the fallacy of electoral accountability

Upload: rvaldezsaldana

Post on 14-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    1/30

    The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    J.S. Maloy

    Assoc. Prof., Dept. of Political Science

    Oklahoma State Univ.

    (Feb. 2012)

    Abstract: The proposition that regular competitive elections are mechanisms of democratic

    accountability still forms the basis of much empirical and theoretical research in political science,

    despite sporadic attacks of skepticism in recent decades. These attacks have been diffuse but well

    founded. This paper surveys and claries the empirical failures and theoretical weaknesses of electoral

    accountability in order to defend a radical form of skepticism: elections are suitable for purposes of

    selection only, not of accountability.

    1

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    2/30

    The idea of electoral accountability is one of the most deeply entrenched aspects of political discourse

    in the late-modern world, and regular competitive elections are usually the institutional center-piece of

    thought and action on behalf of democratic progress. Theoretical as well as empirical literatures in

    political science emphasize the electoral connection (e.g. Mayhew 2004) between voters and

    representatives: the former are supposed to control the latter by rewarding them with reselection or

    punishing with deselection. Scholarly efforts at improving or deepening democracy often revolve

    around electoral institutions (e.g. Streb 2008, Gerken 2009). Even attempts to reconceive political

    accountability in non-electoral terms continue to pay homage to the conventional wisdom that repeated

    elections remain, nonetheless, accountabilitys primary vehicle (e.g. Grant & Keohane 2005, 41;

    Borowiak 2007, 1003; Rubenstein 2007, 618-19).

    At the same time, its well known in academic circles that various considerations qualify the

    force of electoral accountability, and recent research has shown signs of skepticism about both its

    theory and practice. Studies in the history of ideas have established that elections were understood in

    the sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries to perplex rather than to promote popular power,

    and that other, non-electoral procedures of accountability have traditionally been preferred by

    democrats (Manin 1997, Maloy 2008, McCormick 2011). Studies of the empirical realities of modern

    elections suggest that the conditions under which they could be interpreted as vehicles of

    accountability are rarely present, leading to a perceived need to substitute specialized accountability

    agencies (Przeworski et al. 1999, 24, 50-1) or horizontal accountability (Schedler et al. 1999, 2-3, 23-5).

    It was over a decade ago that an edited volume entitledDemocracy, Accountability, and

    Representation (hereafter abbreviated asDAR and cited as Przeworski et al. 1999) forced the

    accountability decits of electoral democracy on our attention, yet the assumed absence of these decits

    has continued to form a conceptual starting-point for much academic research on electoral processes

    and democratic regimes. There may be two reasons for the muted impact of electoral skepticism up to

    2

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    3/30

    now. First, there may be genuine disagreement over exactly how far its defects should lead us to qualify

    or modify the idea of electoral accountability, with the result that some researchers feel licensed to

    regard electoral skepticism as merely tentative or suggestive (and therefore negligible for the time

    being). Second, there may be genuine cases of cognitive dissonance, so that some researchers simply

    prefer to continue the inertia of long-established research agendas despite the possibility that they

    might now be practically futile or theoretically obsolete. What weve not seen at all, however, is either a

    convincing refutation or a systematic deepening of the electoral skepticism ofDAR. Either of these

    things could be the next step in the debate, and either could benet from a capsule survey of the

    precise grounds of electoral skepticism before moving forward.

    My purpose below is to provide this sort of prompt forward. First, I attempt to clarify the

    grounds of skepticism about electoral accountability by collecting its most important features from

    various sources in order to offer something new to the debate: a clear and concise statement of the

    various reasons for doubting that elections are instruments of democratic accountability. I distinguish

    two categories of considerations that contribute to electoral skepticism, empirical and analytical. There

    are empirical considerations that lead us to qualify the idea of electoral accountability by recognizing

    parameters that limit its practical feasibility, and there are analytical considerations that lead us to

    doubt the coherence of the idea itself.

    Second, I argue for a deepening of rather than a retreat from DAR. Electoral skepticism is

    defensible and compelling in more radical terms than have so far been proposed: elections arent good

    for accountability at all but only for selection. One contributor toDAR has already formulated a similar

    thesis based on the distinction between selection and sanction (Fearon 1999), but I now elaborate it in a

    form that directly contradicts one of the volumes main ndings: that the presence of high-quality

    information among voters would redeem the accountability decits of elections (Przeworski et al. 1999,

    23-4, 42-4). In other words, the very idea of electoral accountability is a fallacy. What I present below, to

    be more precise, is an outline of this radical form of electoral skepticism rather than a fully edged

    3

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    4/30

    defense against possible objections. While this may not amount to a convincing proof of radical

    skepticism, it could take cognitive dissonance off the table as a viable response to the debate. That

    would be a step forward, at least.

    Regardless of whether we accept a qualied, modied version of the idea of electoral

    accountability on the basis of the empirical failures brought to light by electoral skepticism, or a more

    radical form of skepticism which rejects the very coherence of the idea, the debate over electoral

    accountability has the potential to transform democratic theory in important ways. In conclusion I

    suggest how the terms of my analysis, irrespective of which conclusions are thought to follow, illuminate

    basic defects in two schools of academic political theory which have recently attempted to respond to

    some sort of electoral skepticism: minimalism and deliberationism.

    Empirical Failures

    In its simplest, strongest form, the idea of electoral accountability rests on the proposition that voters

    use elections to hold representatives accountable. In empirical research, this proposition serves

    sometimes as a testable hypothesis and sometimes as an untested assumption. The latter role is

    illustrated by studies that use the assumption of electoral accountability to tell causal stories about why

    states that hold regular elections rarely go to war with one another (e.g. Bueno de Mesquita et al. 1999,

    Reiter & Tillman 2002) or tend to exhibit low levels of political corruption (e.g. Adsera et al. 2003, Tavits

    2007), for example. A plausible causal story isnt a good one, however, unless the crucial assumption can

    itself be veried as generally true when treated as a testable hypothesis.

