in its account of laws and

categorical in its view of properties. Bird‘s dispositional essentialism incorporates both a

metaphysical necessity view of laws and a potency, non-categorical, view of properties. Bird

aligns the mixed view to contingent (nomic) necessitation.

It is not clear from the literature that all positions divide up this neatly—regularity

view of laws with categoricalism and contingency, dispositional essentialism with potencies

and metaphysically necessary laws, nomic necessitation with the mixed view. To gain clarity,

it helps to distinguish the metaphysical from the epistemic issues.

Ellis‘s view, grounded in the ‗new essentialism‘, is surely dispositionally essentialist—

as Bird himself notes. Ellis‘s talk of the ‗causal powers‘ of ‗natural kinds‘ seems very much to

be what Bird means by ‗potencies‘ (see, e.g. Ellis 2006, 12–13, quoted above), and Ellis aims

at a ‗metaphysical thesis‘ (Ellis 2006: 1). However, Psillos (2006: 16) is surely right to point

out that Ellis‘s arguments turn on the explanatory power of physical realism, and that in

presupposing ‗no concept of truth other than epistemic rightness‘ (Ellis 2006: 1, emphasis

mine) it is difficult for Ellis to get out the metaphysical conclusions that he desires. He

describes the scientific (physicalist) image as ‗stable and revealing‘, and therefore

‗indispensible‘. I suspect an equivocation over the term ‗revealing‘, between metaphysical and

epistemic senses. One might interpret ‗revealing‘ as ‗revealing of the nature of the world‘, or

one may see Ellis‘s arguments merely supporting that the stability of the image is revealing

about ourselves. It may be, as Psillos suggests, a purely epistemic enterprise, one which

reveals something about what we must believe, but not about what is. This might be seen to fit

better with Ellis‘s concept of truth being epistemic rightness—it is what we need to believe,

not necessarily what is.

Given this, I am not sure that Ellis‘s philosophy supports a metaphysically necessary

view of the laws of nature. Epistemic nomic necessity seems a better fit—the laws of the

scientific image are indispensible to our understanding of this world we do in fact experience,

but no argument has been given to extend this to the world as it really is, let alone that it is

indispensible to how all possible worlds are.

Page 136: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

136

The key point to take away from this, however, is not that Bird is wrong to suppose

that there is a link between the dispositional essentialist view of properties and the view that

the laws of nature are metaphysically necessary. Rather, some further argument is required to

establish this; either dispositional essentialism must be augmented with some other claim, or

further argument must be made to show that a dispositionally essentialist position entails

metaphysical necessity for the laws of nature. Ellis does not need to make this claim. We may

read him as epistemically dispositionally essentialist, in the sense that our best beliefs tested

against best fit with what can be said to be known support a belief in dispositional

essentialism. This could be seen as falling short of the metaphysical claim that natural

properties are non-categorical potencies—it is reasonable to believe that or say that it suffices

for knowledge in ordinary contexts, but the defeasibility of his position cannot substantiate

metaphysical necessity58

.

What makes Bird‘s move interesting is his tying of epistemic dispositional essentialism

to the metaphysical dispositionally essentialist view that properties are potencies. It is this, and

his account of potencies, that he argues entails metaphysical necessity for the laws of nature.

He therefore must defend the (metaphysically dispositionally essentialist) potency view

against categoricalism, and the metaphysically necessary dispositional essentialist view of

laws against the regularity view and the nomic necessitation view.

I also need to argue for metaphysically necessary laws, and against categoricalism,

contingent laws, and contingent necessitation. I am not convinced that Bird‘s arguments

against the mixed view are as powerful as he needs them to be. However, it should be noted

that I do not need to defend what he calls ‗dispositional monism‘ (the thesis that all properties

are dispositionally essentialist potencies) over the mixed view. All I require is that we be able

to know that some properties are potencies whose relationships to one another are such that

where one is a mental fact that the sceptic accepts and one is an extra-mental fact that seems

58 Given that Ellis sees his thesis as a metaphysical one, it seems likely he would resist this interpretation. it is not

my purpose to give the ‗correct‘ understanding of Ellis‘s position. I merely want to show that we could do with a

more fine-grained account of dispositional essentialism and the relationship between one‘s view of properties and

one‘s view of laws. Given the plausibility of the interpretation outlined above, one can see that an epistemic

dispositionally essentialist view of properties is not necessarily committed to a metaphysically necessary

dispositional essentialist view of natural laws. What we need is a metaphysical dispositionally essentialist view of

properties.

Page 137: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

137

prima facie to be something the sceptic can reject, elucidation of such a relationship would

reveal that the presence of the mental property entails the presence of the extra-mental one.

With this in mind I will set aside Bird‘s discussion of the mixed view and focus on

defending his dispositional essentialist view of properties (for at least some properties) and

natural laws (for all fundamental natural laws). I shall first outline this position and examine

the criticisms against it. I will defend it against these. I will then examine the nomic

necessitarian view of laws and show that this is not appealing, and, further, that it is not

available to the sceptic. Lastly, I will consider categoricalism about properties and whether the

sceptic can use this, in combination with the regularity view of laws, as an alternate picture of

natural laws. I will conclude that she cannot.

5.6 Bird’s essentialism

Bird‘s argument for a dispositionally monist essentialism focuses on establishing essentialist

potencies for ‗fundamental natural properties … those with non-redundant causal powers‘

(Bird 2007: 13). In this section I will elucidate this definition.

I find some of these terms value-laden, but poorly defined in his text. ‗Natural‘

properties are defined largely by example. They are natural in the sense that it is the task of

scientists to discover them:

For example, a scientist may discover or synthesize a hitherto unknown molecule. It

would be natural to say that her next task is ‗to discover its properties‘. In that sense,

its properties do not include ‗the property of being first synthesized on a Wednesday‘

or ‗the property of being Φ‘ (where something is Φ iff it is a member of the set

{molecule m, the Eiffel tower, the power set of the natural numbers}). (Bird 2007: 9)

He also writes:

we may distinguish the liberal from the restricted use of ‗property‘ by referring to

‗abundant‘ and ‗sparse‘ properties. Or we may talk of ‗natural‘ properties to capture

the restricted sense. I shall use ‗sparse‘ and ‗natural‘ interchangeably. (ibid.)

Which is as much as to say that restricted properties are sparse properties and sparse properties

are natural properties, and liberal properties are abundant and non-natural. He also contrasts

Page 138: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

138

simplicity (associated with sparse-natural-restricted properties) with complexity (liberal-

abundant-non-natural). But defining these terms by reference to each other and to examples

does very little to explain what it is that makes these terms apply to some things and not

others.

However, I think this game of shifting definitions is best clarified when Bird turns to

talk of fundamental natural properties—which he defines as ‗those with non-redundant causal

powers‘ (2007:13)—and the role these have in explanations. He gives the example of the

property of being charged, and the property of being charged*. The property of being

charged* has the extension ‗all charged things except some particular future proton‘. It is a

complex/liberal/abundant/non-natural property in that it combines another property (being

charged) with something else (the exception of some future proton). To be charged is in this

sense fundamental: it is not made from the combination of other properties. ‗Charged‘ has

non-redundant causal powers in that its causal powers cannot be explained by anything else.

‗Charged*‘ does not have that advantage—its causal powers are derived from the causal

powers of ‗charged‘ in conjunction with the exception of ‗some future proton‘. Therefore, an

explanation of any event that called upon ‗charged*‘ would really be supervening on more

fundamental explanations drawn from the properties of which ‗charged*‘ is derived. Bird

argues that if ‗charged‘ and ‗charged*‘ were on an ontological par we could not explain why

one has explanatory value and the other does not. We should therefore accept that there is a

genuine ontological difference between natural properties with fundamental dispositions and

non-natural properties, with no genuine dispositions of their own.

Bird‘s purpose in this is to argue for the ontological robustness of natural/fundamental

properties. The ontological robustness of natural properties lies in their explanatory power,

and their explanatory power is founded upon their causal powers. As the explanatory power is

dependent upon the causal power, the causal powers cannot change from world to world, and

can be subject to metaphysically necessary laws.

I am not entirely convinced that the metaphysically necessary laws should not be extended to

cover derived laws. It seems to me that if the causal powers of non-natural properties are

derived from/supervene upon more fundamental causal powers they are not less causally or

explanatorily efficacious. It is true that they will be dependent for their existence upon natural

properties, but it will still be true that, due to their identification via causal powers, they

should hold from world to world. I am inclined to think that any property instantiated at some

Page 139: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

139

world, if it is to be explanatorily useful, will need to have consistent causal powers across

worlds if it is to be explanatorily effective.

However, I need not wrangle over this point. For my purposes it will be sufficient if

merely some properties have this sort of ontological robustness.

5.7 Dispositional Essentialism and Realism about Universals

Bird‘s argument in favour of dispositional essentialism has several stages. He starts by arguing

for realism about universals, which in this case is the thesis that universals are ontologically

distinct entities over and above the properties of individual particulars. This is opposed to the

nominalist thesis that resemblance alone suffices, without the supposition of anything over and

above particulars. The postulation of universals (or tropes) is not needed as the nominalist

asserts that some resemblances may be explained by reference to other resemblances, and

others are brute and fundamental and require no explanation. In this section I will examine the

debate between Bird and Rodriguez-Pereryra, who has been the most prominent proponent of

nominalism in recent times.

Bird‘s argument against resemblance nominalism is that, firstly, brute resemblance is

unsatisfactory, and secondly, resemblance itself, on this account, looks like a universal itself.

The first point focuses on the meaning of the term ‗resemblance‘. Bird resists the idea that

brute resemblance can provide a grounding for explanations of resemblance that may avoid

regress. He writes:

it is resemblance that needs explaining. When there is resemblance it is natural to want

to explain it, and to explain it in terms of something held in common. Explanations

may have to end somewhere, but ending in brute resemblance seems unsatisfactory.

(Bird 2007: 15)

I think we can understand this as saying that the challenge is not to explain individual

resemblances by reference to each other, and prevent this from becoming a regress by

postulating that some are brute. Rather, it is resemblance itself that requires explaining—what

it is for one thing to resemble another. Typically, this may be done by saying that for one thing

to resemble another is for the two things to have something in common, but then one may ask:

what is it to have something in common (if, that is, they do not share in a universal—an entity

Page 140: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

140

over and above particular properties of an object)? It is easy to see how this may generate a

regress of explanation (or a circular explanation—what it is for two objects to resemble one

another is for them to have something in common, and what it is for them to have something

in common is for them to resemble each other), and this regress is not one that may be solved

by supposing that some resemblances are brute. This is because the question is not why this

thing resembles another, but rather what it is for one thing to resemble another.

