quong-the role of public reason

34
1 The Role of Public Reason * Jonathan Quong October 10, 2015 We disagree about how to live. We disagree, for example, about which God, if any, to worship, about sexual morality, about recreational drug use, and about whether certain artists’ work is obscene and should be banned. There are always some people who aim to resolve these disagreements through the use of coercion: they aspire to use the coercive power of the state to impose their views about how we ought to live on those who disagree. Liberals typically reject this approach—they hold that it’s wrong or impermissible to use coercion to impose one’s views about religion or the good life on those who disagree. Some believe this liberal attitude is best explained by a particular view of public reason. In the most general sense, public reason requires that the moral or political rules that regulate our common life be, in some sense, justifiable or acceptable to all those persons to whom the rules purport to apply. Some liberals appeal to a particular version of this idea to explain the wrongness of coercively imposing one’s views about how best to live: Coercion: Coercion (defined broadly to include conditional threats or the actual use of physical force) is only permissible or legitimate when exercised on the basis of reasons that the subjects of coercion can * I presented a version of this paper to Joseph Raz’s seminar at Columbia, and I’m very grateful to Joseph and all the other participants for their penetrating comments and questions. Thanks also to Tom Sinclair and Rebecca Stone for detailed comments on an earlier draft.

Upload: luis-echegollen

Post on 04-Jan-2016

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Una discusión en torno al papel de la razón pública en el debate político contemporáneo.

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  1  

The  Role  of  Public  Reason*  

 

Jonathan  Quong  

October  10,  2015  

 

We  disagree  about  how  to  live.  We  disagree,  for  example,  about  which  God,  if  

any,  to  worship,  about  sexual  morality,  about  recreational  drug  use,  and  about  

whether  certain  artists’  work  is  obscene  and  should  be  banned.  There  are  always  

some  people  who  aim  to  resolve  these  disagreements  through  the  use  of  

coercion:  they  aspire  to  use  the  coercive  power  of  the  state  to  impose  their  views  

about  how  we  ought  to  live  on  those  who  disagree.  Liberals  typically  reject  this  

approach—they  hold  that  it’s  wrong  or  impermissible  to  use  coercion  to  impose  

one’s  views  about  religion  or  the  good  life  on  those  who  disagree.  Some  believe  

this  liberal  attitude  is  best  explained  by  a  particular  view  of  public  reason.  In  the  

most  general  sense,  public  reason  requires  that  the  moral  or  political  rules  that  

regulate  our  common  life  be,  in  some  sense,  justifiable  or  acceptable  to  all  those  

persons  to  whom  the  rules  purport  to  apply.  Some  liberals  appeal  to  a  particular  

version  of  this  idea  to  explain  the  wrongness  of  coercively  imposing  one’s  views  

about  how  best  to  live:  

 

Coercion:  Coercion  (defined  broadly  to  include  conditional  threats  or  the  

actual  use  of  physical  force)  is  only  permissible  or  legitimate  when  

exercised  on  the  basis  of  reasons  that  the  subjects  of  coercion  can  

                                                                                               *  I  presented  a  version  of  this  paper  to  Joseph  Raz’s  seminar  at  Columbia,  and  I’m  very  grateful  to  Joseph  and  all  the  other  participants  for  their  penetrating  comments  and  questions.  Thanks  also  to  Tom  Sinclair  and  Rebecca  Stone  for  detailed  comments  on  an  earlier  draft.  

Page 2: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  2  

reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse.  Coercion  is,  in  this  way,  special—other  

methods  of  influencing  people  do  not  stand  in  need  of  public  justification.  

 

The  role  of  public  reason,  on  this  view,  is  to  regulate  the  use  of  coercion.  Thomas  

Nagel  and  Charles  Larmore,  among  others,  endorse  versions  of  this  principle.  

  But  some  think  this  principle  doesn’t  go  far  enough.  They  argue  for  a  

more  expansive  view  of  public  reason  as  regulating  all  of  social  morality:  

 

Social  Morality:  Moral  demands  only  have  authority  over  others  when  

made  on  the  basis  of  reasons  that  the  subjects  of  the  demands  can  

reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse.  All  interpersonal  moral  rules  or  

demands  thus  stand  in  need  of  public  justification.  

 

Gerald  Gaus  is  the  main  proponent  of  this  more  expansive  view  of  public  

reason’s  role.  

  I  believe  both  these  views  are  mistaken.  The  former  is  too  narrow,  while  

the  latter  is  too  broad.  Coercion  is  not  the  only  thing  that  stands  in  need  of  public  

justification,  but  public  reason  is  not  so  expansive  as  to  regulate  the  whole  of  

social  morality.  Instead  I  defend  an  alternative  account  of  public  reason’s  role.  

Every  well-­‐‑functioning  society  depends  on  a  set  of  widely  accepted  rules  that  

define  the  terms  on  which  we  interact  with  one  another.  These  terms  include  an  

account  of  individual  rights  and  liberties,  an  account  of  how  political  power  can  

be  obtained  and  exercised,  and  an  account  of  how  the  distribution  of  property  

and  other  advantages  and  disadvantages  arising  from  our  society  is  to  be  

determined.  Although  there  may  be  many  other  social  or  moral  rules,  these  basic  

rules  are  typically  recognized  as  having  priority  over  other  considerations,  and  

whatever  differences  there  are  between  persons,  these  are  the  rules  to  which  all  

Page 3: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  3  

persons  are  expected  to  adhere.  I  argue  that  the  role  of  public  reason  is  to  

regulate  the  content  of  these  rules,  that  is,  to  define  the  terms  of  public  or  social  

justice.  

The  paper  is  structured  as  follows.  Section  I  briefly  sketches  some  key  

issues  for  proponents  of  public  reason.  Sections  II  and  III  analyze,  respectively,  

Coercion  and  Social  Morality.  Section  IV  presents  my  account  of  the  role  of  public  

reason,  Justice,  and  section  V  addresses  some  objections.  

But  before  turning  to  the  main  arguments,  let  me  make  a  few  clarificatory  

remarks.  First,  the  main  topic  of  this  paper  is  the  role  of  public  reason,  by  which  I  

mean  the  purpose  or  function  of  public  reason—what  it’s  supposed  to  do.  But,  

unsurprisingly,  any  view  about  the  role  of  public  reason  will  have  implications  

for  other  closely  related  questions.  For  example,  the  role  of  public  reason  is  very  

closely  linked  to  the  scope  of  public  reason,  that  is,  the  range  of  topics  to  which  

the  constraints  of  public  reason  must  directly  apply.  One’s  view  about  the  role  of  

public  reason  is  also  likely  to  be  tightly  connected  to  the  issue  of  public  reason’s  

moral  basis:  the  underlying  justification  for  public  reason.    

Second,  and  relatedly,  this  paper  does  not  provide  a  comprehensive  

defense  of  the  idea  of  public  reason,  nor  does  it  address  many  of  the  other  

important  questions  relevant  to  a  full  account  of  public  reason.  Of  course  I  hope  

that  my  account  of  public  reason’s  role  is  helpful  in  showing  why  the  idea  of  

public  reason  is  compelling,  and  why  certain  prominent  objections  pressed  

against  it  are  not  necessarily  successful,  but  this  paper  doesn’t  aim  to  persuade  

those  who  see  the  idea  of  public  reason  as  fundamentally  misguided.        

 

I  

The  idea  of  public  reason  is  rooted  in  a  particular  view  of  persons  as  free  and  

equal.  We  are  free  in  the  sense  that  no  person  is  our  natural  ruler  or  moral  

Page 4: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  4  

superior—no  person  is  naturally  in  a  position  to  command  our  obedience  or  tell  

us  how  we  must  live.  We  are  equal  because  we  are  each  free  in  this  way.  How  

then,  can  it  ever  be  permissible  or  legitimate  for  some  people  to  require  that  

others  conform  to  some  rule,  or  even  use  coercion  to  enforce  particular  rules?  Of  

course  this  question  would  not  be  difficult  if  we  were  always  in  agreement  about  

what  to  do  and  how  to  live,  but  in  the  face  of  deep  and  permanent  

disagreement,1  how  can  any  interpersonal  rules  (I  use  this  term  as  a  placeholder,  

for  now,  in  order  to  be  neutral  regarding  the  role  of  public  reason)  be  consistent  

with  the  freedom  and  equality  of  persons?  

  Proponents  of  public  reason  believe  rules  can  be  consistent  with  the  

freedom  and  equality  of  persons  when  those  rules  are,  in  some  sense,  acceptable  

or  justifiable  to  all  those  to  whom  the  rules  purportedly  apply.  Exactly  why  rules  

that  meet  this  standard  are  consistent  with  the  freedom  and  equality  of  persons  

is  the  subject  of  dispute  amongst  proponents  of  public  reason,  and  I  will  

postpone  any  further  discussion  of  this  question  for  now.  Instead  I  want  to  make  

a  few  brief  observations  about  public  reason  that  will  be  useful  for  the  discussion  

to  follow.  

  First,  proponents  of  public  reason  do  not  take  people  as  they  are.  Real  

people  may  make  simple  inferential  errors,  they  may  hold  morally  repugnant  or  

irrational  beliefs,  or  they  may  be  driven  by  narrow  self-­‐‑interest  or  prejudice.  

Proponents  of  public  reason  thus  always  engage  in  a  certain  amount  of  

idealization.  The  constituency  of  persons  to  whom  rules  must  be  acceptable  or  

justifiable  can  be  idealized  epistemically,  morally,  or  both.  The  challenge  for                                                                                                  1  All  accounts  of  public  reason  make  some  assumption  about  the  permanence  of  pluralism  or  disagreement  regarding  religious,  philosophical,  and  ethical  ideas.  Proponents  of  public  reason  also  typically  assume  that  this  disagreement  is  reasonable  in  the  sense  of  being  the  result  of  sincere  and  conscientious  efforts  of  reasonable  and  rational  people  to  reach  answers  about  religion,  morality,  and  ethics  under  free  conditions,  rather  than  being  the  product  of  prejudice,  irrationality,  or  narrow  self-­‐‑interest.  