    For much of its modern history, academic political science has tended to treat electoral

    accountability as a generally reliable fact about the world. Broadly speaking, there have been two ways

    of nding empirical support for this assumption. First, studies of retrospective and especially economic

    voting have found that various measures of material well-being in various times and places have exerted

    a systematic inuence over the electoral fortunes of parties and candidates; here the causal story rests

    4

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    5/30

    on the assumption that voters deliberately reward or punish politicians economic performance at the

    ballot-box. Second, studies of the relative ideological or policy positions of voters and parties (or

    candidates) have found that elections tend to enforce congruence between them; here the causal story

    assumes that voters preferences are exerting control over politicians preferences, not vice versa.

    In response,DAR couldnt be accused of a radical form of electoral skepticism: the editors

    found mixed empirical results on electoral accountability and acknowledged that these were a

    signicant let-down on conventional expectations (Przeworski et al. 1999, 22-4). But the volume as a

    whole does offer, through a combination of empirical and conceptual analysis, considerations that tend

    to undermine the proofs of electoral accountability associated with both economic voting and

    ideological congruence. Ill now address the former while reserving consideration of the latter for the

    analytical or conceptual section of this paper.

    The center-piece of the volumes empirical skepticism is an analysis of economic voting in all

    democracies between 1950 and 1990 (Cheibub & Przeworski 1999). Using the probability of survival of a

    government as the dependent variable, this analysis found that a wide range of economic variables had

    no signicant effect. Only one variable, measuring growth in the labor force, had a modest positive

    effect on the likelihood of re-election. On the whole, then, plenty of governments with bad economic

    records survived while plenty with good records did not. A previous study was replicated which had

    found that clarity of responsibility (secure majority control over government, party unity, and so on)

    determined whether voters were able to reward and punish economic performance in systematic ways

    (Powell & Whitten 1993), thereby explaining away the cases for which economic-voting studies had

    yielded negative results. But Cheibub and Przeworski found with their expanded dataset that results

    didnt improve even when distinguishing disciplined parliamentary regimes with high clarity of

    responsibility.

    In empirical studies that have subsequently appeared to vindicate electoral accountability, the

    key dependent variable has tended to be casually conceptualized and variously operationalized. The

    5

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    6/30

    probability of re-election of individual candidates, not whole governments, has been used as the

    dependent variable in a study of parliamentary elections in Poland (Zielinski et al. 2005), and the actual

    failure of re-election has been used in a study of Italian parliamentary elections focussed on

    representatives involved in corruption trials (Chang et al. 2010), with the conditional nding that

    electoral accountability may work in the presence of intense media coverage. Other studies with positive

    accountability results have measured their dependent variable in terms of changes in incumbents vote-

    share (Bovitz & Carson 2006), changes in incumbents approval ratings in opinion polls (Kelly 2003),

    survey responses about the self-reported candidate choices of voters (Jones 2011), and changes in

    incumbents behavior presumably intended to appeal to voters before election day (Huber & Gordon

    2004). Typically these studies fail to examine the conceptual stipulations or untested assumptions that

    allow their causal stories to include electoral accountability as essential to the interpretation of their

    quantitative results. They ignore, in particular, the unifying but largely implicit theme ofDAR: political

    elites control the institutions that are supposed to enable citizens control over political elites. In

    Maravalls words, an agent who has shirked, i.e. been a bad government, may also be rewarded if he is

    a good politician (Maravall 1999, 193). Key institutions that are prone to strategic manipulation

    include mechanisms for creating districts and selecting candidates; processes of voting and vote-

    counting; and, above all in the eyes of the volumes editors, channels of information.

    A key weakness in studies tending toward electoral skepticism up to now, however, is the lack of

    a capsule overview of those facts about the political world which give cause for doubt about the

    operations of electoral accountability. In order to see what classes of phenomena are relevant, lets

    stipulate that electoral accountability involves a process of translation: from (a) some popular will or

    judgment by which a government is meant to be controlled, to (b) some mechanism of control, viz. the

    reward of reselection or the punishment of deselection. There are at least eight general types of

    empirical failure which thwart electoral accountability in one of these two phases, popular will or

    effective sanction.

    6

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    7/30

    1. Electoral Fraud. The ease and variety of methods of manipulating electoral results, particularly in mass

    elections involving thousands or millions of voters, pose an empirical problem for the democratic

    character of electoral sanctions. The basic types of fraud include voting by ineligible persons, over-

    voting by eligible persons, denial of voting by eligible persons, and changing the value of eligible voters

    votes. Though the academic literature on electoral fraud is relatively thin (Lehoucq 2003, 236-7), well

    known techniques include registering ctitious, deceased, or otherwise ineligible voters; using

    repeaters to vote more than once; imprisoning eligible voters and releasing them after the polls are

    closed; physically blocking eligible voters from leaving home or entering a polling station;

    administratively purging eligibile voters from voting lists; bribing or intimidating eligible voters before

    they cast their ballots; and tampering with ballots or otherwise miscounting them after theyre cast.

    Such techniques are amply attested in the nineteenth-century U.S.A. (Argersinger 1985), but

    their empirical presence is both chronologically and geographically broader in scope. Naturally the

    most recent cases are of most interest, and Putins Russia springs immediately to mind. Even the

    limited academic literature has found cases of fraud in states as various as Great Britain, Mexico,

    Germany, Taiwan, Spain, and Argentina (Lehoucq 2003, 237-45). More celebrated cases have appeared in

    relatively newer democracies like Ukraine, where in the 1990s Pres. Leonid Kuchma used his power

    over the careers of regional leaders to obtain fraudulent but favorable reporting of electoral results (Arel

    2001). Even in the U.S.A. today, the 2000 presidential vote in the state of Florida famously failed to meet

    basic international standards of free and fair elections such that fraud could be ruled out (Bjornlund

    2004, 3-6).