Rodriguez-Pereyra has responded to the criticism that ending in brute resemblance is

unsatisfactory, but his response misinterprets the nature of the criticism. He takes it as being

simply an intuition that ‗―a and b resemble each other‖ cannot be true merely in virtue of the

existence of a and b‘ (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2003: 229), but I do not think this gives sufficient

credit to the point Bird is making. Brute resemblance is not unsatisfactory for realists simply

because they ‗intuit‘ that it is wrong. Rather, it is unsatisfactory in that it is explanatorily

insufficient. Granted, the assertion that some resemblances are ‗brute‘ is meant to justify

acceptance that no explanation is required. However, where intuitions conflict, as where brute

resemblance seems plausible to some but not to others, other factors are considered for or

against the positions. Being explanatorily effective is a point in favour of universals.

Moreover, Rodriguez-Pereyra‘s response to this criticism is precisely to reject an intuitions

analysis in favour of a pros and cons comparison. He writes that he is not required to:

argue directly against the opposition, but to develop Resemblance Nominalism to the

point that all objections against it were properly met and answered (2002: 6). Once

Resemblance Nominalism had been developed to this point, I devoted the whole of

chapter 12 to explaining why Resemblance Nominalism was superior to theories

postulating universals and tropes. Basically Resemblance Nominalism‘s superiority

lies in that, unlike theories postulating universals or tropes, it does not postulate ad hoc

entities, i.e. entities the only or main reason to believe in which is that they solve a

certain theoretical problem, namely the so-called Problem of Universals. (Rodriguez-

Pereyra 2003: 231–2)59

59 This paper is in response to Bird‘s 2003 paper, which employs the same arguments as Bird‘s 2007. Bird‘s

original paper was in response to Rodriguez-Pereyra‘s 2002 book, Resemblance Nominalism, referenced within

this quotation—the book is his 2002a in my bibliography.

Page 141: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

141

The advantage Rodriguez-Pereyra sees in resemblance nominalism is that it postulates no ‗ad

hoc‘ entities, but if the alternative explanation is simply that there is no explanation, this

seems remarkably more ad hoc than to postulate entities that would provide an explanation.

Bird‘s second argument is drawn from Russell‘s regress of resemblance argument (see

Russell 2008: 65). This argument runs that if one takes three white objects, a, b, and c, the

nominalist will say that what they share is not the instantiation of the universal, whiteness, but

a resemblance. a resembles b, and b resembles c. Russell then notes that if it is the same

resemblance that is shared between a and b as that between b and c, then that shared

resemblance is a universal.

This argument has been disputed, in particular, by Rodriguez-Pereyra (2001: 397).

Rodriguez-Pereyra rightly points out that it is not obvious that what follows from Russell‘s

argument (as given at 2008: 65) is a regress, vicious or otherwise. Instead, he identifies two

points that can be drawn from Russell: 1. if Russell has shown that resemblance is a universal,

then it seems that resemblance has not helped us to avoid universals; and 2. it seems pointless

to deny other universals, like whiteness, if we have admitted to resemblance as a universal.

The regress comes in if we insist that the resemblance between a and b, and the resemblance

between b and c, are each, themselves, particulars. In this case, there would then need to be a

resemblance between these two resemblances, and a resemblance between the higher-level

resemblance and the original resemblances, and so on, generating the regress. (Russell

explores this in 1956: pp. 346–7)

Rodriguez-Pereyra responds to this by pointing out that the resemblance nominalist is

under no obligation to reify resemblances. They need ‗only suppose that particulars resemble

each other, not that there are any resemblances‘ (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2001: p. 401). If there are

no resemblances, there can be no regress of resemblances, merely finite particulars that

resemble each other.

This raises the problem of the ‗Many over One‘, or, as Rodriguez-Pereyra puts it,

‗―how can the same thing be of different types?‖‘ (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2002: 39), that is: what

does it mean to say that two particulars resemble each other? In order to resist the appeal to

universals, Rodriguez-Pereyra proposes that what accounts for this is not resemblances, but

resemblance facts, i.e. what makes ‗sentences like ―a and b resemble each other‖ true‘

(Rodriguez-Pereyra 2001: 401). The question then becomes: what makes it true that a and b

resemble each other? And his answer is simply ‗a and b together‘:

Page 142: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

142

If a and b resemble each other then they do so because of their being the entities they

are, and so a and b are the sole truthmakers of ‗a and b resemble each other‘. There is

then no need to postulate extra entities to account for facts of resemblance: the

resembling entities suffice to account for them. (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2001: 403)

This is a deeply unsatisfying answer for the realist—it seems to explain nothing at all. How

can ‗a and b together‘ be the truthmakers of ‗a and b resemble each other‘? How can their

mere existence entail resemblance?

To complete his answer and provide a full explanation, Rodriguez-Pereyra (see 2001:

403–5) must insist on realism about possible worlds, and Lewis‘s counterpart theory. On this

view the mere existence of a and b, being the particulars they are, entails ‗a and b resemble

each other‘ for the world in which a and b exist, because on this view of possible worlds, no

individual exists in more than one world—they merely have counterparts which differ from

them to varying degrees. Therefore, if a and b are resembling particulars, this is entailed by

them being the particulars they are in the world in which they exist. The truth of the one

proposition makes for the truth of the other.

This is an oddly unexplanatory sort of truthmaking. It reduces entailment, as Bird

(2001: 17) points out, to material implication. No true relationship is revealed as holding

between ‗a and b exist‘ and ‗a and b resemble each other‘, as is illustrated by the fact that for

each fact in any possible world, this theory will ensure that all the other true facts at that world

are entailed. To use Bird‘s example: ‗―David Beckham plays football‖ entails ―Snow is

white‖‘ (ibid.) in the same way that can ‗a and b exist‘ entails ‗a and b resemble each other‘,

and there is clearly no explanatory relation between David Beckham playing football and

snow being white.

For these reasons, Bird argues that at best this renders the concept of truthmaking

rather trivial, giving the necessary, but not sufficient, principle (T):

(T) If E1, ..., En, are joint truthmakers of ‗S‘ then ‗E1 exists & ... & En, exists‘ entails

‗S‘. (Bird 2003: 224)60

60 Rodriguez-Pereyra gives (T) as ‗(T**)‘, and seems rather put out that Bird made this change in nomenclature. I

hope he will forgive me for following Bird, I must confess that I find Bird‘s nomenclature easier to digest. See

Rodriguez-Pereyra (2003: 230, n. 1) for more on the fraught issue of changing nomenclature.

Page 143: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

143

(T) is not enough to support that a and b are truthmakers of ‗a resembles b‘. It would only

show that if they exist they are truthmakers for ‗a resembles b‘ in the sense that everything

else that exists at the world where ‗a resembles b‘ is true must exist in order for it to be true.

Counterpart theory is doing all the work, here. The more significant claim for the truthmaking

theory is what Bird calls ‗(Y)‘61

:

(Y) Entity E is a truthmaker of ‗S‘ if and only if E is an entity in virtue of which ‗S‘ is

true. (ibid.)

This, Bird criticises by saying that ‗in virtue of‘ is a ‗thick‘ concept, one which it is hard to

understand in a way that is more than the trivial entailment claim of (T) without cashing out in

terms of ‗a property that is shared by a and b, or their resembling one another‘ (Bird 2003:

225). If this is the case, it looks like we have come back to exactly what Russell was criticising

in the first place. Either E is a truthmaker of S because it instantiates some universal, or

because it involves ‗resemblance‘ in some sense that is circular, or leads to a regress, or that

renders ‗resemblance‘ a universal in itself.

Rodriguez-Pereyra does offer a reply to this argument (see Rodriguez-Pereyra 2003),

of which Bird‘s only comment is that he finds it ‗perplexing‘ (Bird 2007: 18, n. 13). The

challenge to fill out the thick concept of ‗in virtue of‘ is not met. Rodriguez-Pereyra maintains

that his defence of the entailment relation between can ‗a and b exist‘ and ‗a and b resemble

each other‘ was not intended as an argument for a and b being as a truthmakers of ‗a and b

resemble each other‘. He thinks it is enough to show that resemblance nominalism is internally

consistent and superior to realism in terms of answering the problem of universals. Given this,

he asks what candidates there could be for the truthmakers of ‗a and b resemble each other‘

except for a and b. ‗[T]he ontology of Resemblance Nominalism consists of particulars and

classes (sets)‘, but classes are merely sets of particulars, and the only particulars in virtue of

which a and b might resemble each other are a and b.

As an answer, this completely fails to address the issue of what ‗in virtue of‘ means

beyond the triviality of (T). No wonder Bird is perplexed. Overall, one rather feels that Bird

and Rodriguez-Pereyra perplex each other. I think what this comes down to is the pros and

61 What Rodriguez-Pereyra calls ‗(Tʹ)‘ (see his 2003: 230, n. 1).

Page 144: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

144

cons analysis Rodriguez-Pereyra describes in his 2003 (231–2). For Bird, the explanatory

value of the account is prized; for Rodriguez-Pereyra, avoiding what he regards of the

ontological extravagance of invoking universals in order to offer such an explanation.

Rodriguez-Pereyra thinks no deeper explanation is required; Bird does not think universals are

an ontological extravagance if they provide a deeper explanation. As such, they are at an

impasse.

I, like Bird, favour an account that allows for the deeper explanation, but if one is not

convinced by that, one might consider that if resemblance nominalism is required in order to

have an alternative to dispositional essentialism, and dispositional essentialism allows us to

construct a working strong transcendental argument, then it must count in the ‗cons‘ column

that resemblance nominalism opens the door to scepticism. By a similar token, whilst

nominalism might offer a way out for the sceptic who wishes to avoid dispositional

essentialism and a possible strong transcendental argument, the sceptic is thereby forced to

adopt and defend a specific philosophical position, which is a step away from her place as one

who merely prompts us to doubt. As a figure who tests the success of our theories, she would

count against the resemblance nominalist. As the intermittent doubt in one‘s own mind, she

would thereby only gain admittance if one accepted resemblance nominalism, and this serves

to greatly narrow her threat.