Page 5: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  5  

proponents  of  public  reason  is  not  difficult  to  anticipate.  The  more  one  idealizes  

the  constituency  of  persons  to  whom  the  rules  must  be  justifiable,  the  easier  it  

will  be  to  get  determinate  results  that  also  seem  attractive,  but  this  may  come  at  a  

steep  cost:  highly  idealized  accounts  of  the  constituency  may  seem  so  detached  

from  what  real  persons  are  like  that  it  may  be  unclear  in  what  sense  the  resulting  

rules  are  really  acceptable  or  justifiable  to  the  actual  persons  who  are  bound  by  

them.  Alternatively,  accounts  of  public  reason  that  engage  in  very  limited  

degrees  of  idealization  may  seem  to  have  greater  application  to  people  as  they  

are,  but  such  accounts  may  struggle  to  yield  any  determinate  rules  that  are  

acceptable  to  everyone  while  also  being  consistent  with  minimal  moral  

standards.  I  will  return  to  this  issue  in  the  concluding  section.  

  This  issue  of  idealization  is  closely  connected  to  what  it  means  for  a  

proposed  rule  to  be  acceptable  or  justifiable.  If  the  constituency  of  persons  to  

whom  our  rules  must  be  justifiable  is  sufficiently  idealized,  then  public  reason  

may  entail  that  all  successful  justifications  are  unanimous;  if  a  rule  has  been  

justified  to  one  member  of  the  constituency  it  will  be  justified  to  all  since  all  

members  have  been  idealized  to  the  point  where  they  share  the  same  set  of  

beliefs  and  priorities.  But  accounts  of  public  reason  that  engage  in  less  

idealization  may  not  have  this  feature—if  each  real  person  to  whom  some  rule  

applies  is  only  moderately  idealized,  then  a  given  rule  may  be  justifiable  or  

acceptable  to  some  members  of  the  constituency,  but  not  others.    

Relatedly,  accounts  of  public  reason  that  engage  in  less  idealization  are  

more  likely  to  allow  for  convergence  forms  of  public  reason.  Some  rule,  R,  has  

been  justified  via  convergence  when  R  is  acceptable  or  justifiable  to  different  

members  of  the  constituency  for  entirely  different  and  non-­‐‑shared  reasons.  For  

example,  R  might  be  justifiable  to  A  on  the  basis  of  A’s  Catholicism,  whereas  R  

might  be  justifiable  to  B  on  the  basis  of  her  utilitarianism,  and  so  on.  Consensus  

Page 6: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  6  

accounts  of  public  reason,  by  contrast,  are  those  that  require  the  reasons  in  

support  of  a  given  rule  to  be  ones  that  all  members  of  the  constituency  recognize  

as  sound  considerations  that  are,  at  a  minimum,  plausibly  sufficient  to  justify  R.  

The  issues  I’ve  just  described  are  by  no  means  the  only  areas  of  dispute  

amongst  those  who  favor  some  version  of  public  reason,  but  they  are  central  

areas  of  disagreement,  and  their  relevance  will  hopefully  be  apparent  in  the  

discussion  that  follows.  

 

II  

Let’s  return  to  the  first  view  about  the  role  of  public  reason:  

 

Coercion:  Coercion  (defined  broadly  to  include  conditional  threats  or  the  

actual  use  of  physical  force)  is  only  permissible  or  legitimate  when  

exercised  on  the  basis  of  reasons  that  the  subjects  of  coercion  can  

reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse.  Coercion  is,  in  this  way,  special—other  

methods  of  influencing  people  do  not  stand  in  need  of  public  justification.  

 

This  view  can  explain  many  core  liberal  convictions,  in  particular,  why  it  

is  wrong  to  use  the  coercive  power  of  the  state  to  enforce  particular  moral  or  

religious  views  on  dissenting  minorities.  Coercion  might  also  appear  consistent  

with  our  attitudes  towards  non-­‐‑coercive  behavior.  For  example,  though  it  would  

be  wrong  for  me  to  coerce  you  on  the  basis  of  religious  beliefs  that  you  do  not  

share,  it  does  not  seem  similarly  objectionable  for  me  to  refuse  to  marry  you  on  

the  basis  of  religious  beliefs  that  you  do  not  share,  or  for  me  to  give  my  money  to  

charitable  organizations  that  share  my  religious  convictions  and  refuse  to  give  it  

to  those  that  do  not.  Because  the  latter  actions  are  not  coercive,  I  can  legitimately  

be  guided  by  my  own  controversial  religious  views  in  deciding  what  to  do—my  

Page 7: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  7  

actions  do  not  need  to  be  grounded  in  reasons  that  others  can  reasonably  be  

expected  to  endorse.2    

But  while  Coercion  may  cohere  with  many  liberal  convictions,  it  faces  a  

number  of  serious  problems.3  What  these  objections  demonstrate  is  not  that  

coercion  does  not  stand  in  need  of  public  justification,  but  rather:  (i)  coercion  is  

not  the  only  thing  that  stands  in  need  of  public  justification,  and  (ii)  proponents  

of  Coercion  have  failed  to  identify  a  compelling  and  coherent  rationale  for  

restricting  the  role  of  public  reason  to  coercion.  

To  begin,  there  are  various  examples  where  Coercion  has  apparently  

troubling  implications.4  Suppose  our  country  has  a  state-­‐‑run  lottery,  and  the  

profits  from  the  lottery  are  used  to  subsidize  the  Catholic  Church  and  Catholic  

charities.  The  rationale  offered  for  this  policy  is  that  Catholicism  is  the  one  true  

religion.  The  funds  are  not  coercively  obtained,  but  I  think  many  of  the  same  

liberals  who  object  to  the  coercive  imposition  of  religious  views  will  find  this  use  

of  the  lottery  funds  to  be  seriously  objectionable,  even  if  less  troubling  than  

outright  coercion.  Or  imagine  a  society  where  laws  are  debated  and  determined  

democratically,  but  all  citizens  always  internalize  and  voluntarily  comply  with  

the  rules  issued  by  the  government  even  when  they  believe  them  to  be  deeply  

mistaken  or  lacking  a  coherent  rationale.  They  do  so  because  they  believe  they  

are  required  either  as  a  matter  of  justice  or  legitimacy  to  comply  with  a  

democratic  government’s  demands.  Since  these  rules  will  be  followed  as  a  result  

of  internalization  rather  than  via  the  threat  of  coercion  (there  is  no  police  force  or  

penal  system),  proponents  of  Coercion  must  deny  that  the  fundamental                                                                                                  2  My  actions  might  still,  of  course,  be  open  to  criticism,  even  if  they  are  permissible.  3  For  other  critiques  of  Coercion  see  Colin  Bird,  ‘Coercion  and  Public  Justification,’  Politics,  Philosophy,  &  Economics  13  (2014),  189-­‐‑214;  or  Andrew  Lister,  Public  Reason  and  Political  Community  (London:  Bloomsbury,  2014),  chapter  3.  4  These  examples  are  from  my  ‘On  the  Idea  of  Public  Reason,’  in  A  Companion  to  Rawls,  Jon  Mandle  and  David  Reidy,  eds.  (Oxford:  Wiley-­‐‑Blackwell,  2014),  272-­‐‑273.  

Page 8: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  8  

institutions,  rights,  and  laws  in  this  imagined  society  ought  to  be  regulated  by  

the  idea  of  public  reason.  

I  think  these  examples  provide  reasons  to  doubt  that  Coercion  is  correct,  

but  such  examples  are  not  decisive.  Proponents  of  Coercion  can  respond  by  biting  

the  bullet,  and  insist  that  public  reason  does  not  apply  in  these  cases.  They  might  

also  argue  that  other  moral  principles  can  explain  what’s  wrong  with  the  

government’s  behavior  in  the  first  case,  or  why  our  imagined  non-­‐‑coercive  state  

ought  to  abstain  from  passing  laws  that  depend  on  controversial  moral  or  

religious  rationales.  I  have  my  doubts  about  these  replies  on  behalf  of  Coercion,  

but  since  I  think  there  are  deeper  problems,  I  won’t  pursue  this  line  of  argument  

further.    

A  second  problem  emerges  when  we  try  and  identify  which  acts  or  rules  

qualify  as  coercive,  and  why  there  should  be  a  presumption  that  such  acts  or  

rules  are  impermissible  unless  publicly  justified.5  Consider  the  following  cases:  

 

Albert  Gets  a  Date:   Albert  tells  Betty  that  unless  she  agrees  to  go  on  a  

date  with  him,  he  will  destroy  a  painting  that  belongs  

to  Betty,  a  painting  that  she  loves  very  much,  but  

which  has  no  market  value.  

 

Carl  Gets  a  Date:   Carl  tells  Debra  that  unless  she  agrees  to  go  on  a  date  

with  him,  he  will  destroy  a  painting  that  belongs  to  

Carl,  a  painting  that  Debra  loves  very  much.  

 

                                                                                               5  I  originally  developed  this  objection  in  an  online  commentary  I  offered  on  a  paper  by  Kevin  Vallier  and  Gerald  Gaus.  See:  http://publicreason.net/wp-­‐‑content/PPPS/Fall2008/JQuong1.pdf    

Page 9: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  9  

Most  will  agree  that  Albert’s  action  is  coercive:  threatening  to  destroy  someone  

else’s  property  unless  they  do  something  that  they  otherwise  would  not  do  

seems  like  a  paradigm  case  of  coercion.  But  what  about  Carl’s  behavior?  I  suspect  

that  many  people  will  deny  that  Carl’s  behavior  is  coercive  in  the  same  way.  If  

Carl’s  attempt  to  get  a  date  with  Debra  is  not  coercive  in  the  way  that  Albert’s  is,  

this  seems  to  show  that  our  beliefs  about  whether  a  given  action  is  coercive  

depends  on  our  prior  beliefs  about  rights  or  justice.  If  Carl’s  action  is  not  

coercive,  it  must  be  because  Carl,  unlike  Albert,  is  acting  within  his  rights.  He  is  

only  in  threatening  to  destroy  his  own  painting,  not  someone  else’s.  Determining  

whether  or  not  someone  is  acting  within  his  rights  thus  might  seem  to  be  one  of  

the  variables  necessary  to  decide  if  an  act  is  coercive.    