    Measures of the frequency of such cases are difcult to conjure (Lehoucq 2003, 246-9), but

    theres reason to think that social scientists tend to under-estimate them: even in uncompetitive polls

    where the identities of the eventual victors arent in doubt, for instance, fraud is frequently used to

    increase margins of victory (Simpser n.d.). In so far as reliable electoral results are essential to

    7

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    8/30

    interpreting the popular will behind the voting, the difculties of obtaining them make for difculties in

    interpreting elections as vehicles of accountability.

    2. Electoral Technique. Equally important is the fact that problems of electoral fraud, and even of

    unintentional inaccuracies in electoral results, have no denitive technical solutions. Though its well

    known that certain types of ballot yield lower rates of voter error than others, e.g. optical-scan vs.

    punch-card ballots (Saltman 2006, 189), techniques for counting ballots are as important as for marking

    them. Computer technology, for instance, can reduce marking errors to two or three percent of all

    ballots cast (Herrnson et al. 2008, ch. 4), but theres no consensus about whether it offers counting

    procedures that are secure from fraudulent activity (pp. 111-12). As long ago as the early 1970s, when

    computers were rst used to tabulate results from elections in southern California, a team of computer

    scientists demonstrated that the voting results could be systematically skewed by technical

    manipulation (Saltman 2006, 166-7); the trick has recently been repeated with reference to

    computerized touch-screen voting machines (201-4). Even as administrative practices are rened to

    respond to such technical challenges, the basic problem remains that computer-processed results arent

    amenable to a genuine recount: as electoral technology becomes more sophisticated, the number of

    persons capable of certifying the results (i.e. qualied software engineers) shrinks. Attempts to make

    computerized voting machines generate auditable paper-trails have had the side-effect of increasing

    voter error (Herrnson et al. 2008, ch. 6). Unlike a twelve-member jury or a 500-member assembly, a mass

    electorate makes it very slow and costly to conduct a publicly veriable recount.

    In short, if human nature ensures the permanence of the motives for electoral fraud, the

    logistics of mass elections ensure the permanence of the opportunities. At present, these rst two

    empirical failures have the look of ironclad constraints on electoral accountability rather than

    remediable decits. In operational terms, researchers who use parties or candidates vote-share, or

    probability of re-election, or actual re-election, as their dependent variable in quantitative analyses

    8

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    9/30

    designed to prove the existence of electoral accountability are making themselves hostages to the

    possibility of fraud and to the inevitable imperfections of electoral technique on which fraud thrives.

    3. Poor Information. Even if electoral results could always be certied as accurate, their effects on

    accountability would depend on the informed will of the electors. Nearly all writers who address the

    topic of electoral accountability regard good information as essential to voters cognitive processes. But

    here the empirical problem of widespread voter ignorance about public policy, even in relatively

    afuent and educated societies (Hardin 2000), stands as one of the most visible obstacles. One attempt

    to study American voters information from the supply side, the news media, concluded that local

    newspapers ordinarily dont provide enough relevant information to allow voters to deliberately

    reward or punish their representatives in Congress and that there are signicant inequalities between

    residents of rich and poor media environments (Arnold 2004, 251-3). Another study of electoral

    accountability in local contexts in the U.S.A. concluded that voters were able to reward or punish

    incumbents based on their performance in years when local media gave intense scrutiny to relevant

    issues, but not in years when the media didnt (Berry & Howell 2007). Against the theory that only a

    well-informed elite of citizens is necessary to enable accountability, since their opinions lter down to

    less attentive citizens (see e.g. Hutchings 2003), Arnold found that in much of the country the few

    citizens with a high demand for political information never nd a reliable supply of it (Arnold 2004, 7-

    10).

    To a considerable extent, then, the failures of the modern news media translate into failures of

    electoral accountability. Researchers who nd a correspondence between voters preferences and voting

    behavior or electoral results must be careful about using opinion data from opt-in surveys, which tend

    to have a selection bias toward better informed members of society (see e.g. Jones 2011), as evidence for

    a broad phenomenon of electoral accountability throughout a political system.

    9

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    10/30

    4. Weak Parties. Political scientists have often looked to parties to supply coherent ideological cues when

    the fund of information is too limited to allow intelligent policy judgments. Yet theyve equally often

    lamented the failure of parties to play this role in various contexts. One of the signal cases of such

    lamentation, at the conclusion of an otherwise sanguine account of the analytical possibilities of

    retrospective voting as an avenue of electoral control, held that collective responsibility has leaked

    out of the system as a result of parties lack of organizational and ideological coherence in the U.S.A.

    (Fiorina 1981, 202-10). A more recent version of the same empirical point nds that a lack of partisan

    unity obscures the clarity of responsibility which voters need in order to use their ballots as tools of

    accountability (Powell 2000, ch. 3; see also Carey 2009). In some contexts, then, weak parties make

    electoral accountability unrealizable.

    5. Strong Parties. But there are other inhibiting conditions on electoral accountability to be found on the

    other side of the spectrum of party capacity. One respect in which political parties around the world

    tend to remain quite powerful is the preselection of candidates for ofce. If Bachrach and Baratz (1962)

    were right that agenda-setting is an important kind of political power, and if partisan nominations

    amount to setting the agenda for voters to mark their ballots, then electoral results could be said to

    reect elite rather than popular judgments as partisan organizations become stronger and more

    coherent.