5.8 Dispositions

Having rejected resemblance nominalism, Bird then defends the realist analysis of properties

in terms of dispositions. This analysis is complicated by the fact that some property names

resist clear analysis in these terms. In this section I will consider the difference between

‗covert‘ property names and ‗overt‘ dispositional property descriptions. I will argue that the

existence of covert property names does not undermine the dispositions analysis overall; that

their covert nature is a reflection of the imprecision of natural language and not any deep truth

about the nature of properties. I will then give the traditional Conditional Analysis of

properties from which the account of natural laws will be developed.

‗Covert‘ property names are names such as ‗fragility‘, ‗brittleness‘, and ‗elasticity‘.

These covert property names align to covert dispositional predicates, such as: ‗fragile‘,

‗brittle‘, ‗elastic‘. These are ‗covert‘ in the sense that they do not explicitly give their stimuli

Page 145: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

145

and manifestations. ‗Overt‘ dispositional property descriptions overtly take the form ‗the

disposition to M when S‘ (where M is the manifestation and S the stimulus). Overt disposition

property descriptions then align to overt dispositional predicates of the form ‗is disposed to M

when S‘. Thus, fragility cannot be simplistically cashed out in a description because different

stimuli and manifestations may describe fragility in relation to context. The glass is fragile

because it is disposed to break when dropped, but the ancient document is fragile because it

may fragment on touch (see Bird 2007: 19–20).

One might be concerned that a lack of neat correspondence between covert disposition

names and overt disposition property descriptions (and their dispositional predicates) creates a

problem for dispositional analysis of properties. This is too quick a move. Fragility can be

cashed out relative to context—to what it is that makes the glass fragile or the ancient

document fragile. Language is not neat. Some terms may be applied to a number of similar,

but distinct things. Some may align more definitively—especially if the term was devised to

describe a specific phenomenon, as opposed to evolving through centuries of use. Bird (2007:

20) gives as an example: ‗inertial mass may perhaps be characterized as the disposition to

respond to the stimulus of a force by accelerating in proportion to that mass‘. What is

important, for my purposes, is that some dispositional properties can be characterised by overt

dispositional property descriptions and overt dispositional predicates such that they can be

expressed as:

x possesses the disposition to M when S iff x is disposed to M when S. (Bird 2007: 19)

Under the Conditional Analysis (CA) of dispositions, this can be rendered as:

x is disposed to manifest M in response to stimulus S iff were x to undergo S x would

yield manifestation M. (Bird 2007: 24)

I will now turn to the more serious challenge to CA, which are the proposed counter-examples

of ‗finks‘, ‗antidotes‘, and mimics.

Page 146: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

146

5.9 Finks, Antidotes, and Mimics

It has been pointed out that where dispositions take time to manifest following a stimulus, the

disposition may have time to go out of existence. Where this happens, the disposition is called

‗finkish‘62

:

an object‘s disposition is finkish when the object loses the disposition after the

occurrence of the stimulus but before the manifestation can occur and in such a way

that consequently that manifestation does not occur. (Bird 2007: 25)

Bird considers an example which is a variation of Charlie Martin‘s ‗electro-fink‘63

(Martin

1994: 2–3). Suppose a wire has the property of being live, defined by the dispositional

property description ‗disposed to conduct current when in contact with a conductor‘. Suppose

that the wire is attached to a machine called an ‗electro-fink‘, and this machine has a way of

detecting when the wire is in contact with a conductor and changing its disposition to be

‗dead‘ (i.e. disposed to not conduct current when in contact with a conductor) by cutting its

connection to a generator. The wire is live. It is disposed to conduct current when in contact

with a conductor. However, when it receives that stimulus (being in contact with a conductor)

it does not evince the manifestation CA suggests is a necessary part of having that disposition.

Surely, the objection goes, CA is false.

An antidote to a disposition is something that breaks the causal chain that leads from

the stimulus to the response. The obvious example of this would be an antidote to a poison:

Let us understand ‗fatally poisonous‘ to mean ‗disposed to kill if ingested‘. It is

possible to ingest a dose of a fatal poison yet survive if one has also taken an antidote.

(Bird 2007: 27)

62 The origin of the term ‗fink‘ is attributed to David Lewis, although the concept it describes seems to have been

first raised by Mark Johnston, in ‗Objectivity Refigured: Pragmatism Without Verificationism‘, Appendix 2. See

Blackburn (1993: 278, n. 11) concerning origins of the term.

63 In Martin‘s original example the concern is to undermine the conditional in the other direction (i.e. were x to

undergo S, x would yield manifestation M iff x is disposed to manifest M in response to stimulus S). In that

example, the electro-fink ensures that the wire is not live unless touched by a conductor, and so it would seem

that the conduction of a current when touched by a conductor was not a disposition of the wire, even though the

wire underwent the requisite stimulus and manifested the requisite manifestation.

Page 147: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

147

If I ingest a poison, but then take an antidote that changes my body in some way such that it

does not react fatally, then the poison‘s disposition remains intact, but the manifestation

(killing) does not follow necessarily upon the ingesting.

Mimics attack the biconditional in the other direction. Suppose an object lacks the

disposition to M when S, and yet it does M when S. How might this be? Bird gives the

example of a sturdy cooking pot—not fragile in the least—being attached to an explosive

devise with a sensitive detonator. The cooking pot will be broken if knocked even lightly, just

as if it were fragile, and yet it is not fragile.64

5.10 Repairing the Conditional Analysis: Ceteris Paribus Laws

Bird considers a number of possible repairs to CA to avoid these difficulties (see Bird 2007:

37–42), drawing on the work of Lewis, Mumford, and Choi, but finds these proposals

wanting. There is no adequate space to discuss these, here, so I will assume for the sake of

argument that he is correct, and instead move on to consider Bird‘s response. I think an even

more powerful response is at his disposal, but as it builds on Bird‘s work, it helps to outline

this first.

Bird reasons that the respects in which CA is false can be changed from a negative, to

a positive outcome. For it is precisely the areas in which CA fails that allow it to account for

ceteris paribus laws. He therefore proposes the following modification to CA:

(CA→*) if x has the disposition D(S,M) then, if x were subjected to S and finks and

antidotes to D(S,M) are absent, x would manifest M. (Bird 2007: 60)

This might seem a rather arbitrary and convenient addition, exactly the kind of thing the

sceptic can easily doubt. To support it, one needs to examine what exactly ceteris paribus laws

are, and why it would be a good thing if one‘s account of laws were to accommodate them.

Ceteris paribus laws are generally taken to arise for the special sciences, in contrast to

the laws of physics. A law of physicals, such as Newton‘s second law ‗F=ma‘, admits of no

exceptions. Whereas a law of biology, such as Mendell‘s law of segregations (‗In a parent, the

64 The example is from Bird (2007: 29), but the objection is attributed to Johnston (see 1992: 232), and this style

of counter-example to A D Smith (see 1977: 440).

Page 148: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

148

alleles for each character separate in the production of gametes, so that only one is transmitted

to each individual in the next generation‘ (Rosenberg and McShea 2008: 36)), may be subject

to interference, and therefore exceptions. Because of this, some philosophers of science argue

that such laws should be treated as though subject to a ceteris paribus clause, as, other things

being equal, they still hold.

This is disputed.

On one understanding, a law is a ceteris paribus law if it does not entail strict

regularities (see Earman, Roberts, and Smith 2002: esp. 288). It is suggested that to be a true

ceteris paribus law, 1) the law should fail to be specific about what regularities would have to

obtain for the law to hold, or 2) the law should be vague and impossible to be made explicit

due to the conditions upon its regularity composing ‗an indefinitely large set‘ (Earman,

Roberts, and Smith 2002: 284). This looks like a significant problem—if ceteris paribus laws

do not entail strict regularities it sounds as though there is room for the sceptic to cast doubt on

their metaphysical necessity.

However, Cartwright (2002: 425) disputes this definition. She insists that ceteris

paribus laws are laws that: ‗can be stated in precise and closed form or they entail strict or

statistical regularities in the course of events or both‘. For our purposes, ceteris paribus laws

fit Cartwright‘s definition as they can be stated precisely, in that the only exception to their

holding would be finks and antidotes. I do not think it should worry us that only one definition

of ceteris paribus laws fits our requirements. The point of a definition of a type of law is to

attempt to codify a lawlike relation. Both definitions assert the existence of something in

reality that requires explanation. It is of advantage to Cartwright if (CA→*) explains the

presence of ceteris paribus laws as she describes them, just as it is an advantage to Bird if the

modification he proposes would account for such laws.

5.11 Fundamental Dispositions cannot be Finkish

In addition to finding a place for explaining ceteris paribus laws in terms of finkish

dispositions, antidotes, and mimics, Bird argues that fundamental dispositions cannot be

finkish in the standard sense. He writes:

The standard cases of finkish dispositions are those where the causal basis for a

Page 149: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

149

disposition is removed before it can complete its causal work that would otherwise

lead to the manifestation of the disposition. In the case of a fundamental disposition

there is no distinct basis. Hence there can be no cases of finks of this sort. (Bird 2007:

60)

This is confusing. What is meant by ‗distinct causal basis‘? What is being distinguished from

what? In this section I will clarify Bird‘s thought, and in doing so, lead us to an even stronger

argument in favour of the impossibility of finkish65

dispositions at the fundamental level.

The confusion arises from a little carelessness of phrasing. The manifestation of a

finkish disposition is for it to fail to manifest something or other. What it is manifesting is the

failure to manifest of a different disposition, one which contributes to the make-up of the

finkish disposition. Take the example of the electro fink. The wire is disposed to be live up

until the point at which it is put in touch with a conductor, at which point the electro fink

causes it to lose this disposition. This is a disposition that never manifests—the live wire is

never touched by a conductor and therefore never conducts a current. It is not the live wire

whose disposition is finkish. The finkish disposition is a composite of the properties of the

wire and the electro fink; it is the disposition for the wire to lose the disposition to conduct

electricity (to be live) at the moment it is touched by a conductor. Obviously a fundamental

disposition can never be finkish in this sense. Its simplicity is such that it can never be

explained by appeal to a ‗deeper level‘ of dispositions, just as the finkish disposition is

explained away by appeal to the dispositions of the live wire and the electro fink combined.