This  pair  of  examples  poses  a  dilemma  for  proponents  of  Coercion.  On  the  

one  hand,  a  proponent  could  agree  the  first  case  is  an  instance  of  coercion,  and  

the  latter  is  not,  and  thus  only  the  former  is  regulated  by  public  reason.  This  

response  effectively  concedes  that  coercion  is  a  moralized  notion—that  we  

cannot  know  whether  something  is  coercive  until  we  already  have  a  substantial  

set  of  background  beliefs  about  justice  and  individual  rights.  But  to  make  this  

concession  seems  fatal  to  Coercion  since  it  precludes  public  reason  from  playing  

any  role  in  determining  the  content  of  all  those  individual  rights  and  principles  

of  justice  that  are  prerequisites  for  understanding  whether  a  given  act  or  rule  is  

coercive.  On  this  view,  public  reason  would  seem  to  arrive  far  too  late  in  the  

justificatory  process  to  play  the  sort  of  substantive  role  attributed  to  it  by  

proponents  of  Coercion.  Any  apparently  coercive  policy  could  be  justified  by  

appeal  to  a  controversial  religious  or  ethical  doctrine,  and  declared  exempt  from  

the  standards  of  public  reason  by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  the  policy  determines  

Page 10: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  10  

what  rights  individuals  possess,  and  thus  is  not  coercive  in  the  relevant  

moralized  sense.6  

On  the  other  hand,  the  proponent  of  Coercion  could  insist  that  the  two  

examples  are  in  fact  analogous;  that  Carl,  just  like  Albert,  is  guilty  of  trying  to  

obtain  a  date  via  coercion.  On  this  view  coercion  could  be  defined  by  reference  to  

the  severity  of  the  harm  (physical,  psychological,  financial)  that  the  coercer  

threatens  to  impose,  regardless  of  whether  or  not  the  coercer  has  the  moral  right  

to  impose  this  harm.  Since  (we  can  assume)  the  harm  Carl  threatens  to  impose  on  

Debra  is  equivalent  to  the  harm  Albert  threatens  to  impose  on  Betty,  then  if  

Albert’s  act  is  coercive,  so  is  Carl’s.    

Even  if  we  set  aside  any  doubts  about  the  plausibility  of  this  account  of  

coercion,  this  latter  reply  will  not  serve  as  an  effective  defense  of  Coercion.  The  

problem  with  this  reply  is  that  it’s  not  plausible  to  suppose  that  Carl’s  act  ought  

to  be  subject  to  the  same  justificatory  burden  as  Albert’s.  Because  the  painting  

belongs  to  Carl,  he  surely  ought  to  be  able  to  decide  what  to  do  with  the  painting  

without  having  to  publicly  justify  his  decision.  Consider  a  different  case.  

Suppose  I  have  justly  acquired  some  wealth,  and  I  now  make  the  following  

threat  to  my  local  pastor:  stop  condemning  same-­‐‑sex  marriage  in  your  sermons,  

                                                                                               6  A  proponent  of  Coercion  might  try  to  blunt  the  force  of  this  first  horn  of  the  dilemma  by  conceding  that  although  coercion  is  a  moralized  notion,  it  can  be  defined  relative  to  a  fairly  minimal  view  about  natural  rights  against  physical  force.  Since  most  political  rules  do  involve  threatened  transgressions  against  individuals’  natural  rights  against  physical  force  (there  is  always  the  threat  of  criminal  sanction  lurking  in  the  background),  there  will  thus  still  be  a  large  role  for  public  reason  to  play.  This  response,  however,  does  not  seem  promising  for  two  reasons.  First,  it  ties  the  proponent  of  Coercion  to  a  particular  view  about  natural  rights  against  force,  and  thus  disputes  about  whether  this  view  of  individual  rights  is  sound  cannot  be  resolved  by  appeal  to  public  reason.  Second,  the  proponent  of  Coercion  seems  committed  to  the  view  that  coercive  acts  stand  in  need  of  public  justification  because  such  acts  threaten  the  natural  rights  of  persons.  But  then  it’s  open  to  opponents  of  Coercion  to  argue  (plausibly)  that  the  natural  rights  of  persons  include  more  than  claims  against  physical  force,  they  also  include  positive  rights  to  be  provided  with  urgently  needed  aid  when  it’s  easy  to  do  so,  in  which  case  failures  to  aid  would  also  stand  in  need  of  justification,  regardless  of  whether  they  are  coercive.  

Page 11: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  11  

or  I  will  leave  my  small  fortune  to  the  local  animal  shelter  rather  than  your  

church.  If  we  adopt  the  non-­‐‑moralized  account  of  coercion,  my  threat  is  coercive,  

but  it  seems  very  strange  to  insist  that  I  cannot  threaten  my  pastor  in  this  way  

unless  I  my  threat  can  be  justified  to  him  on  the  basis  of  public  reasons.    

But  let’s  set  aside  this  concern  about  the  formulation  of  coercion  and  turn  

our  attention  to  the  main  Kantian  rationale  offered  for  Coercion.  Charles  Larmore  

says  that  “to  respect  another  person  as  an  end  is  to  require  that  coercive  or  

political  principles  be  as  justifiable  to  that  person  as  they  presumably  are  to  us”.7  

Conversely,  “if  we  try  to  bring  about  conformity  to  a  rule  of  conduct  solely  by  

the  threat  of  force,  we  shall  be  treating  persons  merely  as  means,  as  objects  of  

coercion,  and  not  also  as  ends,  engaging  with  their  distinctive  capacity  as  

persons”.8  Similarly,  Thomas  Nagel  says  that  “if  you  force  someone  to  serve  an  

end  that  he  cannot  be  given  adequate  reason  to  share,  you  are  treating  him  as  a  

mere  means—even  if  the  end  is  his  own  good,  as  you  see  it  but  he  doesn’t.  In  

view  of  the  coercive  character  of  the  state,  the  requirement  becomes  a  condition  

of  political  legitimacy”.9    

I  think  there  are  at  least  two  problems  with  this  rationale.  First,  I  do  not  

think  it’s  true  that  whenever  you  coerce  someone  to  serve  an  end  he  cannot  be  

given  adequate  reason  to  share,  you  treat  that  person  as  a  mere  means,  if  by  

“mere  means”  we  mean  an  object  that  has  no  moral  claims  or  standing  of  its  

own.  As  Derek  Parfit  has  shown,  we  can  coerce  or  harm  others—even  when  

those  others  lack  sufficient  reasons  to  share  our  ends—and  yet  still  treat  those  we  

coerce  or  harm  as  much  more  than  mere  means.10  Suppose,  for  example,  I  force  

you  to  help  me  rescue  a  boy  that  I  believe  to  be  the  incarnation  of  the  Buddha,                                                                                                  7  Charles  Larmore,  “The  Moral  Basis  of  Political  Liberalism,”  Journal  of  Philosophy  96  (1999),  608.  8  Ibid.,  607.  9  Thomas  Nagel,  Equality  and  Partiality  (New  York:  Oxford  University  Press,  1991),  159.  10  Derek  Parfit,  On  What  Matters:  Volume  I  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2011),  222-­‐‑223.  

Page 12: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  12  

and  this  rescue  costs  you  your  leg,  but  further  suppose  that  I  am  going  to  lose  my  

own  life  in  this  rescue.  I  could  save  my  life  if  I  imposed  further  harm  on  you  (say  

the  loss  of  another  leg),  but  I  don’t  do  this  because  I  believe  doing  so  would  be  a  

wrongful  imposition  on  your  freedom;  I  think  you  can  be  forced  to  sacrifice  your  

leg  for  a  God,  but  not  for  a  regular  person  like  me.  It  does  not  seem  right  to  say  I  

treat  you  as  a  mere  means,  as  a  mere  object  to  be  used  however  I  see  fit,  since  I  

recognize  significant  moral  constraints  on  the  ways  I  may  permissibly  treat  you.  

A  proponent  of  the  Kantian  rationale  for  Coercion  may  reply  that  this  

objection  misunderstands  what  she  means  by  treating  someone  as  a  “mere  

means”.  She  does  not  literally  mean  treating  a  person  as  if  he  were  an  inanimate  

object;  rather,  she  means  forcing  someone  to  serve  an  end  that  he  does  not  have  

adequate  reason  to  share.  But  if  this  is  what  it  means  to  treat  others  as  a  mere  

means,  the  rationale  becomes  an  empty  tautology:  whenever  you  coerce  someone  

to  serve  an  end  he  cannot  be  given  adequate  reason  to  share,  you  coerce  someone  

to  serve  an  end  he  cannot  be  given  adequate  reason  to  share.    

But  even  if  we  set  this  objection  aside,  the  proposed  Kantian  rationale  also  

fails  to  establish  that  coercion  uniquely  stands  in  need  of  public  justification.  