    In the U.S.A., moreover, partisan control of the boundaries of electoral districts also inject elite

    judgments into electoral results. The marked decline of the number of competitive or marginal

    Congressional districts in recent decades (see McDonald & Samples 2006) has been attributed in part to

    partisan redistricting (Ansolabehere & Snyder 2002). Theres a serious debate, to be sure, over whether

    high rates of re-election for incumbents do in fact count as an accountability decit, since it could be

    the case that incumbents rarely lose because they tend to jump before theyre pushed by an angry

    electorate (Cox & Katz 2002). But the more general proposition that close, competitive districts are

    10

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    11/30

    better for electoral accountability (a.k.a. the marginality hypothesis), which underlies the specic

    worry about incumbency advantage, seems secure (Grifn 2006). If voters cant effectively sanction a

    representative who faces no challengers, or no viable ones, the empirical fact of partisan control over

    electoral districts could be a signicant hindrance to the operation of electoral accountability.

    6. Constitutional Structures. The strength or weakness of political parties is involved in interactive effects

    with the basic electoral processes and constitutional structures of a given state. The most common view

    of this interaction among political scientists is that a system of plurality voting within single-member

    districts (a.k.a. SMD) is ill suited to the collective accountability of each party, whereas a system of

    party-list voting with allocation of seats in proportion to a partys percentage of votes (a.k.a. PR) is ill

    suited to the individual accountability of representatives (Powell 2000, 66-8, 86-7; Kunicova & Rose-

    Ackerman 2005; Hellwig & Samuels 2008). PR systems, on the other hand, end up exhibiting a higher

    rate of legislative turnover, suggesting that its easier for voters to deselect their incumbent

    representatives through elections (Matland & Studlar 2004). PR systems are also typically favored by

    other measures of quality of democracy, such as ideological congruence between government and

    electorate (McDonald et al. 2004, Powell 2006). Which of these measures are more and which less

    essential to democracy is a matter of analytic and normative dispute, but either way a number of

    established democracies face signicant accountability decits that are built into their constitutional

    structures.

    At the same time, nearly all such democracies are structured as mixed regimes with

    multicameral legislatures, multiple veto-points, and checks and balances among various governmental

    agencies; many of them are also federal systems with multiple layers of elected authority, from the

    national down to the regional and local. Such complex webs of power, of course, exacerbate problems of

    information and clarity of responsibility, as a long line of observers from Thomas Paine down to the

    present day has noticed (Paine 2003, 8, 249-50; Arnold 2004, 5).

    11

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    12/30

    7. Weak Incentives. The electoral connection depends on the motivation of incumbents to retain their

    seats on election day, but the incentives for staying in power are sometimes too weak to confer deterrent

    power on voters. In local governments in rural China, for example, ofcial salaries are meager and

    elected ofcers therefore little fearful of the consequences of performing below their constituents

    expectations (Tsai 2007, 254-5). In other countries, of course, the problem doesnt take this form: in the

    U.S.A., senators and representatives salaries exceed the median citizens earnings by a factor of four or

    ve. But non-monetary aspects of elected ofce can also corrode the motivation to win re-election, and

    therefore the decision not to face the voters again at the next poll cant always be construed as an

    evasion of likely defeat by an otherwise motivated ofce-seeker (cf. Cox & Katz 2002).

    8. Financial Inuence. Even healthy levels of ofcial compensation might be overwhelmed by monetary

    inducements from unofcial sources. In theory all democracies must respect the rule of one person,

    one vote, but none of them enforces a similarly egalitarian distribution of economic resources. This

    nancial inequality leads, at least in states where campaigns are funded by private citizens and

    corporations, to a presumptive inequality of inuence over elected ofcers i.e. to elite rather than

    popular control of public affairs after election day. One attempt to analyze this control in terms of an

    investment theory of American electoral politics has found evidence that parties and candidates

    switch policies after elections in response to the interests of campaign donors (Ferguson 1995): the

    deterrent power of votes, in other words, might be matched or exceeded by that of dollars. It also makes

    strategic sense for elected ofcers to anticipate the reactions to their policies of not only their own

    donors but also their opponents (Ball 1999).

    Interactive effects have been observed between economic inequality and other empirical

    failures of electoral accountability. The poor diet of information offered to American voters by local

    media has been found to improve only when a well-funded candidate challenges an incumbent member

    12

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    13/30

    of Congress (Arnold 2004, 253). But the difculty of challengers in gathering funds against an

    entrenched incumbent, in turn, has been identied as one of the principal causes of the decline in

    competitive elections for Congress (Abramowitz et al. 2006), and the weakness of state-level campaign-

    funding regulations (which are usually meant to reduce funding inequalities) has been found to play a

    similarly anti-competitive role in sub-national elections (Hogan 2004). If good information and electoral

    competition are among the premises of electoral accountability, funding inequalities are a prime cause

    of their violation.

    In some contexts the interference of pecuniary inuence with the electoral connection is even

    more direct. In the 1990s Peru had the typical institutional accoutrements of electoral democracy:

    periodic and competitive elections, an independent judiciary, and privately owned media. But between

    elections it operated as a one-party state, thanks to the elaborate scheme of bribery of Vladimiro

    Montesinos, Pres. Alberto Fujimoris intelligence chief. The monthly cost of a deputy from another party

    was about $20,000; of a non-partisan judge, $10,000; of the owner of a television network, $60,000

    (McMillan & Zoido 2004). Under these cirumstances the notion that voters inuence policy, much less

    have any idea how policy is really made, was problematic, but so too was the notion that replacing one

    ofcer with another could amount to accountability. When the cash nexus dominates politics, the

    incentive of re-election and the likelihood that the electoral winner will govern differently from the

    loser are both reduced.