Note that this point is made without clarifying whether the ‗distinct causal basis‘ is

intended to refer to the distinct dispositions, the distinct objects, or both. This becomes

relevant when Bird goes on to discuss whether:

objects can be made to acquire or lose dispositions not only by causing them to gain or

lose their distinct causal bases. It must be possible for an entity to gain a fundamental

potency directly. For example, electrons can be spin-up or spin-down and they can be

caused to change from one to the other. If these are fundamental properties then the

interactions that result in a change of spin direction will act by bringing about this

change directly, rather than indirectly by causing a change at some even deeper level

of property. (ibid., emphasis mine)

65 And antedotish and mimicish.

Page 150: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

150

Here an object is theorised to be able to gain a fundamental potency without losing or gaining

a ‗distinct causal basis‘. Bird (2007: 60–2) worries that this looks finkish, concluding that

whether or not there can be finkish properties depends on one‘s understanding of time.

However, I think he‘s missed something that, if properly understood, gives us a more powerful

reason for supposing that finkish dispositions cannot occur on the fundamental level at all.

In the example, the electrons are still caused to change from spinning up or down by an

external object, and this is the gain/loss of a fundamental potency. The changes happen

‗directly‘ in the sense that they are not brought about by causing a change at a deeper level of

the property. But then, this does not look finkish at all. The object simply gains or loses a

property. I think Bird has become confused in slipping between talk of fundamental properties

(simple dispositions with no deeper levels) and fundamental potencies (dispositional essences

that make an object the kind of object it is). The electrons are changed from being spin up to

spin down electrons. This change happens by a direct causal connection from the stimulus to

the spin of the electron. The object is still the same object (possessed of other fundamental

properties that make it an electron, like being negatively charged), but it has changed

potencies (the causal dispositions determined by it spinning one way, rather than the other). It

is still an electron, but now it is an electron of the kind with spin down causes and effects. The

illusion of finkishness must come from supposing that the electron staying the same object is

somehow contradictory with its loss of potency, but this is not so. It is just an electron that has

changed how it spins. This will have causal consequences for other things, but it is not finkish.

I therefore argue that Bird‘s position is even more persuasive than he takes it to be:

there cannot be finkish dispositions at the fundamental level. Finkish dispositions are

dispositions that are composites of more complex dispositions—ones that change over time.

The simpler dispositions upon which they are based are not finkish—they simply change to a

different disposition before they can manifest.

Similarly for antidotes. If I have taken an antidote before consuming a poison, then I

have changed the disposition of my body to react to those chemicals. It is no longer the kind of

thing that can be poisoned by such chemicals, even though prior to consumption of the

antidote it was. The antidote sensitive disposition is a combination of my (complex) body‘s

states over a period of time. But at a time when I have taken an antidote, I simply do not have

the disposition to manifest ‗being poisoned‘. This makes the disposition to poison humans

complicated and difficult to express otherwise than via a ceteris paribus law, but that is only

Page 151: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

151

due to complexity of the objects in question and their changing dispositions. At the

fundamental level the root causes covered by the law will not be ceteris paribus. The

disposition of arsenic to be an allosteric inhibitor of pyruvate dehydrogenase66

does not

change simply because one applies a DMSA monoester67

, preventing death or reducing

symptoms.

As regards mimics, it should be obvious that the kind of object that can be a mimic is a

complex entity. It is the combination of the properties of the pot with the properties of the

explosive device that make it manifest in a way that suggests fragility in response to s

stimulus. This is a distinguishing feature of covert dispositions: they are the result of

combination of several properties, to which more properties could be combined to change

outcomes. So adding something to a non-fragile pot that makes it behave in a fragile way can

be explained in that it is not the pot by itself that is fragile, but the combination of the pot with

something else (the explosive). The very act of adding something to a fundamental potency

will mean that the two properties combined are not fundamental. And any mimic will involve

some such addition. This explains why ceteris paribus laws are needed to account for mimics,

and why mimics are impossible at the fundamental level.

Having established this, I will now turn to the matter of giving a precise statement of

the laws of nature in terms of potencies.

5.12 The Metaphysical Necessity of Laws of Nature

Bird makes the following argument from his characterisation of dispositional essentialism to

the necessity of the laws of nature.

He proposes that we can understand the individuation of dispositionally essentialist

properties (potencies) by their powers. Even that we might identify them with their powers68

.

We may then characterise dispositionally essentialist potencies as follows:

66 The property that makes arsenic normally poisonous to humans.

67 An antidote to arsenic.

68 He says that this is not required for his argument; I do not think it is required for mine either, but it does seem

to me correct—proposing that potencies are something over and above the powers by which we individuate them

seems ontologically extravagant.

Page 152: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

152

(DEP) □(Px→D(S,M) x). (Bird 2007: 45)

Where P is a potency, D is a disposition, M is a manifestation, and S is a stimulus. He also

suggests that we consider CA as a necessary equivalence:

(CA□) □(D(S,M) x ↔ Sx □→ Mx). (Bird 2007: 43)

This seems reasonable: (excepting finks, antidotes, and mimics) necessarily, if and only if x

has the disposition such that it is disposed to manifest M when S, then if x has stimulus S, it

necessarily follows that x will manifest M.

Combining these two principles generates:

(I) □(Px → (Sx □→ Mx)). (Bird 2007: 46)

I.e. necessarily, if x has a potency P, then x is disposed to manifest M when stimulated by S;

and given that the disposition for x to manifest M when stimulated by S is equivalent to it

being necessary that if x is stimulated by S, then x will manifest M, it follows that it is

necessarily true that if x is a potency, then, necessarily, if x is stimulated by S, then x will

manifest M.

For any world, w, where some x has potency P and receives stimulus S:

(II) Px & Sx (ibid.)

It will then follow from (I) and (II) that:

(III) Mx (ibid.)

So (I), (II), and (III) deliver:

(IV) (Px & Sx) →Mx. (ibid.)

Which, given that x is arbitrary, can then be generalised to:

(V) ∀x((Px & Sx) →Mx). (ibid.)

Page 153: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

153

Bird suggests two ways via which (V) can account for the laws of nature.

One view might take (V) to state a law of nature in itself. Laws would be regularities,

as with the Lewisian view, but to be a regularity would not be sufficient for being a law. What

makes one regularity a law, when another might be happenstance, would be whether the

regularity is guaranteed by the essentially dispositional nature of the property or properties

involved.

Alternatively, one might take laws to be a kind of relation between universals. A law

might then be characterised as necessitation ‗N‘ for relating P, S, and M, such that N(P&S,M).

This would be similar to the Armstrongian position that laws are nomic relations described as

‗N(F,G)‘, where:

N(F,G) iff □(∀x(Fx→Gx) (where ‗F‘ and ‗G‘ are names of universals). (Bird 2007:

47)69

However, on the dispositional essentialist account, ‗N‘ is restricted to instances that arise

necessarily from the essence of a property, such that it is a relation between a potency,

stimulus, and manifestation as described in (V). Bird also stresses that the dispositional

essentialist‘s ‗N‘, unlike Armstrong‘s, need not be a universal itself; it may be supervenient on

the dispositional nature of properties. Moreover, it differs from Armstrong‘s in that it is

metaphysically necessary, as opposed to Armstrong‘s ‗nomic‘ necessity, which has been

critiqued earlier.

As (V) holds for any arbitrary world, it follows that it is necessary:

(V□)□∀x((Px & Sx)→Mx). (Bird 2007: 48)

69 Bird introduces an ‗r‘ to accompany the ‗x‘ for ‗∀rx‘ here which I have omitted. He does so without defining r,

and continues from this point onwards to use ‗r‘ in variations of (V). It‘s not quite clear what the role is. It might

be a way of specifying that x is a relation, although as ‗N(F,G)‘ and ‗N(P&S,M)‘ are supposed to be the relations,

this seems unlikely. Additionally, as (V) is supposed to be ambivalent between laws-as-regularities and laws-as-

relations-between-universals, this would seem peculiar. I therefore think it is clearer to remove the ‗r‘, both here,

and in the variations of ‗V‘ below.

Page 154: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

154

If we then built in the ceteris paribus requirement, with ‗finks, antidotes, and mimics to D are

absent‘ as the ceteris paribus clause, V□ would become:

(V*) ∀x (finks and antidotes [and mimics] to D are absent →((Dx & Sx)→Mx)). (Bird

2007: 60)

Given what we have previously said about finks, antidotes, and mimics, the absence of finks,

antidotes, and mimics is a given, and we could therefore give the following as a fundamental

law of nature:

(V**) ∀x (P*x →((Dx & Sx)→Mx))

Where ‗P*‘ is a fundamental property.

It is now time to turn out attention back to the strong transcendental response to the

sceptic. Will we be able to incorporate a metaphysically necessary law of the kind Bird has

argued for into our argument?

5.13 Finkish Dispositions, Psychophysical Laws, and the Sceptic

Recall that finkish dispositions were dispositions such that the disposition is lost after the

stimulus but before the manifestation. What we need to examine is how a psychophysical law

would operate such that it would follow from dispositional essentialism in the manner of (V*)

or (V**).

If we assume that D is a mental disposition and M is a physical manifestation, then we

seem to be headed for trouble. Something could interfere with the causal process such that

mental dispositions disposed to have physical consequences might have no connection to a

physical world at all. However, this is not the set-up. A transcendental argument works on a

premise such that something extra-mental is a necessary condition of something mental, so it

is not concerned with necessary physical consequences of mental dispositions.

Let us try it the other way around, then. Let D be a physical disposition to give rise to a

mental consequence, M, in response to stimulus S. Again, this does not give us what we need.

The necessary connection in that set-up is one way, so knowing M will tell us nothing about

the causal story that led up to M. That Mx necessarily follows from Dx + Sx does not tell us

Page 155: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

155

that M can have no other cause, and we do not get the result we were looking for from

metaphysically necessary laws of nature, as this cannot be known to be a law from knowledge

of mental propositions alone.

The problem is that our supposition to get around there being a ‗gap of necessity‘ that

needed to be bridged was that mental properties necessarily supervened upon extra-mental

properties (hence, no gap); but the metaphysical necessity drawn for the laws of nature by

dispositional essentialism looks to be a causal relation, not a relation of supervenience. This is

how the time factor creates room for the fink problem.