Coercion,  we  can  assume,  involves  either  threats  made  with  the  aim  of  getting  

another  person  to  perform  or  refrain  from  performing  some  act,  or  else  the  use  of  

violence  or  force  against  others.  But  suppose,  for  example,  that  I  live  upstream  

and  you  live  downstream  along  a  river.11  We  both  rely  on  fishing  the  river  to  

survive.  I  construct  a  net  that  catches  all  the  fish  upstream  and  prevents  any  of  

the  fish  from  reaching  you  many  miles  downstream.  I  have  no  intention  of  

getting  you  to  do  anything,  nor  do  I  use  violence  or  force  to  take  anything  from  

you:  I’m  just  trying  to  catch  as  many  fish  as  I  can.  But  doing  so  means  you  will  

                                                                                               11  I  borrow  the  basic  form  of  the  example  from  Kok-­‐‑Chor  Tan,  Justice,  Institutions,  and  Luck:  The  Site,  Ground,  and  Scope  of  Equality  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2012),  162.  

Page 13: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  13  

starve  to  death.  Or  suppose  that  in  order  to  construct  a  temple  to  my  God,  I  use  

chemicals  that  seep  into  the  ground  under  the  temple,  and  eventually  affect  the  

soil  you  use  for  farming,  rendering  it  infertile,  which  leaves  you  facing  

starvation.  I  foresee  this  consequence,  but  I  am  not  trying  to  get  you  to  perform  

any  particular  act,  and  it  seems  a  stretch  to  say  that  I  use  force  or  violence  against  

you.12  I  find  it  difficult  to  see  why  the  injunction  not  to  treat  others  as  mere  

means  should  not  apply  in  these  cases  as  well.  It’s  true  that  in  these  cases  

harming  you  is  not  instrumentally  useful  to  me,  but  I  may  still  treat  you  as  an  

object  with  no  substantial  moral  standing.  These  cases  seem  sufficiently  similar  

to  cases  of  wrongful  coercion  where  the  coercion  cannot  be  justified  to  those  who  

are  coerced:  in  my  examples  you  are  treated  in  ways  that  do  not  seem  justifiable  

to  you,  and  which  result  in  serious  and  (let’s  stipulate)  easily  avoidable  harm.    

Of  course  the  proponent  of  the  Kantian  rationale  can  insist  that  my  cases  

are  different—that  the  special  wrongness  of  treating  others  as  mere  means  is  

restricted  to  instances  where  you  use  force  to  get  others  to  act  in  particular  ways.  

It’s  the  attempt  to  bend  a  person’s  will  to  your  own  that  is  uniquely  subject  to  the  

requirement  of  public  reason—not  more  general  instances  of  harming  or  

negatively  affecting  others.  But  I  think  this  response  depends  on  a  very  specific  

and  controversial  ethical  doctrine—one  that  makes  our  wills  or  the  maxims  on  

which  we  act  of  special  moral  importance,  perhaps  the  only  thing  that  grounds  

our  moral  worth  or  status.  This  is  a  Kantian  view,  but  many  reasonable  people  

do  not  accept  this  account  of  our  moral  worth.  Insofar  as  one  of  the  main  aims  of  

public  reason  is  to  provide  an  account  of  interpersonal  justification  that  

reasonable  persons  can  all  be  expected  to  endorse,  it  seems  self-­‐‑defeating  for                                                                                                  12  Of  course  one  might  insist  these  cases  do  involve  coercion  by  appealing  to  a  moralized  baseline  to  determine  what  counts  as  force  or  violence  (i.e.  perhaps  I  am  stealing  or  damaging  your  property  and  thus  using  force  against  you)  but  this  will  not  be  of  much  help  to  the  proponent  of  Coercion—the  same  problem  arises  here  as  it  did  in  the  examples  involving  Albert  and  Carl.  

Page 14: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  14  

proponents  of  public  reason  to  rely  on  such  a  narrow  account  of  what  is  morally  

important  about  persons.  But  without  this  narrow  account,  the  appeal  to  the  

wrongness  of  treating  others  merely  as  a  means  will  not  vindicate  a  unique  focus  

on  coercion.    

In  sum,  Coercion  seems  deeply  flawed.  It  has  counterintuitive  implications  

about  the  exercise  of  political  power  when  that  power  is  not  coercive,  it  does  not  

look  plausible  regardless  of  whether  we  adopt  a  moralized  or  non-­‐‑moralized  

account  of  coercion,  and  its  Kantian  rationale  does  not  seem  successful.  

 

III  

Gerald  Gaus  has  recently  offered  a  very  different  picture  of  the  role  of  public  

reason.13  He  begins  with  this  question:  can  social  morality’s  alleged  authority  be  

reconciled  with  a  conception  of  others  as  being  free  and  equal  interpreters  of  

morality;  as  each  having  equal  standing  to  decide  what  is  true  or  false  with  

regard  to  morality’s  requirements?  As  he  puts  it,  

 

Because  we  recognize  other  moral  persons  as  free  and  

equal,  having  authority—perhaps  we  should  say  

“moral  sovereignty”—to  interpret  their  own  moral  

obligations  for  themselves,  our  claims  to  have  

standing  to  command  that  they  comply  with  our  view  

of  the  demands  of  morality  appears  to  manifest  

disrespect  for  them  as  equal  interpreters  of  morality.14  

 

                                                                                               13  Gerald  Gaus,  The  Order  of  Public  Reason:  A  Theory  of  Freedom  and  Morality  in  a  Diverse  and  Bounded  World  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  University  Press,  2011).  14  Ibid.,  17.  

Page 15: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  15  

Given  pervasive  disagreement  about  morality,  how  can  we  engage  in  the  

practice  of  morality—the  regular  practice  of  making  demands  on  others  and  even  

enforcing  those  demands—in  a  way  that  also  manages  to  respect  others  as  free  

and  equal  interpreters  of  morality?  Gaus’s  answer  is  that  a  justified  social  

morality  will  only  make  demands  of  us  when  we  already  have  sufficient  reasons  

to  act  in  accordance  with  its  demands,  that  is,  when  the  demands  of  social  

morality  can  be  justified  to  us.  This  is  how  we  can  treat  each  other  as  free  and  

equal  interpreters  of  morality’s  demands.  Indeed,  on  Gaus’s  account,  public  

reason  is  an  implicit  and  essential  feature  of  our  everyday  moral  practices.15  In  

particular  the  main  reactive  attitudes  associated  with  interpersonal  morality—

including  blame,  indignation,  and  resentment—only  make  sense  when  the  moral  

demands  we  make  of  others  can  be  justified  by  appeal  to  reasons  that  those  

others  have;  that  is,  to  reasons  a  moderately  idealized  agent  would  endorse  from  

within  the  evaluative  perspective  of  the  person  to  whom  the  demand  is  made  

(throughout  the  rest  of  this  section,  following  Gaus,  this  is  what  I  shall  mean  

when  talking  about  the  reasons  a  person  “has”).  Gaus  thus  endorses  

 

Social  Morality:  Moral  demands  only  have  authority  over  others  when  

made  on  the  basis  of  reasons  that  the  subjects  of  the  demands  can  

reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse.  All  interpersonal  moral  rules  or  

demands  thus  stand  in  need  of  public  justification.  

 

Gaus’  theory  of  public  reason  is  very  rich  and  complex,  and  my  aim  here  is  not  to  

evaluate  his  whole  account,  or  even  his  account  specifically.16  Rather,  I  focus  on  

                                                                                               15  Ibid.,  184.  16  I  offer  a  brief  critique  of  one  of  its  central  elements  in,  ‘What  is  the  Point  of  Public  Reason?’  Philosophical  Studies  170  (2014),  533-­‐‑545.  

Page 16: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  16  

two  reasons  to  doubt  that  an  expansive  account  of  public  reason’s  role,  like  Social  

Morality,  is  correct.  

First,  Social  Morality  seems  implausibly  broad.  When  adherents  of  a  

religious  community  hold  each  other  to  account  for  failing  to  live  up  to  their  

religion’s  requirements,  the  members  of  the  religious  community  treat  these  

requirements  as  being  authoritative,  but  not  necessarily  because  the  

requirements  pass  some  test  of  public  reason.  The  religious  requirements  are,  by  

their  nature,  controversial  and  not  grounded  in  public  reasons.    

A  proponent  of  Social  Morality  might  respond  that  this  misunderstands  

how  the  demand  for  public  justification  operates.  When  a  moral  demand  is  made  

of  everyone,  then  its  justification  must  eschew  controversial  religious  or  ethical  

doctrines  and  appeal  only  to  public  or  shared  reasons,17  but  when  a  moral  

demand  is  made  only  of  some  sub-­‐‑set,  like  the  members  of  a  particular  religious  

community,  then  the  demand  only  needs  to  be  justifiable  to  the  members  of  the  

community,  and  thus  controversial  or  sectarian  rationales  for  moral  demands  are  

perfectly  appropriate  within  particular  religious  or  ethical  communities.  

  I  don’t  find  this  response  persuasive.  I  think  it  misconstrues  the  way  the  

members  of  the  community  can  understand  the  basis  of  their  religious  or  moral  

requirements.  Members  of  particular  religious  and  ethical  communities  do  not  

necessarily  understand  their  practices  of  interpersonal  morality—blaming,  

resentment,  indignation,  holding  accountable—as  being  dependent  on  any  

notion  of  public  justifiability  even  when  the  constituency  of  persons  to  whom  the  

rules  must  be  justifiable  is  restricted  to  members  of  the  group.  Rather,  the  

members  of  many  such  communities  may  see  it  as  appropriate  to  hold  each  other  

                                                                                               17  Proponents  of  convergence  forms  of  public  reason  will  protest  that  shared  reasons  are  not  required  even  in  these  cases,  but  I  set  this  worry  aside  for  now.  

Page 17: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  17  

accountable  to  God’s  commandments,  or  religious  truth,  as  each  person  sees  it,  

regardless  of  whether  others  see  it  in  the  same  light.  