    The man atop this whole scheme was still subject to re-election, of course. The broader account

    of Fujimoris reign in Peru by Stokes (2001) is one of the most thorough empirical case-studies available

    of the troubled relations between elections and accountability. Fujimori ran for the presidency in 1990

    as an opponent of neo-liberal economic reforms that would impose scal austerity, shrink the welfare

    state, and introduce foreign investment on easy terms. Yet after his electoral victory he implemented the

    very reforms hed campaigned against. Despite this betrayal of his mandate, he successfully cultivated

    the image of a leader whose hands had, unfortunately, been tied. He also launched two initiatives that

    13

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    14/30

    proved more popular: a counter-insurgency campaign against the Shining Path militia and, less than a

    year before the next election, a public-works program that reduced unemployment among the lower

    classes (Stokes 2001, 142-8, 152-3). Fujimoris re-election in 1995 bears an important lesson about

    electoral accountability: as Stokes sums it up, through intensive and politically targetted

    expenditures ... a politician may mislead voters to win ofce, abandon his mandate, and be re-elected

    even without persuading people in any lasting way that the unmandated course was the right one (153).

    Analytical Doubts

    The case of Fujimori in Peru happens to illustrate some of the most important empirical realities of the

    world of politics which have a signicant bearing on the idea of electoral accountability. Since this case

    has even been cited as proof of electoral accountability by way of economic voting (Kelly 2003), it also

    illustrates the timeless nostrum that empirical data alone dont reveal the truth about politics. How data

    are interpreted depends on conceptual stipulations and analytical assumptions, as well as

    complementary empirical assumptions.

    One of the great revelations of theDAR volume is that, in terms of careful and deliberate

    theoretical treatment, electoral skepticism has no robust anti-skeptical position to argue against. Some

    of the volumes most notable contributions (i.e. Fearon 1999, Ferejohn 1999) spell out the various ways

    in which the theory of electoral accountability has already been limited and qualied by what some

    political scientists might presume is the most friendly methodological approach to the subject:

    principal-agent theory within a rational-choice framework. Indeed, when we turn to conceptual or

    analytical foundations, we nd that key elements of skepticism have long been recognized in some of

    the classic treatments of the concept of electoral accountability in American political science.

    KeysRetrospective Voting in American National Elections (1966) is famous for its claims that the

    fear of loss of popular support powerfully disciplines the actions of governments and that the only

    really effective weapon of popular control in a democratic regime is the capacity of the electorate to

    14

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    15/30

    throw a party from power (Key 1966, 10, 76). But these claims were in fact severely qualied, if not

    defeated entirely, by the conceptual framework in which Key suggested that his results should be

    interpreted. His opening chapter revolved around an echo-chamber metaphor for electoral politics:

    parties rst put noise into the chamber, and voters then return the echo in the form of electoral results;

    the contours of the chamber, as it were, change over time according to circumstances. Remarkably, Key

    was convinced that social science itself had a role to play in the messages put into the chamber in the

    rst instance, since parties and candidates would alter their pitch according to their operative theories

    of voters behavior one of the domains, of course, of psychologists and political scientists. Social-

    scientic theories affect political operatives perceptions of voters, Key suggested, and in turn those

    perceptions determine the nature of the voice of the people, for they determine the character of the

    input into the echo-chamber (7). This strikingly constructivist account of public opinion calls into

    question, in a fundamental way, the meaning of electoral accountability: in a sense it becomes the

    accountability of political elites to their own rhetorical constructions. And this conceptual framing may

    explain why, by contrast with his famous statements to the contrary, Key also hinted that the function of

    voters in elections wasnt so much control as inuence (77).

    Nonetheless, Keys nding that several American presidential elections in the middle twentieth

    century were decided by voters deliberate changes of mind about policy was hailed as a vindication of

    the rationality of the American electorate (Key 1966, vii-xv). Barro (1973) is often credited with having

    planted a more analytically rigorous seed for the rational choice theory of electoral accountability, but

    hes less often given credit for the way, like Key, he qualied the strength of the theory: the basic

    conclusion here is that, even with a competitive supply of potential ofce-holders, electoral control is

    only partially effective as a mechanism for inducing the ofce-holder to advance the interest of his

    constituents (19-20, emphasis added). In addition to the assumption of competitive elections, Barro

    kept his theoretic model simple by assuming that incumbents have no control over the electoral process

    itself (26) and are unafliated with political parties (41). Ferejohn (1986) noticed two other basic

    15

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    16/30

    assumptions of Barros and deliberately modied them by introducing (a) asymmetric information as

    between voters and incumbents and (b) diversity of evaluative standards among voters themselves (10).

    Ferejohns conclusion was that these new assumptions would allow incumbents (a) to exploit their

    superior information by masking their real failings and (b) to play off the voters against one another in

    order to maximize chances of re-election (see also Ferejohn 1999, 132-4). The result, in other words,

    vastly reduc[ed] the level of electoral control unless citizens could undertake sociotropic voting by

    abandoning their self-regarding motives in favor of some unitary criterion of public welfare (20-2).

    In other words, as the rational-choice model of electoral accountability became more realistic,

    expected levels of popular control got weaker. Not only did Barro interpret the results of his mathematic

    model as showing relatively weak electoral control; subsequent research (as we saw above) has turned

    up good empirical reasons to weaken Barros ve key assumptions competitive elections, independent

    electoral structures (such as the drawing of districts), symmetric information between voters and

    candidates, unitary evaluative standards among voters, and the absence of political parties. Only the last

    of these assumptions could be revised in accord with empirical reality in such a way as to strengthen

    rather than weaken electoral control, but even here scholarly opinion is mixed about actually existing

    parties net effects on accountability.