The mistake, here, is in misunderstanding the nature of a psychophysical law. The

supervenience relationship is not one of a mental disposition that has a physical consequence;

nor is it one of a physical disposition that has a mental consequence. The mental and physical

dispositions that supervene upon one another are not causally linked to each other. Rather,

they have the same causes and effects, although the one may rely upon the other to offer a

more satisfactory explanation of why that is the case. Supervenience physicalism is motivated

by explanatory efficacy.

How can this fit into Bird‘s analysis of dispositional essentialism? I propose the

following analysis for psychophysical laws (PP):

(PP) ∀x ((finks and antidotes to B are absent→((Bx & Sx)→Mx)))↔(finks and

antidotes to A are absent→((Ax & Sx)→Mx))))

Where A is a physical disposition and B is a mental disposition. This expresses the

supervenience of any law that applies to a mental disposition, A, on any law that applies to a

physical disposition, B. Once it is clarified that the link between A and B is not causal, it

becomes obvious that finks and antidotes cannot disrupt the necessary connection between A

and B. This is because any case in which the connection between (Bx & Sx) and Mx is

disrupted will also be a case in which the connection between (Ax & Sx) and Mx is disrupted.

In other words, should disposition B be at all finkish, it will only be finkish in the exact same

ways as disposition A. Similarly, if something is an antidote to disposition B, it will also be an

antidote to disposition A. For example, if I take ibuprofen I do it because it is an antidote to

the mental state ‗pain‘, but it is only an antidote to the mental state ‗pain‘ because it is an

Page 156: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

156

antidote to the conversion of arachidonic acid to prostaglandin H2 by cyclooxygenase70

. This

conversion would be the normal disposition in response to various physical stimuli associated

with physical injury or damage, but the antidote, in preventing this, also serves to prevent the

mental state of ‗pain‘ that supervenes on such conversion; in the absence of ibuprofen, the

disposition of bodies such as ours to respond by producing the chemical reactions that are the

physical manifestation of pain would necessarily be accompanied by the mental manifestation

of pain.

Now, if physicalism is correct, then there will be some mental states that can only be

adequately explained by their supervenience upon physical states. It will not be possible to

fully articulate their stimulus and manifestation conditions solely in terms of relations between

mental properties. If however, a theory can be provided that can explain the existence of the

mental state in terms of something extra mental, then it will take the form of (PP), for such an

explanation would involve articulation of stimulus and manifestation conditions in terms of

something other than the mental.

Given that the metaphysical necessity of the laws of nature follows from dispositional

essentialism, then there can only be one set of stimulus and manifestation conditions that

governs the mental property A. So if an explanation (an account of the stimulus and

manifestation conditions) for A can be provided in terms of extra-mental stimulus and

manifestation conditions only at some world, then, because that explanation will involve a law

of nature, those will be the only possible stimulus and manifestation conditions at all worlds.

In chapter three I established that there are at least some mental propositions that the

sceptic must accept as true. Her doubt rests on the thought that these could be equally well

explained by some sceptical scenario in which the world is radically different to how it seems

to me and there is no extra-mental world. Her doubt is not one that supposes that the world

might work in some completely random manner: there are regularities in our experience and

this demands explanation. She doubts the existence of the extra-mental world because she

worries that truths about the mental content she does not doubt could be equally well

explained in purely mental terms (such as that I am a deluded solipsistic purely mental

consciousness). However, attempts to explain the regularities in our experience based solely

on propositions relating to other mental states fail. If physicalism is correct then a complete

70 One way in which painkillers act upon the body to prevent pain.

Page 157: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

157

science would be able to explain our mental states in terms of physical states, including an

explanation of mental states (such as certain pains) that would otherwise come seemingly out

of nowhere. If dispositional essentialism is correct, then, the explanation offered by a

completed science in a physicalist world will take the form of a psychophysical law structured

along the lines of PP and, due to the metaphysical necessity of the laws of nature, it will

follow that this that the relationships between properties so described could not have been

otherwise.

The sceptic might then further worry that it is not humanly possible that a complete

science can be known. Yet, this is not sufficient to undermine the possibility of providing the

explanation we need. All a strong transcendental theorist needs is for some part of science to

be revealed that is not current known. Namely: that part of science that gives the stimulus and

manifestation conditions for mental state prized by the sceptic—a much smaller hurdle.

The sceptic might further object that articulating the totality of any one thing‘s

stimulus and manifestation conditions may be beyond human ability. As discussed earlier,

covert property names resist overt dispositional property descriptions. What if all mental states

the sceptic takes herself to know she possesses have only properties that can be given covert

property names, and not overt dispositional property descriptions? Two points can be made

against thinking that this will be the case.

Firstly, as indicated earlier, dispositional property descriptions for covert property

names can be cashed out once context is clarified. ‗Fragility‘ is difficult to pin down when we

do not know if we are talking about a vase or an ancient document: ancient documents are

fragile because they easily tear or fragment when touched; vases are fragile because they

easily break upon being dropped or hit. Fragility as a whole is difficult to define; the fragility

of a specific object is not.

Secondly, the difficulty of providing overt dispositional property descriptions vanishes

at the foundational level. Part of the reason the difficulty of providing such descriptions arises

for covert property names is because they arise through complex evolution of language. By

contrast, descriptions of foundational properties are simple, and thus precise and well-defined.

If it can be shown that a mental property supervenes upon a foundational physical property or

properties, then it will be explicable in terms of overt dispositional property descriptions.

To return to our painkiller example: if I sustain a muscular injury I will usually

experience pain, but the application of ibuprofen will usually reduce or entirely prevent the

Page 158: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

158

pain. This conditional is clearly open to antidotes. However, if supervenience physicalism is

correct, wherever there is pain, there will be some kind of physical event upon which the

experience of pain supervenes, and the prevention of the mental event (say, by the application

of painkillers) will be explained by the absence of that physical event. At the broad, complex

level, the law does not hold, but at the fundamental level it does. As the pain comes out of

nowhere on the mental level, we would then have reason to think that the physical world

exists, supplying the cause. The pain itself can be certainly known to be experienced, giving us

some reason to think that it supervenes on something that is a fundamental potency. Nothing

can come between my thinking that I experience pain and my actually experiencing it. This in

itself is not open to finks or antidotes, although clearly there are broad characterisations of

when I experience pain that are open to antidotes. Spraining a muscle (or thinking that I do, or

having an experience as of spraining a muscle, if all muscles are imagined, purely mental

constructs) is broadly a stimulus for pain, but taking ibuprofen can prevent the experience of

that pain. However, if we can identify some foundational property (some property of C-fibres

when fired, perhaps71

) that, whenever appropriately stimulated, pain manifests, it will be

explained how we could not possibly be mistaken about pain, because that property is not

possibly finkish or open to antidotes.

5.14 Necessitarianism about Laws

To return to the argument for the necessity of natural laws: as V□ follows from dispositional

essentialism, partial necessitarianism about laws follows:

(PNL) At least some of the laws of nature are metaphysically necessary. (Bird 2007:

50)

On this view at least some laws would be metaphysically necessary on the basis of

dispositional essentialism. Other laws might be accounted for in a more Lewisian or

Armstrongian way. We would thus have a mixed view of laws, as well as a mixed view of

71 This is the oft cited event upon which pain is thought to supervene. As I am not claiming to make a successful

transcendental argument here, nothing turns on the accuracy of this description.

Page 159: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

159

properties. This is opposed to full necessitarianism, on which theory all laws would be

metaphysically necessary.

The transcendental theorist is not forced to argue for full necessitarianism. It will

suffice for my purposes if at least some potencies exist and therefore some metaphysically

necessary laws of nature exist. What I require, after all, is that metaphysically necessary laws

of nature entail a metaphysically necessary connection between certain mental propositions

that the sceptic accepts and the truth of some extra-mental propositions. So long as it can be

shown either that the truth of some mental proposition depends on a mental manifestation

which only manifests if some extra-mental potency exists, the metaphysical architecture will

support a strong transcendental argument. However, it would be beneficial to the strong

transcendental theorist if full-necessitarianism were true, in as much as simply showing that a

law of nature so related some mental property and some physical one, without having to show

in addition that the law of nature in question happened to be a metaphysically necessary one.72

In any case, although Bird does not offer a smack down argument in favour of full

necessitarianism (i.e. not one the sceptic would obviously have to agree to), most scholars

seem to prefer a unified approach to accounting for the laws of nature, and if partial

necessitarianism is true, and a unified approach should prove to be necessary, full

necessitarianism will be true by default.

Bird also identifies two views one might take on the nature of the metaphysical

necessity in question. If the law supervenes upon the presence of the universals it concerns,

then it would seem that some laws do not hold at all worlds because the potencies they operate

over do not. This is what Bird (2007: 49) calls a ‗conservative‘ view of necessitarianism. The

thought is that on this view the necessary unity would reside in ‗nomological consistency‘ of

facts: no fact at any world would provide a counter-example to any law, existent at another,

even though some laws would not hold for some worlds simply because the necessary

potencies were not present to operate over. This is contrasted with a ‗radical‘ or ‗strong‘

72 To an extent, the ‗labour-saving‘ point is moot. If all laws of nature are metaphysically necessary because they

supervene on the operations of potencies, then identifying a law of nature will still be done by demonstrating its

operation over potencies. This is the same operation one would employ in identifying those laws of nature which

are metaphysically necessary were partial necessitarianism true. However, the simplicity of appeal to a unified

approach would be a point in favour of necessitarianism as a whole, so it seems that if a strong necessitarian

account can be given, it would be beneficial to do so.

Page 160: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

160

necessitarianism for which the laws of nature are necessary in the sense that they hold over all

possible worlds, and thus the universals they govern exist at all possible worlds. Although

Bird clarifies that: ‗the proposition can be true of a world where the fact does not exist‘ (Bird

2007: 50); just as with Kripke‘s notion of the necessity of identity, where ‗Geroge Orwell =

Eric Blair‘ will be true at all worlds, regardless of whether the fact of Orwell‘s existence is

true at that world (see Bird 2007: 49–50)73

. On this view, worlds may be nominologically

consistent as regards laws, but not facts.

Bird sees strong necessitarianism as problematic for those, like Armstrong, who accept

the Aristotelian notion that to exist at a world, a universal must be instantiated at that world.