  A  proponent  of  Social  Morality  can  insist  that  there  is  a  second-­‐‑order  sense  

in  which  the  notion  of  public  justification  or  shared  reasons  operates  in  such  

cases.  All  the  members  of  the  community  agree  (at  some  level  of  idealization)  

that  members  of  the  community  can  hold  each  other  to  account  by  appealing  

directly  to  religious  truth  or  God’s  will,  and  so  while  the  first-­‐‑order  rationale  for  

some  alleged  requirement  may  not  meet  the  test  of  being  justifiable  to  others,  the  

more  general  framework  is  justifiable  to  each  member  of  the  community,  and  

this  is  what  vindicates  the  authority  of  the  more  specific  requirements  or  

commands.    

This  explanation  strikes  me  as  dubious,  however,  at  least  when  presented  

as  an  account  of  how  members  of  religious  or  other  ethical  communities  

necessarily  understand  their  own  moral  practices.  Of  course  a  proponent  of  Social  

Morality  might  insist  that  regardless  of  whether  the  members  of  a  community  

understand  their  moral  practices  in  this  way,  their  practices  must  have  this  

characteristic  in  order  for  some  member  A  to  properly  blame  B  or  hold  B  to  

account.  In  other  words,  if  some  higher  order  norm  such  as  “God’s  commands  

are  the  sole  basis  of  authoritative  moral  requirements”  is  not  justifiable  to  each  

member  of  the  community,  then  community  members  are  not  engaged  in  

legitimate  instances  of  blaming  or  holding  accountable  when  they  invoke  God’s  

commands  as  the  basis  of  blaming  others  or  holding  others  to  account.  But  this  

seems  a  very  large  bullet  for  the  proponent  of  Social  Morality  to  bite.18  I  don’t  

think  the  best  account  of  public  reason  should  be  committed  to  the  view  that  

                                                                                               18  Perhaps  particularly  for  Gaus,  who  emphasizes  the  importance  of  taking  the  actual  practices  of  social  morality  seriously  when  developing  our  philosophical  theories  of  morality.  See  for  example  Gaus,  Order  of  Public  Reason,  174.  

Page 18: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  18  

members  of  particular  religious  or  ethical  communities  cannot  legitimately  or  

properly  hold  each  other  to  account  or  blame  each  other  unless  their  particular  

community’s  moral  standards  are  justifiable  to  each  member  of  the  community—

this  imposes  the  idea  of  public  justification  on  aspects  of  our  moral  or  ethical  

lives  where  it  doesn’t  necessarily  belong.  Some  of  our  everyday  moral  practices  

do  not  depend  upon  or  presuppose  public  justification;  rather  they  seem  to  

depend  on  other  forms  of  justification,  including  direct  appeals  to  religious  or  

moral  truth.  

  The  preceding  objection  focuses  on  the  way  public  reason  may  not  

necessarily  regulate  the  moral  claims  we  make  on  each  other  within  certain  

religious  or  ethical  communities.  But  I  also  think  public  reason  does  not  regulate  

many  of  the  moral  claims  that  cross  sub-­‐‑group  boundaries.  Consider,  for  

example,  the  debate  that  two  people  from  different  religious  communities  might  

have  about  pre-­‐‑marital  sex.  Ernest  is  from  an  Evangelical  Christian  family,  and  

believes  pre-­‐‑marital  sex  to  be  morally  wrong.  Felicity  is  a  liberal  atheist,  and  

believes  sex  between  consenting  adults  is  not  wrong,  and  more  strongly,  she  

believes  it’s  a  very  good  thing  if  most  adults  have  pre-­‐‑marital  sex.  One  way  to  

characterize  their  dispute  is  that  they  disagree  about  the  scope  of  social  morality:  

Felicity  thinks  self-­‐‑regarding  choices  that  do  not  harm  others  are  essentially  

outside  the  scope  of  social  morality,  whereas  Ernest  holds  a  different  view.  But  of  

course  they  hold  different  views  about  the  scope  of  social  morality  because  they  

hold  different  views  about  the  underlying  grounds  of  moral  wrongdoing:  Ernest  

thinks  the  underlying  basis  is  God’s  will,  whereas  Felicity  thinks  moral  

wrongdoing  must  be  explicable  by  reference  to  some  setback  to  the  interests  of  

persons.  Ernest  blames  Felicity  for  engaging  in  and  encouraging  activity  he  sees  

as  wrongful,  and  Felicity  blames  Ernest  for  holding  what  she  sees  as  narrow-­‐‑

minded  and  Puritanical  views.  

Page 19: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  19  

  How  can  a  proponent  of  Social  Morality  make  sense  of  their  disagreement,  

and  the  reactive  attitudes  they  hold?  If  we  assume  that  Felicity’s  views  depend  

on  an  ethical  framework  that  Ernest  cannot  reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse  

(and  vice  versa)  then  the  proponent  of  Social  Morality  must  believe  that  Ernest  

and  Felicity  cannot  rightfully  hold  each  other  accountable  or  blame  each  other—

such  behavior  is  inconsistent  with  showing  due  respect  for  others  as  free  and  

equal  interpreters  of  morality’s  requirements.    

  This  conclusion  seems  hard  to  believe.  A  significant  part  of  moral  life  

consists  in  disagreements  like  the  kind  Ernest  and  Felicity  are  having.  We  often  

disagree  with  others  about  the  scope  of  social  morality,  as  well  as  the  underlying  

basis  of  moral  wrongdoing  and  rightness.  When  we  have  these  disagreements,  

and  when  we  hold  others  accountable  for  acting  on  and  holding  what  we  take  to  

be  false  and  morally  pernicious  views,  we  do  not  necessarily  treat  others  

disrespectfully,  nor  threaten  their  status  as  free  and  equal  interpreters  of  

morality’s  requirements.  Ernest  need  not  deny  that  Felicity  has  the  standing  to  

make  her  own  judgments  about  morality’s  requirements—I  don’t  think  he  needs  

to  be  acting  in  a  way  that  ought  to  trigger  public  justification.  Rather,  we  can  

imagine  Ernest  saying,  “Of  course  you  are  [in  some  sense  yet  to  be  defined]  at  

liberty  to  make  up  your  own  mind  about  sexual  morality,  but  I  think  you  are  

terribly  mistaken  in  the  judgments  you’ve  reached,  and  in  reaching  those  

judgments  and  acting  on  them  you  show  yourself  to  be,  at  least  in  one  sense,  a  

bad  person  who  acts  wrongly,  and  I  blame  you  for  that”.  And  Felicity  may  take  a  

similar  view  of  Ernest.  This  kind  of  moral  disagreement  is  an  essential  feature  of  

social  morality  in  a  pluralistic  society,  and  yet  because  it  involves  foundational  

disagreements  about  the  underlying  basis  of  morality,  it  cannot  be  regulated  by  

public  reason.  

Page 20: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  20  

  Not  all  moral  demands  and  reactive  attitudes  invoke  the  particular  kind  of  

demands  that  should  be  the  appropriate  object  of  public  reason.  Ernest  can  hold  

Felicity  accountable  for  her  (as  he  sees  it)  pernicious  views,  he  can  blame  her,  and  

even  shun  her,  while  still  respecting  Felicity  status  as  free  and  equal,  as  someone  

who  has  the  standing  to  make  her  own  determinations  about  sexual  morality.  He  

may  think  she  is  a  bad  person  who  violates  moral  requirements  in  a  way  that  

merits  criticism  and  condemnation,  but  if  he  recognizes  that  his  judgment  

depends  on  an  evaluative  perspective  Felicity  can  reasonably  reject,  and  thus  

recognizes  that  this  judgment  should  play  no  part  in  determining  Felicity  basic  

rights,  claims  over  property,  and  other  matters  of  basic  justice,  then  I  submit  that  

Ernest  shows  the  appropriate  respect  for  Betty’s  status  as  free  and  equal.  On  this  

account—which  I  develop  and  defend  in  the  following  sections—moral  

judgments  and  demands  only  need  to  be  publicly  justified  when  they  invoke  the  

special  status  reserved  for  justice.  

 

IV  

Let’s  begin  with  the  circumstances  that  give  rise  to  the  problem  to  which  I  

believe  public  reason  is  addressed.  The  circumstances  are  familiar—they  are  the  

circumstances  of  justice.  These  circumstances  are  characterized  by  a  conflict  as  

well  as  an  identity  of  interests.  As  Rawls  famously  explains,  “there  is  an  identity  

of  interests  since  social  cooperation  makes  possible  a  better  life  for  all  than  any  

would  have  if  each  were  to  live  solely  by  his  own  efforts.  There  is  a  conflict  of  

interests  since  persons  are  not  indifferent  as  to  how  the  greater  benefits  produced  

by  their  collaboration  are  distributed,  for  in  order  to  pursue  their  ends  they  each  

Page 21: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  21  

prefer  a  larger  share  to  a  lesser  share”.19  These  circumstances  give  rise  to  the  

special  problem  of  social  justice:    

 

A  set  of  principles  is  required  for  choosing  among  the  

various  social  arrangements  which  determine  this  

division  of  advantages  and  for  underwriting  an  

agreement  on  the  proper  distributive  shares.  These  are  

the  principles  of  social  justice:  they  provide  a  way  of  

assigning  rights  and  duties  in  the  basic  institutions  of  

society  and  they  define  the  appropriate  distribution  of  

the  benefits  and  burdens  of  social  cooperation.20  

 

This  is  the  problem  of  social  justice.  To  live  together  in  a  way  that  will  be  

mutually  beneficial,  there  must  be  rules,  generally  accepted  as  binding,  which  

allocate  individual  rights  and  duties,  and  determine  the  rightful  division  of  

advantages  and  disadvantages,  particularly  given  moderate  scarcity  of  resources  

and  the  fact  that  persons  are  not  purely  altruistic,  but  rather  have  their  own  

distinct  ends  they  wish  to  pursue.  A  conception  of  justice  provides  a  common  

point  of  view  from  which  competing  claims  can  be  adjudicated;  “one  may  think  

of  a  public  conception  of  justice  as  constituting  the  fundamental  charter  of  a  well-­‐‑

ordered  human  association”.21    

But  a  conception  of  justice  must  do  more  than  provide  a  commonly  

recognized  set  of  rules  for  allocating  rights  and  resources.  After  all,  authoritarian  

societies  ruled  by  tyrants  might  also  have  a  publicly  recognized  set  of  rules  that  

                                                                                               19  John  Rawls,  A  Theory  of  Justice:  Revised  Edition  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  1999),  4.  20  Ibid.,  4.  21  Ibid.,  5.  