    These qualications of the conceptual force of electoral accountability can be extended into the

    realm of radical skepticism. If Pettit (2008) is correct to identify an analytic distinction between

    institutional control and causal inuence which reects the language of Keys retreat from

    control to inuence we might use these terms to explore how far either type of power can be

    realized through electoral accountability. Analyses of the conceptual dimensions of democratic

    accountability typically distinguish two phases, a process of scrutiny and judgment (or will-formation)

    and a subsequent process of sanction. The analytic assumption that I now wish to defend is that

    accountabilityas a function of human relations is distinct fromselection; how we conceptualize processes

    16

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    17/30

    of sanction is essential to making this distinction. Ill also suggest that several important propositions

    follow from this distinction.

    FIG. 1 INFORMATION JUDGMENT ACTION SIGNIFICANCE

    SELECTION personal character,past conduct,future pledges

    comparative,dichotomous; oneyes, others no

    choice consent:authorization

    ACCOUNTABILITY past conduct individualized,continuous (poor,fair, good, etc.)

    sanction control: incentivesto act in targettedways

    The basic similarity between selection and accountability involves the element of scrutiny and

    judgment which is common to both; the difference involves what happens next, as between choice and

    sanction. To be an object of choice is to be grouped with other alternatives, to be judged not necessarily

    on ones own account but primarily in comparison with others, and then to be either selected or passed

    over. To be an object of sanction, by contrast, is necessarily to be judged in isolation and then either

    rewarded or punished. Both retrospective and prospective considerations, affecting what kinds of

    information are brought to bear on judgment, may be part of scrutiny in either case, but the action-

    phases of selection and accountability are what make a clean distinction between the two. The action-

    phase of choice is to confer authority, or to grant license toward future conduct, i.e. prospectively; of

    sanction, to reward or to punish for past conduct, i.e. retrospectively. To speak somewhat more grandly,

    selection is a power whose normative moorings lie in consent; accountability, in control.

    Of course theres some conceptual overlap between selection and accountability, or else

    categories like the electoral connection would never have gained currency in the rst place. Selection

    often appears to involve control as well as consent: in other words, the moment of choice does at times

    look equivalent to a moment of sanction. These presumptions supply the foundation for the argument

    that periodic elections are a vehicle of accountability. Authorizing one actor in preference to another

    often does have some causal effect over which actions ultimately ensue the choice makes a

    17

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    18/30

    difference, so to speak. But Pettits (2008) distinction between causal inuence and institutional control

    is relevant here: whatever makes a difference is exercising the former, whereas the latter also requires

    some intention or target. In the absence of evidence of a target or of movement toward it, we can have

    inuence but not control. Pettits terminology points up the analytic signicance of accountabilitys two

    phases, will or judgment (choosing the target) and effective sanction (causing movement toward the

    target). Using some prominent recent elections in the U.S.A. as food for thought-experiment, we can see

    how regular competitive elections typically fail to identify a target and to move government toward it.

    Few would dispute, in retrospect, that the selection of George Bush the younger rather than Al

    Gore as president in 2000 made a difference, perhaps a very large one, over the following four or eight

    years. But this difference was the result of, in Pettits terms, causal inuence rather than institutional

    control. The consequences of the election werent within anyones control to the extent that no one

    couldve adequately assessed in advance either the propensities of the candidates (however hard we may

    try during the campaign) or the uctuations of events. Whatever target the popular will might

    theoretically have settled on during the 2000 campaign (say, reducing the chances of adultery among

    high ofcials), events in the world soon made it irrelevant: the electoral result helped to cause one set of

    actions rather than another, but not by dint of setting any target toward which the actions were driven.

    Another interesting example is the bid of George Bush the elder for re-election in 1992. There

    were not two but three major candidates in this poll, and therefore the citizenry sorted itself into four

    camps: supporters of each of the three candidates plus supporters of none of them (including non-

    voters). Among voters for Bush, suppose that many of them were satised with his performance and

    wished to reward him by reselection, but also that some of them wished to punish him with deselection

    but were deterred from doing so by their unhappiness with his rivals. In both the Clinton and Perot

    camps, suppose that many of these voters wished to punish Bush, and that some of them probably

    didnt but were enticed for one reason or another to vote for one of the challengers. Among non-voters,

    suppose that some wished to punish Bush but didnt like the alternatives, that some wished to reward

    18

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    19/30

    Bush but were kept away from the polls by accident, circumstance, etc., and that some had no desire in

    either direction. If we could obtain reliable information about the exact proportions of these different

    wills and judgments within the electorate, only then could we estimate the accountability result of the

    1992 election. The important point, however, is that the electoral process itself obviously isnt designed

    to yield such a result: it allows (untargetted) inuence but not control; its function, in other words, is

    selection not accountability.

    Even if mass voting results could be reliably associated with a targetted popular will, a counter-

    factual question about 1992 accentuates the weakness of the effective translation of this will into

    sanctions: what if a quirky Texas millionaire had decided not to launch a self-funded national campaign?

    Its likely that Perots advertising elicited discontent with the incumbent which otherwise wouldve

    remained latent, and its possible that, in the absence of Perots candidacy, Bush wouldve narrowly

    defeated Clinton. Would we then have been forced to say that the American people rewarded Bush

    through electoral means? If Perot himself constituted such a decisive factor in the nations political

    judgment, it hardly makes sense to speak of the electoral process in terms of democratic accountability.