The thought being that the law is true by virtue of the universals it involves. If the universals

only exist when instantiated, then no law can be applied, as there will be no universals to

apply it to, or to express a relation between. Bird sees a reliance upon particulars by universals

as a ‗failure of nerve as regards realism about universals‘ (Bird 2007: 55) and ‗diagnoses‘ the

failure as being because Armstrong, and all who favour the instantiation condition, are tacitly

treating universals as categorical—defined by relations in the world, and not by any essence

that they possess.

For our purposes, it does not matter if the laws needed by a strong transcendental

argument only hold where the universals are instantiated. The sceptic is only concerned with

worlds at which those universals are instantiated anyway. Worlds where a mental property that

is a part of one of the sceptic‘s prized mental propositions exists will, by the nature of that

property, have whatever relations are necessary to it being that property. Therefore any

psychophysical law that showed that if such a property were to exist, some physical property

would have to exist, will hold. It does not matter if it should be the case that this law will not

hold at worlds where these properties do not exist.

73 Note that this would not be accepted by philosophers such as Timothy Williamson (2002) and David Efird

(2010), who argue that any necessary truth about a particular entails the necessary existence of that particular.

Hence, they would say that it is not true that ‗Geroge Orwell = Eric Blair‘ is necessarily true even if Orwell/Blair

does not exist at that world. There is no space to adequately address their arguments here, but I do not think it is

necessary to do so. If all particulars for which there are necessary truths exist and do so necessarily, so much the

better! We will have all the more reason to think that the potencies that make them of one kind or another will

continue to ensure laws of nature. However, if they are wrong and Bird is right, my conclusions will still go

through on a partial necessitarian view.

Page 161: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

161

5.15 Regularity and Dispositional Essentialism

It may be wondered whether dispositional essentialism about properties might not be

compatible with a mere regularity view of the laws of nature, rather than entailing

metaphysical necessaity. Bird concedes: ‗Strictly a regularity view of laws need not require

categorical properties nor be inconsistent with dispositional essentialism‘ (Bird 2007: 83). The

sense in which dispositional essentialism is compatible with the regularity view of laws stems

from the fact that it is not the laws that impose order upon the properties. The laws are a

pattern of regular relations that supervene on the essential dispositions of potencies. They

describe these relations, rather than governing them. In this sense they are merely ‗regularities

which hold as a consequence of the essentially dispositional nature of fundamental properties‘

(ibid.).

However, unlike the regularity view of laws associated with categoricalism about

properties, the sense in which the regularity view of laws that flows from dispositional

essentialism supervenes upon those properties, whose powers remain the same transworld,

entails that the laws are metaphysically necessary. Therefore, the only way in which a

regularity view of laws can work in the absence of categorical properties is for that regularity

to be metaphysically necessary. It is a derived metaphysical necessity—owed to the nature of

the properties, rather than anything specific about being a law—but it is metaphysical

necessity nonetheless.

5.16 Conceivability and the Illusion of Nomic Contingency

Having given the reasons the sceptic should accept dispositional essentialism and the

consequent metaphysical necessity of the laws of nature, it must be explained why the illusion

of nomic contingency—that laws are not metaphysically necessary—is so compelling. The

contingency of the laws of nature is often simply assumed, suggesting a strong intuition that

should be explained.

With Bird, I doubt the authority of this intuition. It does seem plausible that the

tradition of regarding the laws of nature as contingent has helped form our intuitions, rather

than the other way around. Bird (2007: 170) suggests that the historical origin stems from

Page 162: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

162

imagining that God might have chosen other laws to govern the world. Chalmers (2002: 146)

gives this definition for metaphysical possibility: ‗a world that God might have created, if he

had so chosen‘. Resting such a definition on the possible existence and powers of God is

highly problematic, of course. Especially for our sceptic, who professes not to know if anyone

but me exists. If the intuition that the laws of nature are not metaphysically necessary stems

from this, she must question such an intuition.

Recall that for Hume the motivation for supposing the laws of nature could not be

metaphysically necessary was because necessary connections should be either ‗either

intuitively or demonstratively certain‘ (Hume 1748: 4.1). The intuitively certain are known

because their contrary cannot be conceived, and Hume supposed that the contrary of the laws

of nature could be conceived. That on encountering an entirely novel object one cannot tell

how it will act in conjunction with another object. However, as Chalmers (2002: 159–60) has

outlined, there is a gap between prima facie conceivability and possibility. Prima facie

conceivability is contrasted to ideal conceivability, where ideal conceivability is what is

conceivable on ideal rational reflection. Upon prima facie imperfect information and reflection

on an object, I may imagine all kinds of actions to be conceivable. For example, the law of

gravity means that if I drop a billiard ball on Earth under normal conditions, it will fall;

however, Hume would say, I can prima facie conceive that it might fly off in any direction, or

that it might explode etc. However, this conception is incomplete in two senses: firstly, were I

to become better acquainted with the object, I would find that there are many actions that are

not possible due to the laws of nature operating at the actual world. The materials of which the

ball is made are not volatile or likely to explode under normal conditions, and they are denser

than air, thus disposed to fall through air to the ground as an operation of the law of gravity.

Secondly, the conception is incomplete in terms of what rules could consistently apply at other

worlds. The first sense is a matter of what Chalmers calls ‗primary conceivability‘—of what

could be conceived to happen at the actual world—whilst the second is a matter of ‗secondary

conceivability‘—of what might have been true at other possible worlds (see Chalmers 2002:

156–9).

It is not ideal primary conceivable that the ball would fly into the air or explode, and

this is relatively uncontroversial. The illusion of nomic contingency comes from the prima

facie secondary conceivability of the ball doing so at other worlds, where the laws of nature

are different. However, such conceivability must rest upon a categoricalist understanding of

Page 163: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

163

the nature of properties. For, as we have argued, if properties are understood as dispositionally

essentialist potencies, then they are defined by their powers. These powers determine a

network of relations upon which the laws of nature supervene. Wherever the properties of the

billiard ball truly are the same, they must necessarily react in the same ways given the same

conditions. Otherwise they would not be the properties they are, the ball would not be the kind

of ball it is, the conditions (density of air, proximity to a planetary body, etc.) would not be the

kinds of things they are.

Thus we can explain the illusion of nomic contingency whilst also showing that it is an

illusion.

5.17 Conclusion

There is more to be said about dispositional essentialism and the laws of nature than there is

room for here. Nevertheless, I think enough has been said for my purposes. My aim here is to

defend the plausibility of a strong transcendental response to external world scepticism.

Dispositional essentialism is a plausible theory which we have good reason to think entails

metaphysical necessity for the laws of nature. Moreover, the way in which this entailment

works reveals a plausible mechanism via which a psychophysical law of the kind the strong

transcendental theorist needs for her second premise can work. Namely, that some mental state

the sceptic prizes may be necessarily possessed of a mental property, A, whose stimulus and

manifestation conditions can only be given in terms of the stimulus and manifestation

conditions of some extra-mental property, B, in accordance with (PP).

I do not hereby offer a completed strong transcendental argument, but I have offered a

plausible account of how such a psychophysical law could be shown to be metaphysically

necessary if one accepts dispositional essentialism as an account of at least fundamental

properties. I have also shown that there is good reason for the sceptic to accept dispositional

essentialism. This is not a complete defence, but it is enough to show that there is a case here

to answer. It is not enough to assert that some sceptical hypothesis could equally well explain

our mental states. It is not enough to assert that a bridge of necessity is needed to reason from

mental premises to physical conclusions, and that such a bridge is impossible. The burden of

proof is shifted. I have shown that there is at least one plausible line of approach that could

exclude the possibility of an explanatory gap between the physical and the mental; more, there

Page 164: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

164

is the potential to show that a physical explanation is necessary to give an adequate account of

the mental.

The sceptic must now find reasons to defend specific metaphysical views in order to

maintain her sceptical doubt. She would need to attack dispositional essentialism and the

metaphysical necessity of the laws of nature; defend categorical monism about properties, or

show that, under a mixed view, we have reason to think that all relevant prized mental

properties are categorical—it is not at all obvious how such an argument could be made. These

are not views that can be trivially dismissed. A much richer view would need to be provided

by the sceptic than merely suggesting that I might be a mad, solipsistic consciousness.

With plausibility restored to the possibility of offering a strong transcendental response

to scepticism, the dynamic of the dialectic with the sceptic is changed. We are not left

choosing between doubt and insisting that the question itself does not make sense. We can

demand greater justification from the sceptic, defences of specific views. She is not free solely

to attack and shift position on whimsy. This, in itself, is no small feat.

Page 165: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

165

Conclusion

I have shown that it is entirely plausible that a strong transcendental argument could be found

that offers a robust defence against the sceptic who worries that I might have all the thoughts

and experiences I do now without the existence of an extra-mental world.

I have shown that transcendental arguments as a whole are well-suited to addressing

the question on the basis that they start from premises the sceptic accepts and can take

seriously her standards for justification. As the conclusion of a transcendental argument is

shown to be a necessary condition of the truth of a proposition concerning the mental that the

sceptic prizes, the justification she values having in such a proposition is transferred across to

the conclusion.

I have established that strong transcendental arguments are to be preferred to weak

transcendental arguments, and I have defended the plausibility of such arguments. I have

shown that it is not necessary for a strong transcendental argument to incorporate a suppressed

verification principle, and that the supposition that that it is rests on the deeper criticism that it

is not possible to reason from premises concerning the mind to a conclusion concerning the

world. I have shown that this deeper criticism rests on the mistaken assumption that the mind

is not a part of the world. I have shown that we can understand the relationship of mind to the

extra-mental world as being one of a category of facts (mental facts) that supervenes on other

categories of facts—in particular, physical facts. Any argument that it is not possible to have

entailment relations between mental facts and extra-mental facts has been shown to rest on an

illicit assumption about the nature of the relationship between mind and the extra-mental

world that we have been given no reason to think plausible. I have shown that an alternate

picture of the relationship of mind to extra-mental world is available in the form of

supervenience physicalism, and I have defended the plausibility of this picture.

Lastly, I have given a plausible account of how the second premise of a transcendental

argument could work, based on a dispositional essentialist understanding of properties, which

would entail a metaphysically necessary conception of laws of nature, on which it would be

plausible to offer a psychophysical law of a form that could be used as the second premise of a

strong transcendental argument.