Page 22: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  22  

perform  this  function  that  most  people  accept  as  binding.  Instead,  we  want  our  

conception  of  justice  to  be  one  that  is  congruent  with  our  status  as  free  and  equal:  

we  are  each  equally  free,  not  naturally  subject  to  anyone  else’s  authority.  And  so  

a  conception  of  social  justice,  Rawls  suggests,  should  be  something  that  can  “be  

shared  by  citizens  as  a  basis  of  a  reasoned,  informed,  and  willing  political  

agreement”.22  Rules  that  are  simply  imposed  with  force,  but  that  make  no  claim  

to  the  reasoned  allegiance  of  persons,  cannot  successfully  serve  as  the  public  

charter  of  a  society  of  free  and  equal  persons.    

  If  this  is  the  role  of  a  conception  of  social  or  public  justice  (I  will  use  these  

terms  interchangeably),  public  reason  is  an  essential  feature  of  a  just  society.  

Without  the  constraint  of  public  reason,  a  conception  of  justice  could  permissibly  

draw  on  any  reasonably  contested  religious,  ethical,  and  philosophical  views.  

The  resulting  conception  of  social  justice  would  not  fulfill  its  role;  it  would  not  be  

one  that  can  serve  as  the  basis  of  free,  informed,  and  willing  agreement  amongst  

persons,  provided  we  assume  that  reasonable  disagreement  about  religious,  

ethical,  and  philosophical  matters  is  a  permanent  fact  of  life.  Instead,  our  

conception  of  justice  should  be  constructed  by  appeal  to  public  or  shared  

reasons—considerations  that  all  persons  (suitably  idealized)  can  recognize  and  

be  expected  to  endorse.  Only  when  a  conception  of  justice  is  regulated  by  the  

idea  of  public  reason  can  it  successfully  serve  as  an  appropriately  shared  

perspective  from  which  decisions  about  individual  rights,  duties,  and  

entitlements  can  be  fairly  made.  In  sum,  I  believe  we  should  endorse:  

 

Justice:  Demands  of  social  or  public  justice  should  only  be  made  on  the  

basis  of  reasons  that  the  subjects  of  the  demands  can  reasonably  be  

                                                                                               22  Rawls,  Political  Liberalism  (New  York:  Columbia  University  Press,  1996),  9.  

Page 23: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  23  

expected  to  endorse.  Conceptions  of  social  or  public  justice  thus  stand  in  

need  of  public  justification,  but  this  is  not  necessarily  true  of  other  moral  

demands.      

 

This  view  has  clear  advantages  over  Coercion.  That  view,  recall,  had  

implausible  implications  in  cases  that  did  not  involve  coercion,  but  which  did  

involve  matters  of  basic  justice,  for  example,  a  government  lottery  to  allocate  

resources  to  one  religious  group  rather  than  another,  or  a  government  which  had  

the  ability  to  impose  duties  on  citizens  without  the  use  of  coercion.  If  public  

reason  regulates  anything,  it  surely  must  regulate  the  basic  rules  that  determine  

how  resources  will  be  allocated  in  society.    

Justice  also  has  advantages  when  compared  to  Social  Morality,  since  it  does  

not  implausibly  expand  the  role  of  public  reason  to  cover  every  moral  demand  

that  we  make  of  each  other.  But  this  comparison  to  Social  Morality  may  also  be  

puzzling.  What  is  special  about  the  demands  of  justice  when  compared  to  other  

moral  demands?  Two  features  of  our  public  conception  of  justice  provide  the  

answer  to  this  question.    

First,  we  expect  others  to  give  priority  to  the  demands  of  justice.  You  and  I  

may  have  deep  religious,  ethical,  or  philosophical  disagreements,  and  these  

disagreements  may  lead  us  to  think  badly  of  each  other,  to  blame  each  other,  and  

to  denounce  each  other  as  vicious  or  immoral.  But  these  disagreements  do  not  

trump  claims  of  justice.  I  do  not  share  your  religious  beliefs  and  I  think  it’s  

morally  wrong  for  you  to  raise  your  children  to  hold  these  beliefs,  and  morally  

wrong  for  you  to  donate  charitably  to  your  Church.  But  justice  demands  of  me  

that  I  recognize  your  right  to  make  these  moral  mistakes,  and  I  must  give  this  

right  priority  over  my  other  moral  judgments.  What,  exactly,  does  it  mean  for  

justice  to  take  priority  in  this  way?  Of  course  it  means—as  proponents  of  Coercion  

Page 24: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  24  

will  be  quick  to  point  out—that  I  am  duty-­‐‑bound  to  refrain  from  using  coercion  

to  interfere  in  these  choices  of  yours  that  I  believe  are  wrong.  But  the  priority  of  

justice  involves  much  more  than  this  restriction  on  the  permissible  use  of  

coercion.  Most  obviously,  I  am  duty-­‐‑bound  to  obey  the  accepted  rules  of  public  

justice  that  apply  to  me,  regardless  of  whether  these  rules  accord  with  my  

religious,  ethical,  or  philosophical  convictions.  I  am  also  duty-­‐‑bound  to  take  

reasonable  steps  to  protect  your  rights  against  those  who  might  try  and  infringe  

them,  even  when  I  share  the  moral  judgments  of  the  would-­‐‑be  infringers.  I  

should  also  support  measures  to  compensate  you  if  your  rights  are  infringed  

regardless  of  my  personal  views  about  the  immorality  of  your  choices.  The  

priority  of  justice  also  entails  that  I  must  set  aside  all  of  my  beliefs  that  are  not  

reasonably  acceptable  to  others  when  I  exercise  my  political  power  on  matters  of  

social  justice  (e.g.  when  I  vote).  Furthermore,  although  I  may  try  to  overturn  laws  

that  I  believe  are  unjust  (even  engage  in  civil  disobedience)  I  should  not  try  and  

overturn  laws  I  recognize  to  be  just,  but  which  conflict  with  my  religious  beliefs  

or  conception  of  the  good.23    

The  second  feature  of  social  justice  is  its  role  as  a  framework  of  rules  that  

apply  to  societies  characterized  by  the  fact  of  reasonable  pluralism.  As  I  mentioned  

earlier,  pluralism  is  reasonable  when  we  assume  that  persons  disagree  about  

religious,  ethical,  and  philosophical  matters  not  as  a  result  of  self-­‐‑interest,  

ignorance,  prejudice,  or  irrationality,  but  rather  as  a  result  of  the  sincere  efforts  of  

reasonable  and  rational  people,  living  under  free  conditions,  to  decide  how  to  

live  and  what  to  value.      

                                                                                               23  We  may  wish  to  add  the  caveat  that  the  claims  about  priority  described  in  this  paragraph  only  apply  when  the  requirements  of  justice  meet  the  further  condition  of  being  legitimate.  I  return  to  this  point  in  section  V.  

Page 25: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  25  

These  two  features,  priority  and  reasonable  pluralism,  combine  to  explain  

why  the  demands  of  social  justice  are  special  when  compared  to  other  moral  

demands,  and  unlike  other  moral  demands,  stand  in  need  of  public  justification.  

Without  the  fact  of  reasonable  pluralism—if  there  were  complete  agreement  

about  religious,  ethical,  and  philosophical  issues—the  requirement  for  public  

justification  would  be  superfluous.  Alternatively,  if  justice  did  not  have  the  sort  

of  priority  described  in  the  penultimate  paragraph,  then  the  demands  of  justice  

wouldn’t  call  for  public  justification  even  assuming  the  fact  of  reasonable  

pluralism.  What’s  special  about  the  demands  of  justice  is  that  we  expect  others  to  

give  them  priority  over  their  reasonable  religious,  ethical,  or  philosophical  views,  

and  others  expect  the  same  of  us.  Consider  this  way  of  expressing  the  priority  of  

justice:  “I  know  you  think  I  am  acting  wrongly,  and  I  know  your  judgment  arises  

as  a  result  of  your  sincere  and  reasonable  efforts  to  determine  moral  truth,  but  

nevertheless  you  must  accord  priority  to  my  right  to  act  wrongly  (as  you  see  it)”.  

In  order  for  the  “must”  in  this  sentence  to  be  plausible—for  it  to  be  consistent  

with  treating  the  person  to  whom  the  sentence  is  spoken  as  a  free  and  equal  

member  of  our  society—the  right  in  question  must  be  justified  by  appeal  to  

shared  values  or  reasons  that  others  can  reasonably  be  expected  to  endorse.  

Unless  this  condition  of  public  justification  is  met,  there  would  be  nothing  to  

ground  the  priority  of  justice.  If  Albert’s  act  of  φ-­‐‑ing  appears  wrong  when  

viewed  from  within  Betty’s  religious  or  ethical  doctrine,  then  he  cannot  require  

her  to  respect  his  right  to  do  wrong  if  the  justification  for  that  right  is  sectarian  

and  grounded  in  Albert’s  religious  or  ethical  doctrine  that  Betty  reasonably  

rejects.  This  would  amount  to  Albert  demanding  Betty  give  priority  to  his  

religious  or  ethical  doctrine  rather  than  her  own  reasonable  doctrine.    