    The Perot-less counter-factual for 1992 seems all the more plausible when we consider Bush the

    youngers bid for re-election in 2004. Public discourse in the mass media was xated on the decision to

    invade Iraq and the conduct of the subsequent occupation, though of course voters were anything but

    united around this issue as the sole criterion of electoral judgment. If a conservative anti-war candidate

    say, Pat Buchanan had entered the race that year, its conceivable that John Kerry wouldve played

    Clinton to Buchanans Perot, and Bush the younger wouldve followed Bush the elder to electoral

    defeat. In the absence of a Buchanan gure, however, Bush the younger earned a narrow victory,

    showing what the elder mightve achieved in the 1992 race without Perot. Even with only two

    candidates, however, the target indicated by this result was unclear, given that American voters appeared

    to disagree whether the Iraq war or the legalization of homosexual marriage (among other issues) was

    the most important standard for evaluating the candidates that year. While many observers considered

    19

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    20/30

    the war to be very unpopular, Bushs campaign was able to invoke other criteria of judgment to

    discourage deselection. On the terms of Ferejohns analysis of electoral control, the incumbent used

    informational advantages and cognitive diversity within the electorate to fend off accountability. On the

    terms of Stokes analysis of Peru, Bush 2004 was Fujimori 1995 redux.

    What lies behind the intuitions Ive tried to elicit through these examples is a basic analytic

    difference between accountability and selection, i.e. between sanction and choice, which poses

    insurmountable obstacles to translating judgment into sanction by electoral means. As is well known,

    certain assumptions about the psychology of voters and candidates must be in place in order for the

    threat of removal to act as a genuine deterrent to some behaviors and a spur to others; moreover, voters

    information about candidates must be good for the threat or spur to be applied effectively. But there is

    another stringent condition that Figure 1 brings to light, under the heading of judgment: unless the

    voting is done for a plebiscite or retention election, in which the incumbent is isolated for purposes of

    scrutiny and judgment and the choice is purely and simply between reselection and deselection, voters

    cant truly be said to exercise a power of sanction. Contested elections with multiple candidates always

    mingle prospective with retrospective considerations (Fearon 1999, 58-60) because even voters wanting

    to remove the incumbent must rst weigh whether the alternative candidates would bring any

    improvement. But in fact its not the prospective or retrospective as much as the comparative character

    of electoral judgments which inhibits accountability. Thats why representatives whom voters would like

    to punish often get re-elected anyway: the decision depends more on the challengers than on the

    incumbent. Negative campaign advertising, designed to sully ones opponents reputations, is

    controversial for its effects on voter turn-out and for its ethical implications, but its primary purpose is

    to defeat democratic accountability. It does this by actively discouraging voters from doing what we

    expect accountability to do: judging the incumbent.

    Its an analytic dead-end, therefore, to expect a competitive election to do the job of translating

    a clear judgment into an effective sanction; and, ironically, the less is known about a victorious

    20

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    21/30

    challenger, the more entitled we are to say that electoral accountability has been realized. A voter who

    decides to study carefully the character, conduct, and plans of every candidate is neutering any

    sanctioning potential inherent in the vote. Only if all voters in a particular election decide to ignore the

    challengers, or at least a majority who are solidly united in their judgment about the incumbent do so,

    can they be said to be using their votes for accountability. In exchange, of course, theyd be surrendering

    the function of selection to fate. Voters can use an election for selection or for accountability, but not for

    both. When voters try to use elections for both, as in any sizeable electorate they inevitably will, the

    result is the mutual attrition of both: rather than doing one job well, they do two jobs badly. We can

    now see that regular competitive elections are in theory a mechanism of pure selection, not of

    accountability. The electoral thesis of accountability requires elections to carry more than they can bear.

    Skepticism about the electoral connection between voting for representatives and holding them

    accountable has been advanced on both empirical and analytical grounds before now (Przeworski et al.

    1999, 22, 24, 44, 50), and my analysis so far claries and reinforces those doubts. But Ive also developed

    reasons for radicalizing the skepticism: even the remediation of all the empirical failures, from electoral

    fraud to party activities to pecuniary corruption, couldnt remove the analytical weaknesses inherent in

    the electoral thesis of accountability. A particularly striking implication of my analysis is that improving

    information, though necessary to the processes of scrutiny and judgment which both selection and

    accountability have in common, is radically insufcient for the latter. In this connection, one ambiguity

    about the new accountability agencies recommended by Przeworski et al. (1999) is whether theyre to

    be robustly punitive institutions or merely clearing-houses of high-quality information. If the latter,

    were still caught in a trap: information alone cannot supply the accountability decit of the electoral

    thesis. If the former, however, we need to consider the institutional-design possibilities for non-electoral

    mechanisms of sanction.

    21

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    22/30

    Theories and Institutions

    Electoral skepticism within democratic theory has in recent decades thrown up two alternatives to the

    conventional wisdom that regular competitive elections make governments accountable to citizens. Both

    the minimalist and the deliberative schools of democratic theory are grounded in some sense of

    electoral accountabilitys inadequacies, whether empirical or analytical.

    The minimalist theory of democracy surrenders the very notion of popular control through

    accountability, building on Schumpeters redenition of democracy as a forum of competitive partisan

    struggle which enables popular authorization of governments but not sanction or control (Schumpeter

    1942, ch. 22). Whereas Schumpeter dismissed the idea of democratic accountability in primarily

    normative terms, Przeworski (1999) is less scornful than mournful: given the ease with which political

    elites manipulate electoral processes in order to avoid accountability, democratic theory has no choice

    but to retreat to more modest goals. Hardin (2000) reaches a similar conclusion by emphasizing the

    informational and epistemological limitations of citizens attempts to hold their representatives

    accountable through elections. But elections at least have the saving virtue of allowing peaceful

    transfers of power from one set of elites to another, which is no small matter, considering the alternative

    of civil war (Przeworski 1999). They also offer subjects the existential drama (Dunn 1999, 342) of the

    occasional humbling of one set of elites for the benet of another. Thus the operational focus of

    minimalist democracy turns to using elections as instruments of stability, e.g. through understanding

    the conditions of losers consent (Anderson et al. 2005). Reform elections by all means, the minimalists

    say, but with an eye to psychic assurance and social peace rather than democratic power.