I have not here given a strong transcendental argument. The development and defence

of any such argument would be a much larger project than there is room for here. However, I

Page 166: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

166

have shown that the materials are available from which one plausibly might construct such an

argument. Moreover, I have shown that any attempt to reject this plausibility will have to rely

upon the defence of specific philosophical positions, such as resemblance nominalism

concerning the laws of nature or a specific and limiting conception of the relationship between

mind and world. This forces the sceptic into a more definitive position than simply insisting

that a sceptical scenario could just as easily account for the thoughts and experiences we have

as the supposition that the extra-mental world exists. To defend the thought that no strong

transcendental argument could be offered against her doubt, she must adopt philosophical

positions that we, ourselves, may not agree with. This shifts her from her position of voicing a

natural doubt many humans feel from time to time and forces her into adopting positions that

many of us would reject.

Whilst scepticism itself has not been refuted, the mere plausibility of offering a strong

transcendental argument against this type of sceptic can offer us a certain amount of comfort

by revealing something about how the world would have to be in order for a strong

transcendental argument to not be possible.

Page 167: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

167

Bibliography

Al-Ghazali (2002), Deliverance from Error and Mystical Union with the Almighty,

Muhammad Abulaylah (trans.) and George F. McLean (ed.),

<http://www.ghazali.org/books/md/>, accessed 7th

May 2013, Council for Research in Values

and Philosophy

Andrews, F M, and Withey, S B (1976), Social Indicators of Well-Being, New York: Plenum

Press

Anzai, Tetsuo (1999), Shakespeare in Japan, Lewiston, NY: Lampeter

Armstrong, David Malet (1983), What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Augustine (1991), Confessions, Henry Chadwick (int. and trans.), Oxford: Oxford University

Press

Augustine (1995), Against the Academics and the Teacher, Peter King (int. and trans.),

Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company

Austin, J L (2003), ‗Are There A Priori Concepts?‘ (pp. 32–54), Philosophical Papers, J. O.

Urmson, and G. J. Warnock (eds), Oxford Scholarship Online,

<http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/019283021X.001.0001/acprof-

9780192830210-chapter-2>, accessed 5th

November 2008

Bailey, Sally (2011), ‗Play as a Staging Ground for Performance and Life‘ (pp. 137–154),

Play and Performance: Play and Cultural Studies, Vol. 11, Carrie Lobman and Barbara E.

O‘Neil (eds), Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America

Page 168: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

168

Bayne, Tim and Spencer, Maja (2010), ‗Introspective Humility‘ (pp.1-22), Philosophical

Issues 20, Philosophy of Mind

Berkeley, George (1998), Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, Jonathan Dancy

(ed. and intro.), Oxford: Oxford University Press

Bett, Richard (2010), ‗Introduction‘ (pp. 1–10), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient

Scepticism, Richard Bett (ed.), Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press

Beck, Aaron T, Brad A Alford (2009), Depression: Causes and Treatment, Philadelphia:

University of Pennsylvania Press

Berkeley, George (1998), A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge,

Jonathan Dancy (ed.), Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press

Bird, Alexander (2007), Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties, Oxford: Oxford

University Press

Blackburn, Simon (1993), ‗Circles, Finks, Smells and Biconditionals‘ (pp. 259–279),

Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 7

Brecht, Bertolt (1961), ‗On Chinese Acting‘ (pp. 130-36), The Tulane Drama Review, Vol. 6,

No. 1, Eric Bently (trans.)

Brooks, E. Bruce, and A. Taeko Brooks (1998) The Original Analects, New York: Columbia

University Press

Burge, Tyler (1986), ‗Individualism and Psychology‘ (pp. 3–45), The Philosophical Review,

Vol. 95, Durham, NC: Duke University Press

Page 169: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

169

Care Quality Commission (2015), Monitoring the Mental Health Act in 2013/14,

<http://www.cqc.org.uk/content/mental-health-act-annual-report-201314>, accessed 17th

April

2015

Cartwright, Nancy (2002), ‗In Favor of Laws that are not Ceteris Paribus After All‘ (pp. 425-

39), Erkenntnis, Vol. 57

Chakravartty, Anjan (2014), ‗Scientific Realism‘, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

(Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),

<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/scientific-realism/>, accessed 19th

March

2015.

Chalmers, David (2002), ‗Does Conceivability Entail Possibility?‘ (pp. 145–200),

Conceivability and Possibility, Tamar Szabó Gendler and John Hawthorne (eds), Oxford and

New York: Oxford University Press

Cicero, (1933), De natura deorum; Academica, H. Rackham (trans.), London: William

Heinemann

Cinpoeðs, Nicoleta (2010), Shakespeare's Hamlet in Romania, 1778-2008: A Study in

Translation, Performance, and Cultural Adaptation, Lewiston, NY: Lampeter

Clark, Andy (2008), Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension,

Oxford: Oxford University Press

Coleridge, Samuel Taylor (2004), Biographia Literaria, Tapio Riikonen and David Widger

(eds), Project Gutenberg, accessed 15th

April 2013, last updated 26th

January 2013

Crane, Tim and D. H. Mellor (1990): ‗There is No Question of Physicalism‘ (pp. 185-206),

Mind, Vol. 99, Oxford: Oxford University Press

Page 170: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

170

Crane, Tim (1991), ‗Why Indeed? Papineau on Supervenience‘ (pp. 32-37), Analysis, Vol. 61,

Oxford: Oxford University Press

Cronenberg, David (1998), eXistenZ, UK: Momentum Pictures

Currie, Gregory and Jon Jureidini (2001), ‗Delusion, Rationality, Empathy‘ (159–62),

Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology, Vol. 8.

Davidson, Donald (1980), ‗Mental Events‘, Essays on Action and Events, Oxford: Clarendon

Press

Davidson, Donald (2002a), ‗Knowing One‘s Own Mind‘ (pp. 15–38), Subjective,

Intersubjective, Objective, Oxford University Press: Oxford

Davidson, Donald (2002b), ‗A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge‘ (pp. 137–57),

Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective, Oxford University Press: Oxford

Davidson, Donald (2002c), ‗Empirical Content‘ (pp. 159–75), Subjective, Intersubjective,

Objective, Oxford University Press: Oxford

Davidson, Donald (2002b), ‗Three Varieties of Knowledge‘ (pp. 205–20), Subjective,

Intersubjective, Objective, Oxford University Press: Oxford

Dennett, Daniel C (1978), Brainstorms, Cabridge, MA: Bradford Books

Dennett, Daniel C (1991), Consciousness Explained, London: Penguin

Descartes, René (1996), Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections from the Objections

and Replies, John Cottingham (ed. and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Page 171: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

171

Descartes, René (1932), ‗The Principles of Philosophy‘, The Philosophical Works of

Descartes, Elizabeth S Haldane and G R T Ross (eds and trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press

Dretske, Fred (1977), ‗Laws of Nature‘ (pp. 248–68), Philosophy of Science, Vol. 44

Dretske, Fred (2004), ‗Change Blindness‘ (pp. 1-18), Philosophical Studies: An International

Journal for Philosophy in the AnalyticTradition, Vol. 120

Earman, John, John Roberts, and Sheldon Smith (2002), ‗Ceteris Paribus Lost‘ (pp. 281-301),

Erkenntnis, Vol. 57

Efird, David (2010), ‗Is Timothy Williamson a Necessary Existent?‘ (pp. 97-108), Modality:

Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Ellis, Brian (2001), Scientific Essentialism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ellis, Brian (2002), The Philosophy of Nature, Chesham: Acumen

Ellis, Brian (2006), ‗Physical Realism‘ (pp. 1–13), Metaphysics in Science, Malden, MA and

Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

Frances, Bryan (2005), Scepticism Comes Alive, Oxford: Oxford and New York

Ghent, Henry of (2002), The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, Robert

Pasnau (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Haybron, Daniel M. (2007), ‗Do We Know How Happy We Are? On Some Limits of

Affective Introspection and Recall‘ (pp. 394–428), Noûs, Vol. 41, No. 3

Page 172: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

172

Henrich, Dieter (1989), ‗Kant‘s Notion of a Deduction and the Methodological Background of

the First Critique‘, Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, Eckart Förster (ed.), Stanford: Stanford

University Press

Hirstein, William and V S Ramachandran (1997), ‗Capgras Syndrome: A Novel Probe for

Understanding the Neural Representation of the Identity and Familiarity of Persons‘ (pp. 437–

44), Proceedings: Biological Sciences, Vol. 264.

Hirsten, William (2010), ‗The Misidentification Syndromes as Mindreading Disorders‘ (pp.

233–60), Cognitive Neuropsychology, Vol. 15

Hobbes, Thomas (2007), ‗Objection 1‘ (p. 42), Objections to the Meditations and Descartes’s

Replies, Jonathan Bennet (ed.), <http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/pdf/descobje.pdf>, last

updated November 2007, accessed 21st April 2013

Huang, Alexa (2011), ‗Shakespeare and Translation‘ (pp. 68–105), The Edinburgh Companion

to Shakespeare and the Arts, Stockport: University of Edinburgh Press.