The  rules  of  social  justice  are  meant  to  provide  a  fair  set  of  terms  by  which  

those  with  different  plans  and  different  religious  and  ethical  views  can  interact  

Page 26: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  26  

with  one  another  in  cooperative  and  mutually  beneficial  ways.  If  each  person  

must  give  priority  to  these  rules  over  their  own  religious  or  ethical  perspectives,  

then  the  fairness  of  the  rules  depends  on  the  rules  being  justifiable  by  appeal  to  

shared  political  values  alone.  If  the  rules  of  public  justice  did  not  meet  this  

condition—if  they  were  grounded  in  some  reasonably  disputed  religious  or  

ethical  viewpoint—then  some  citizens  would  be  required  to  give  special  priority  

to  the  religious  or  ethical  views  of  others,  views  which  they  reasonably  reject.  

This  would  not  be  a  world  where  citizens  stand  as  equals.  This  is  what  makes  the  

demands  of  justice  special,  and  the  appropriate  focus  of  public  justification.  

Other  moral  demands—ones  that  do  not  have  the  special  priority  we  

attach  to  the  demands  of  justice—are  different.  As  I  suggested  in  the  previous  

section,  we  can  criticize  and  blame  others  by  appeal  to  what  we  take  to  be  the  

whole  truth  about  religion  or  ethics,  but  we  respect  others  as  free  and  equal  so  

long  as  we  also  recognize  that  our  beliefs  about  religious,  ethical  or  philosophical  

truth  are  subordinate  to  principles  of  social  justice.  

 

V  

In  closing,  let’s  examine  a  few  objections  to  the  preceding  account  of  the  role  of  

public  reason.  

First,  consider  two  related  worries  about  the  scope  of  political  authority  

and  public  reason.    One  worry  is  that  Justice  offers  an  unduly  narrow  picture  of  

what  our  legal  and  political  institutions  may  legitimately  do.  It  might  seem  to  

entail  that  the  only  permissible  objective  of  the  legislative  and  executive  branches  

of  government  is  justice,  and  any  policies  designed  to  promote  other  objectives  

are  precluded.  But  this  isn’t  entailed  by  Justice:  this  view  of  public  reason’s  role  is  

compatible  with  a  broader  account  of  the  role  of  government  or  political  life,  one  

where  the  government  pursues  objectives  apart  from  establishing  and  securing  

Page 27: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  27  

justice  (e.g.  promoting  artistic  excellence,  or  increasing  the  funds  available  to  

charitable  causes  beyond  what  justice  requires).  I  endorse  the  view  that  the  role  

of  government  should  be  restricted  to  establishing  and  securing  justice,  but  

further  arguments  are  needed  to  establish  this  conclusion:24  it  can’t  be  derived  

from  the  narrower  thesis  that  the  exclusive  role  of  public  reason  is  to  regulate  our  

debates  and  decisions  about  justice.  

  A  second  worry  is  that  Justice  yields  a  view  about  the  scope  of  public  

reason  that  is  unduly  narrow.  Consider  the  recent  Supreme  Court  ruling  in  Town  

of  Greece  v.  Galloway.25  In  this  case,  the  Court  ruled  that  opening  town  board  

meetings  with  public  prayers  did  not  violate  the  Constitution’s  establishment  

clause.  Some  constitutional  scholars  have  endorsed  this  view,  apparently  

endorsing  something  like  a  close  cousin  of  Coercion,  whereby  the  establishment  

clause  only  protects  citizens  from  religious  coercion  by  the  state,  but  does  not  

prohibit  religious  expressions  or  affirmations  by  the  state  that  are  non-­‐‑coercive.  

But  others  worry  that  this  interpretation  of  the  establishment  clause  is  far  too  

narrow:  shouldn’t  the  state  be  prohibited  from  religious  affirmations,  even  when  

non-­‐‑coercive?26  A  similar  worry  might  be  pressed  against  Justice.  Suppose  the  

federal  government  put  up  billboards  declaring  that  Jesus  is  the  Lord  Our  Savior.  

This  seems  like  something  that  an  account  of  public  reason  ought  to  condemn,  

but  it  might  seem  that  Justice  lacks  the  resources  to  do  so.  After  all,  surely  

symbols  or  expressions  are  not  the  stuff  of  justice—justice  concerns  individual  

rights  and  liberties,  and  the  distribution  of  burdens  and  benefits.  

                                                                                               24  I  try  to  provide  some  of  these  further  arguments  in  chapters  2-­‐‑4  of  my  Liberalism  Without  Perfection  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2011).  25  133  S.Ct.  2388  (2013).  26  For  discussion  of  this  case  along  these  lines  see  Micah  Schwartzman’s  and  Nelson  Tebbe’s  article  in  Slate,  ‘A  Prayer  for  Liberals’.  http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/jurisprudence/2014/05/the_strange_liberal_argument_that_thin_skinned_religious_minorities_should.html    

Page 28: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  28  

  The  appropriate  response  is  to  deny  the  premise  that  government  symbols  

and  expressive  acts  never  have  anything  to  do  with  justice.  First,  there  is  the  

trivial  point  that  government  resources  spent  on  symbols  or  expressive  acts  

could  be  spent  in  other  ways  (e.g.  programs  to  improve  opportunities  for  the  

least  advantaged)  and  thus  at  least  many  instances  of  government  expression  do  

raise  issues  of  the  rightful  allocation  of  resources.  Second,  setting  this  first  point  

aside,  government  expression  may  often  affect  the  distribution  of  advantages  in  

society,  and  so  government  expression  may  be  an  appropriate  object  of  social  

justice.  Consider,  for  example,  a  society  with  a  history  of  racial  injustice  and  

segregation  where  equality  of  opportunity  for  members  of  the  minority,  the  

Greens,  has  not  yet  been  achieved.  Suppose  the  government  were  to  issue  public  

statements  such  as,  “Greens  are  lazy  and  unmotivated,”  or  “Greens  don’t  yet  

possess  the  intellectual  ability  to  compete  for  the  best  jobs”.  Such  statements  are  

not  merely  racist;  they  are  also  unjust  in  light  of  the  history  of  racial  injustice  in  

our  imagined  society.  Finally,  individual  citizens  have  a  right,  at  the  bar  of  

justice,  to  equal  treatment  under  the  law,  and  it’s  not  implausible  to  suppose  this  

right  includes  a  claim  that  the  government  refrain  from  any  acts  of  expression  

that  imply  some  members  of  society  are  worth  less,  or  that  the  executive  or  legal  

branches  of  government  view  their  claims  as  having  less  weight.  Whether  any  

particular  instance  of  government  expression—for  example  the  public  prayer  at  a  

town  board  meeting—infringes  this  right  to  equal  treatment  seems  dependent  on  

historical  and  other  contextual  details,  but  there’s  no  basis  for  holding  that  

government  expression  or  symbolic  acts  are  necessarily  beyond  the  scope  of  

social  justice.    

  Consider  a  third  objection.  As  many  critics  of  political  liberalism  and  

public  reason  have  pointed  out,  the  fact  of  reasonable  pluralism  is  not  limited  to  

matters  of  religion  and  the  good  life:  it  extends  to  matters  of  justice  as  well.  

Page 29: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  29  

Reasonable  people—on  any  plausible  definition  of  that  term—disagree  about  

free  speech,  abortion  rights,  taxation  policy,  immigration  reform,  and  affirmative  

action,  to  name  just  a  few  examples.  But  if  reasonable  people  disagree  so  deeply  

about  justice,  it  might  seem  implausible  that  the  role  of  public  reason  could  be  to  

regulate  conceptions  of  social  justice.  Perhaps  we  should  expect  something  more  

minimal  from  an  account  of  public  reason.27  Perhaps  public  reason  is  only  meant  

to  provide  an  account  of  the  permissible  limits  of  political  authority,  by  which  I  

mean  roughly  an  account  of  which  directives  the  state  has  the  moral  right  to  

issue  and  enforce  without  wronging  those  subject  to  the  directives.  Reasonable  

persons  may  not  agree  about  exactly  what  justice  requires,  but  perhaps  they  can  

agree  that  laws  are  only  legitimate  when  certain  democratic  procedures  are  

observed,  and  when  the  laws  in  question  do  not  violate  certain  minimal  moral  

standards  (e.g.  the  laws  do  not  involve  religious  persecution,  or  racial  or  sexual  

discrimination,  etc…).  On  this  alternative  view,  the  role  of  public  reason  is  not  to  

regulate  the  content  of  social  justice,  but  rather  to  provide  an  account  of  political  

legitimacy.    

  To  evaluate  this  alternative  view,  we  need  to  distinguish  two  different  

ways  public  reason  might  be  thought  to  contribute  to  an  account  of  political  

legitimacy.  The  first  version  begins  with  the  following  assumption:  it  is  at  least  

presumptively  wrong  to  restrict  a  person’s  negative  liberty  without  explicit  or  

tacit  consent.  But,  as  we  all  know,  the  state  regularly  uses  coercion  to  restrict  our  

liberty  and  it  does  so  even  though  the  vast  majority  of  us  have  never  explicitly  or  

tacitly  consented  to  these  restrictions.  How,  then,  can  the  state’s  coercive  power  

be  legitimate?  This  is  the  puzzle  of  political  legitimacy  as  framed  by                                                                                                  27  Some  point  to  the  fact  of  reasonable  disagreement  about  justice  to  press  a  different  objection,  namely,  that  proponents  of  public  reason  posit  an  unjustifiable  asymmetry  between  disagreement  about  justice  and  disagreements  about  the  good  life.  I  address  this  objection  in  chapter  seven  of  Liberalism  Without  Perfection.  

Page 30: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  30  

philosophical  anarchists  and  voluntarists  such  as  A.  John  Simmons.  Some  believe  

the  aim  of  public  reason  is  to  solve  this  puzzle:  to  reconcile  the  state’s  coercive  

power  with  the  negative  liberty  of  persons—to  show  this  power  can  be  legitimate  

because  it  is  power  to  which  we  would,  at  some  level  of  idealization,  consent.    

But  skeptics  argue  public  reason  cannot  succeed  in  this  task  since  what  it  

offers  is  nothing  like  genuine  consent.28  In  order  to  yield  determinate  results  that  

are  morally  acceptable,  the  constituency  of  persons  to  whom  political  principles  

and  rules  are  justified  must  be  significantly  idealized,  to  the  point  where  it’s  

implausible  to  suggest  that  public  justification  establishes  anything  

approximating  the  consent  of  real  persons.  But  if  the  philosopher  of  public  

reason  avoids  too  much  idealization,  and  sticks  fairly  closely  to  what  the  actual  

persons  believe  when  constructing  an  account  of  which  principles  and  rules  can  

be  publicly  justified,  it’s  unlikely  the  account  of  public  reason  yields  determinate  

or  morally  acceptable  rules.  As  Joseph  Raz  argues:  

 

It  seems  tempting  to  say  that  our  duty  to  act  only  on  

political  principles  to  which  the  reasonable  consent  is  

simply  the  duty  to  act  on  well-­‐‑founded,  valid  

principles.  For  that  is  what  the  reasonable  consent  to.  

This  eliminates  the  independent  role  of  consent….The  

puzzle  is  how  one  can  give  consent  a  viable  role,  

without  saying  that  only  principles  already  agreed  to  

by  all  can  be  relied  on.  One  must  find  a  reasonable  

interpretation  of  the  intuitively  appealing  idea  that  

political  principles  must  be  accessible  to  people  as                                                                                                  28  David  Enoch,  ‘Against  Public  Reason,’  Oxford  Studies  in  Political  Philosophy:  V.  1  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2015),  112-­‐‑142.  

Page 31: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  31  

they  are…Politics  must  take  people  as  they  come  and  

be  accessible  to  them,  capable  of  commanding  their  

consent  without  expecting  them  to  change  in  any  

radical  way.  But  at  the  same  time,  justified  political  

principles  may  be  controversial,  and  may  fail  to  

command  actual  consent.  Nagel  and  Rawls  offer  

interpretations  of  this  intuition  which  aim  to  be  both  

coherent  and  attractive.  Their  failure  suggests  that  the  

underlying  idea  may  at  bottom  be  unstable  and  

incoherent.  There  may  be  no  middle  way  between  

actual  (including  implied)  agreement  and  rational  

justification.29  

 

  But  I  think  the  force  of  this  objection  depends  on  the  assumption  that  

public  reason  is  trying  to  solve  the  puzzle  of  political  legitimacy  as  framed  by  the  

philosophical  anarchist  or  voluntarist—that  the  goal  is  to  use  public  reason  as  a  

proxy  for  consent  so  as  to  reconcile  the  coercive  power  of  the  state  with  

individuals’  negative  liberty.  On  my  view,  however,  this  is  not  public  reason’s  

role.  Public  reason  is  not  a  pale  form  of  consent,  intended  to  satisfy  the  

voluntarist’s  worry  about  political  legitimacy.  Instead,  public  reason  is  a  

condition  on  an  acceptable  conception  of  social  justice.  We  cannot  treat  one  

another  justly  unless  decisions  about  justice  are  regulated  by  the  standards  set  by  

public  reason.  The  point  of  public  reason  is  to  ensure  that  the  rules  that  regulate  

our  interactions  with  others  are  reasonably  fair  or  just,  by  ensuring  the  

                                                                                               29  Joseph  Raz,  ‘Facing  Diversity:  The  Case  of  Epistemic  Abstinence,’  Philosophy  &  Public  Affairs  19  (1990),  46.  

Page 32: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  32  

justifications  for  the  rules  of  justice  are  mutually  acceptable  to  suitably  motivated  

parties.    

  But  this  leads  to  the  second  way  public  reason,  more  indirectly,  

contributes  to  an  account  of  political  legitimacy.  Instead  of  following  voluntarists  

like  Simmons,  and  assuming  that  actual  consent  (or  something  that  mimics  

consent)  is  needed  to  establish  political  legitimacy,  we  might  adopt  a  different  

view,  one  where  legitimacy  is  grounded  in  the  duties  of  justice  we  owe  to  one  

another.  This  is,  of  course,  a  well-­‐‑known  approach  whose  contemporary  

exponents  include  John  Rawls,  Jeremy  Waldron,  and  Christopher  Heath  

Wellman.  Here  is  one  way  of  formulating  the  duty-­‐‑based  conception  of  legitimacy:  

 

One  way  to  establish  that  a  person  has  legitimate  authority  over  

another  person  involves  showing  that  the  alleged  subject  is  likely  

better  to  fulfill  the  duties  of  justice  he  is  under  if  he  accepts  the  

directives  of  the  alleged  authority  as  authoritatively  binding  and  

tries  to  follow  them,  rather  than  by  trying  to  directly  fulfill  the  

duties  he  is  under  himself.30  

 

I  will  not  rehearse  the  arguments  in  favor  of  this  view  here.31  Instead,  I  want  to  

assume  this  view  is  correct,  and  explain  how  it  can  address  the  fact  of  reasonable  

disagreement  about  justice.32    

Consider  the  following  simple  view:  the  exercise  of  political  power  is  only  

legitimate  when  it  is  perfectly  just,  where  “perfectly  just”  means  just  according  to  

your  preferred  account  of  social  justice.  If  each  person  endorsed  this  view,  this                                                                                                  30  From  my  Liberalism  Without  Perfection,  128.  This  principle  is  deliberately  adapted  from  Raz’s  influential  normal  justification  thesis.  31  I  offer  a  brief  defense  of  the  duty-­‐‑based  view  in  sect.  4.4  of  Ibid.  32  The  following  is  a  condensed  version  of  the  argument  I  present  in  sect.  4.5  of  Ibid.  

Page 33: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  33  

would  almost  certainly  have  very  bad  consequences  for  promoting  and  securing  

justice  in  our  society.  If  each  person  believed  laws  were  illegitimate  unless  they  

conformed  exactly  with  their  own  preferred  conception  of  justice,  then  on  many  

issues  no  matter  which  particular  policy  the  state  enacted,  most  people  would  

view  the  policy  as  illegitimate,  and  this  would  presumably  make  effective  state  

action  difficult,  if  not  impossible.  This  will  not  be  a  good  result  from  the  

standpoint  of  justice.  A  world  where  we  have  an  effectively  enforced  progressive  

taxation  policy  that  I  believe  to  be  unjust  is  nevertheless  vastly  superior  from  the  

standpoint  of  justice  to  a  world  where  there  is  no  effective  taxation  policy  at  all  

because  any  policy  the  state  tries  to  enact  is  rejected  as  unjust  and  therefore  

illegitimate  by  the  majority  of  citizens.  

But  the  duty-­‐‑based  account  of  legitimacy  can  offer  a  solution  to  this  

problem.  In  a  pluralistic  society  where  reasonable  people  disagree  about  what  

justice  requires,  we  better  fulfill  our  natural  duty  to  promote  and  maintain  just  

institutions  by  accepting  as  legitimate  any  publicly  justifiable  views  about  justice  

that  all  reasonable  citizens  could  endorse  as  just  even  if  there  is  in  fact  a  great  deal  

of  reasonable  disagreement  about  what  justice  requires.  We  reasonably  disagree,  

suppose,  about  which  policy  from  the  set  [P1,  P2,  P3,  P4,  P5]  is  required  by  

justice  on  some  issue,  but  no  one  can  reasonably  deny  that  justice  is  better  

promoted  and  maintained  if  some  member  of  the  set  is  chosen  and  effectively  

implemented  as  opposed  to  any  one  of  the  obviously  unjust  alternative.  This  is  

why  one  member  of  the  set  can  be  legitimately  imposed  even  in  the  face  if  

reasonable  disagreement  about  justice.  

We  now  have  in  hand  an  explanation  of  the  relationship  between  three  

central  concepts:  public  reason,  justice,  and  political  legitimacy.  Public  reason  is  a  

constraint  or  condition  on  acceptable  conceptions  of  social  or  public  justice.  Such  

conceptions  must  be  publicly  justifiable  to  successfully  serve  as  a  framework  of  

Page 34: Quong-The Role of Public Reason

  34  

binding  rules  that  could  be  the  basis  of  reasoned,  informed,  and  willing  

agreement  amongst  persons  who  reasonably  disagree  about  religious,  ethical,  

and  philosophical  matters.  There  will  be  a  plurality  of  publicly  justifiable  views  

about  social  justice,  any  one  of  which  might  be  the  basis  of  legitimate  political  

authority,  but  political  legitimacy  is  not  derived  directly  from  the  idea  of  public  

reason,  rather  it  depends  in  addition  on  the  duty-­‐‑based  conception  of  political  

legitimacy.  Notice  that  one  might  accept  the  justice-­‐‑based  view  of  public  reason  

while  holding  some  alternative  account  of  political  legitimacy,  and  one  might  

accept  the  duty-­‐‑based  conception  of  legitimacy  while  rejecting  the  idea  that  

public  reason  is  a  constraint  on  acceptable  conceptions  of  justice.  My  view  is  

distinctive  in  that  I  endorse  both  the  duty-­‐‑based  view  of  legitimacy  and  the  

justice-­‐‑based  view  of  public  reason’s  role.  

To  return  to  the  original  worry,  once  we  abandon  the  assumption  that  

public  reason  is  an  effort  to  mimic  the  normative  role  of  consent  as  conceived  by  

anarchists  or  voluntarists,  it’s  no  longer  any  sort  of  objection  to  point  out  that  

public  justification  fails  to  look  like  consent.  Public  reason  is  not  meant  to  

establish  that  each  individual  somehow  consents  to  the  coercive  authority  of  the  

state.  Rather,  it’s  an  attempt  to  construct  a  shared  social  perspective  from  which  

reasonable  people  can  reason  together  about  the  fair  terms  that  will  regulate  their  

interactions  and  determine  their  rights  and  duties  with  regard  to  one  another.