Hume, David (1748 and 1777), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Peter Millican

and Amyas Merivale (eds), <http://www.davidhume.org/texts/thn.html>, davidhume.org, last

updated May 2012, accessed 18th

May 2015

Hume, David (1739–40), A Treatise of Human Nature, accessed online from

http://www.davidhume.org/texts/thn.html, Peter Millican and Amyas Merivale (eds),

davidhume.org, last updated May 2012, accessed on 5th

April 2014

Jackson, Frank (2000), ‗Serious Metaphysics and Supervenience‘ (pp. 1-?), From Metaphysics

to Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press

Johnston, Mark (1992), ‗How to Speak of the Colours‘ (pp. 221–63), Philosophical Studies,

Vol. 68

Page 173: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

173

Johnston, Mark (1993), ‗Objectivity Refigured: Pragmatism Without Verificationism‘ (pp. 85–

130, Reality, Reprtesentation, and Projection, John Haldane and Crispin Wright (eds), Oxford:

Oxford University Press

Kant, Immanuel (1962), Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics that will be able to Present

Itself as a Science, Peter G. Lucas (trans.), Manchester: Manchester University Press

Kant, Immanuel (1996), Critique of Pure Reason, Werner S. Pluhar (trans.) and Patricia

Kitcher (intro.), Cambridge, Indianapolis: Hackett

Klima, Gyula, Fritz Allhoff, and Anand Jayprakash (2007), Medieval Philosophy: Essential

Readings with Commentary, Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing

Koller, John M. (2000), ‗Syādvāda as the Epistemological Key to the Jaina Middle Way

Metaphysics of Anekāntavāda‘ (pp. 400-7), Philosophy East and West, Vol. 50, No. 3

Kripke, Saul (1981), Naming and Necessity, Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

Kumar, Dehdev (2001), Jain Temples of Rahjasthan, Janpath, New Delhi: Indira Gandhi

National Centre for the Arts

Lao-tzu (1891), ‗Tao Te Ching‘, Sacred Books of the East, Vol 39, J. Legge (trans.),

<http://www.sacred-texts.com/tao/taote.htm>, accessed 7th

May 2013

Lewis, David Kellogg (1973), Counterfactuals, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

Litvin, Margaret (2011), Hamlet's Arab Journey : Shakespeare's Prince and Nasser's Ghost,

Princeton, N J: Princeton University Press

Loewe, Michael and Edward L. Shaughnessy (1999), The Cambridge History of Ancient

China: From the Origins of Civilization to 221 BC, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Page 174: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

174

Martin, C B (1994), ‗Dispositions and Conditionals‘ (pp. 1-8), The Philosophical Quarterly,

Vol. 44

McManus, Sally, Howard Meltzer, Traolach Brugha, Paul Bebbington, and Rachel Jenkins

(eds) (2009), ‗Key Facts‘, Adult Psychiatric Morbidity in England—2007, Results of a

Household Survey, Health and Social Care Information Centre,

<http://www.hscic.gov.uk/pubs/psychiatricmorbidity07>, accessed 14 April 2015, last updated

27 January 2009

Nolan, Christopher (2010), Inception, UK and USA: Warner Bros Pictures

O‘Daly, George (2001) ‗The response to scepticism and the mechanisms of cognition‘ (pp.

159-70), The Cambridge Companion to Augustine, Eleonore Stumpr and Norman Kretzmann

(eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Papineau, David (1990), ‗Why Supervenience?‘ (pp. 66-71), Analysis, Vol. 50, Oxford:

Oxford University Press

Papineau, David (1991), ‗The Reason Why: Response to Crane‘ (pp. 37-40), Analysis, Vol.

51, Oxford: Oxford University Press

Papineau, David (2004), ‗Supervenience and Identity‘, Philosophical Naturalism,

<http://www.kcl.ac.uk/ip/davidpapineau/Staff/Papineau/PhilNat2nded/ch1%20revised.htm>,

accessed 14th

February 2010

Passer, Kevin M and Julia K Warnock (1991), ‗Pimozide in the Treatment of Capgras‘

Syndrome: A Case Report‘ (pp. 446–8), Psychosomatics, Vol. 32

Peirce, C S (1902) Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 8 vols, vols. 1–6, C Hartshorne

and P Weiss (eds), Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press

Page 175: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

175

Pellegrin, Pierre (2010), ‗Sextus Empiricus‘ (pp. 120–41), The Cambridge Companion to

Ancient Scepticism, Richard Bett (ed.), Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University

Press

Phillips, D. P. and Wills, J. S. (1987), ‗A Drop in Suicides Around Major National Holidays‘

(pp. 1–11), Suicide and Life Threatening Behaviour, Vol.17

Plato (2002), Five Dialogues: Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo, G M A Grube

(trans.), revised by John M Cooper, Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett

Psillos, Stathis (1999), Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks the Truth, London and New

York: Routledge

Psillos, Stathis (2006), ‗Scientific Realism and Metaphysics‘ (pp. 14–32), Metaphysics in

Science, Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

Putnam, Hilary (1973), ‗Meaning and Reference‘ (pp. 699–711), The Journal of Philosophy,

Vol. 70, New York: Journal of Philosophy

Putnam, Hilary (1975), ‗The Meaning of ―Meaning‖‘ (pp. 131–93), Minnesota Studies in the

Philosophy of Science, Vo. 7

Putnam, Hilary (1993), Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

Robinson, Don (1991), ‗On Crane and Mellor‘s Argument against Physicalism‘ (pp. 135–6),

Mind, Vol. 100

Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo (2001), ‗Resemblance Nominalism and Russell‘s Regress‘ (pp.

395–408), Austalasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 79

Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo (2002a), Resemblance Nominalism, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Page 176: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

176

Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo (2002b), ‗The Problem of Universals and the Limits of

Conceptual Analysis‘ (pp. 29–47), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 31

Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo (2003), ‗Resemblance Nominalism and Counterparts:

Reply to Bird‘ (pp. 229–37), Analysis, Vol. 63

Rose, David, Wesley Buckwalter, and John Turri (2014), ‗When Words Speak Louder than

Actions: Delusion, Belief, and the Power of Assertion‘ (pp. 683–700), Australasian Journal of

Philosophy, Vol. 92

Rosenberg, Alex and McShea, Daniel W. (2008), Philosophy of Biology: A Contemporary

Introduction, New York and London: Routledge

Russell, Bertrand (1956), An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London: George Allen and

Unwin

Russell, Bertrand (2008), The Problems of Philosophy, Rockville, Maryland: Arc Manor

Schwitzgebel, Eric (2008), ‗The Unreliability of Naive Introspection‘, (pp. 245-273),

Philosophical Review, Vol. 117

Sextus Empiricus (2005), Outlines of Scepticism, Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes (eds and

trans.), Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press

Shakespeare, William (1997), The Riverside Shakespeare: Second Edition, The Complete

Works, G Blakemore Evans, J J M Tobin, et al (eds), Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin

Company

Shakespeare, William (Wil'yam Shex'pir) (2000), The Klingon Hamlet: The Restored Klingon

Version, Nick Nicolas and Andrew Strader (trans.), New York: Pocket Books

Page 177: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

177

Shoemaker, Sydney (1984), Identity, Cause, and Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press

Smith, A D (1977), ‗Dispositional Properties‘ (pp. 439-44), Mind, New Series, Vol. 86

Sosa, Ernest (2007), A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Oxford:

Oxford University Press

Swoyer, Chris (1982), ‗The Nature of Natural Law‘ (pp. 203–23), Australasian Journal of

Philosophy, Vol. 60,

Sparhawk, T. G. (1987), ‗Traditional Holidays and Suicide‘ (pp. 245-246), Psychological

Reports, Vol. 60

Spitzer, Robert L., Janet B. W. Williams, Kurt Kroenke, and colleagues (2010a), ‗Patient

Health Questionnaire-9 (PHQ-9)‘, Patient Health Questionnaire (PHQ) Screeners, Pfizer, <

http://www.phqscreeners.com/>, accessed 8th

May 2015, last updated April 2010.

Spitzer, Robert L., Janet B. W. Williams, Kurt Kroenke, and colleagues (2010b), ‗GAD-7‘,

Patient Health Questionnaire (PHQ) Screeners, Pfizer, < http://www.phqscreeners.com/>,

accessed 8th May 2015, last updated April 2010.

Stanislavski, Constantin (1961), Creating a Role, Joshua Logan (int.) and Elizabeth Reynolds

Hapgood (trans.), New York: Theatre Arts Books

Stern, Robert (2000), Transcendental Arguments and Scepticism: Answering the Question of

Justification, Oxford: Clarendon Press

Stoneham, Tom (2004), ‗Self-Knowledge‘ (pp. 647-672), Handbook of Epistemology, M

Sintonen Niiniluoto and J Woleński (eds), Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers

Page 178: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

178

Strawson, P F (1976), The Bounds of Sense: A Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason,

London: Methuen

Strawson, P F (1985), Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties, London: Methuen

Strawson, P F (1987), Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics, London and New

York: Methuen

Stroud, Barry (1979), ‗The Significance of Scepticism‘ (pp. 277–97), Transcendental

Arguments and Science: Essays in Epistemology, Peter Bieri, Rolf-Peter Horstmann, and

Lorenz Krüger (eds), Dordrecht, Holand and Boston USA: D Reidel Publishing Company

Stroud, Barry (2000a), ‗Transcendental Arguments‘, Understanding Human Knowledge:

Philosophical Essays (pp. 9-25), Oxford: Oxford University Press

Stroud, Barry (2000b), ‗Kantian Argument, Conceptual Capacities, and Invulnerability‘,

Understanding Human Knowledge: Philosophical Essays (pp. 155-176), Oxford: Oxford

University Press

Stroud, Barry (2000c), ‗Radical Interpretation and Philosophical Scepticism‘, Understanding

Human Knowledge: Philosophical Essays (pp. 177-202), Oxford: Oxford University Press

Stroud, Barry (2000d), ‗The Goal of Transcendental Arguments‘, Understanding Human

Knowledge: Philosophical Essays (pp. 203-223), Oxford: Oxford University Press

Svavarsson, Svavar Hrafn (2010), ‗Pyrrho and Early Pyrrhonism‘ (pp. 36–57), The Cambridge

Companion to Ancient Scepticism, Richard Bett (ed.) Cambridge and New York: Cambridge

University Press.

Tooley, Michael (1977), ‗The nature of laws‘ (pp. 667–98), Canadian Journal of Philosophy,

Vol. 7

Page 179: On the Plausibility of a Strong Transcendental Response to ...etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/11344/7/FINAL_SUBMISSION.pdf · 3.8 CARTESIAN INFALLIBILITY VS INCORRIGIBILITY ... there prevails

Tom Stoneham

179

Unger, Peter (2003), Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism, Oxford Scholarship Online:

<http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/0198244177.001.0001/acprof-

9780198244172>, accessed 12th

March 2013; print publication date 1978

Wachoski, Andy and Lana Wachowski (1999), The Matrix, Australia and USA: Warner Bros

Pictures

Weir, Peter (1998), The Truman Show, USA: Paramount Pictures

Weiskrantz, L (1986), Blindsight: A Case Study and Implications, Oxford: Clarendon Press

Whiteley, C H (1975), ‗Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism By Peter Unger Clarendon Press:

Oxford University Press, 1975, vii + 319 £6.50‘ (pp. 489–90), Philosophy, Vol. 50, Issue 194,

published online 25th

February 2009

Williams, B (1978), Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Harmondsworth: Penguin

Williamson, Timothy (2002), ‗Necessary Existents‘ (pp. 233–51), Royal Institute of

Philosophy Supplement, Vol. 51

Wright, Crispin (1992) ‗On Putnam‘s Proof that we are Not Brains in a Vat‘ (pp. 67-94),

Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 92