    The deliberationist theory also proposes reforms around the edges of existing electoral

    institutions, and in some variants is also primarily motivated by the norm of ameliorating disagreement

    in pluralistic societies. But the deliberationist impulse is basically resistant to the notion that citizens

    cant be well enough informed, as either an empirical or analytical matter, to govern themselves.

    Accordingly, the focus of deliberative reform has been to create opportunities for citizens to learn about

    22

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    23/30

    public policy and then to communicate their informed, rational judgments to their representatives and

    fellow citizens: focus-groups and deliberative panels ought to issue advice to the general public before

    elections and to the elected ofcers after elections (e.g. Fishkin 1995, Gastil 2000). By offering citizens

    forums in which to become better informed and through which to offer advice to policy-makers,

    deliberative reforms are often explicitly aimed at soothing disenchantment and healing disagreement

    within a particular society (e.g. Gutmann & Thompson 1996).

    Despite marked differences in tone and method, the minimalist and deliberationist responses to

    the accountability decits of electoral democracy seem to share a fundamental premise: the end is

    consent, not control. This premise is made explicit only in minimalism, but the citizen of a deliberative

    democracy is promised the power of advice, not of sanction. There accountability means merely the

    right to ask questions and to receive answers, and persuasion and shame are citizens only means of

    inuencing their political superiors. If we relax the analytical assumption that this verbal or discursive

    exchange counts as popular control over government, or the empirical assumption that it will proceed

    from the formation of a genuinely popular and coherent will, a rapprochement between minimalism

    and deliberationism is possible. The presence of deliberative forums might, under the right

    circumstances, be more likely than their absence to promote civic harmony: solidifying winners

    consent before elections and losers consent after.

    Theres a third possible response to electoral skepticism. Instead of keeping elections while

    jettisoning the norm of control which formerly supplied their rationale, or injecting elections with some

    participatory ideal while leading them into the analytic dead-end of more or better information, we

    might consider a radical alternative: popular control might be achieved through non-electoral

    institutions.

    In other words, it may be possible to retain electoral forms for purposes of selection but to

    implement non-electoral processes for purposes of accountability. For this there is long-standing

    historical precedent (Maloy 2008, McCormick 2011), according to the extant records of ancient and

    23

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    24/30

    Renaissance politics, as well as surviving practices in Anglo-American law. The two basic forms of non-

    electoral accountability in the Western tradition are audit and impeachment: the rst involves a

    thorough review of an individuals conduct at the end of a dened period of time; the second, an ad hoc

    review on some emergent occasion. The classic case of the former is the review (euthyna) given to each

    magistrate in ancient Athens at the end of his one-year, non-renewable term; of the latter, the

    indictment and trial of ofcers of state for high crimes in British and American constitutional history.

    Both audit and impeachment allow persons holding authority to be scrutinized and sanctioned

    by persons granting authority. Neither involves a cognitive process of comparison among several

    candidates who engage in campaigning to inuence the result; unlike competitive elections, therefore,

    neither allows the structure of incentives of an authoritative gure to be skewed by the vagaries of a

    multi-player game of manipulating information.

    In the roster of democratic institutions now recognized by popular and scholarly standards

    alike, versions of audit and impeachment are relatively invisible compared to electoral institutions. Yet

    analogs do exist in modern constitutional republics. In the U.S.A., for example, committees in Congress

    are supposed to perform audits, or oversight, with respect to other departments of the federal

    government. And the power of impeachment which Congress holds over executive and judicial ofcers

    has been invoked on two occasions in the last 40 years. Procedures like these offer some means for

    governmental ofcers to be held accountable independently of elections and therefore offer a concrete

    starting-point for thinking about the possibilities of non-electoral accountability.

    Yet there are two related limitations on the potential of these already existing versions of audit

    and impeachment in American national politics to remediate the accountability decits of regular

    competitive elections. First, ordinary citizens have no agency in these processes, which are essentially

    vehicles of intra-elite as opposed to mass-on-elite accountability. Whats important about

    congressional oversight and impeachment is that Congress thereby acquires some control over other

    players within the federal government. As James Madison made abundantly clear in 1788, the basic aim

    24

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    25/30

    of the U.S. Constitutions checks and balances is that they rst enable the government to control the

    governed, and in the next place oblige it to control itself (Wootton 2003, 247); they shouldnt, obviously,

    enable the governed to control the government.

    Secondly, the saving democratic feature of congressional oversight and impeachment powers

    can only come from some connection between the controllers (i.e. Congress) and the controllers

    controllers (i.e. voters). But in regular competitive elections the one mechanism allowed by Madison to

    enable the people to control the government weve already seen a mechanism ill-suited to the job of

    accountability. As currently constituted, then, audit and impeachment within the American federal

    government continue to beg our original question.

    Conclusion

    Shortly after his successful bid for re-election in 2004, George Bush the younger was asked whether his

    administration would hold anyone in the American government accountable for faulty intelligence and

    poor planning for the invasion of Iraq. His response was negative, because we had an accountability

    moment, and thats called the 2004 elections (VandeHei & Fletcher 2005). Its unsurprising that the

    idea of electoral accountability is popular among the established governments of the world: its meant to

    give them what they want, which is popular consent as a substitute for popular control. But Ive

    attempted to show that consent and control arent the same thing, and that these separate political

    functions happen to require distinct institutional arrangements. Unfortunately, it appears that the only

    applications for which the idea of electoral accountability is suited are the rhetorical and the naive.

    Democratic accountability has to be pursued beyond electoral bounds, or not at all.

    References

    Abramowitz, A.I., B. Alexander, & M. Gunning. 2006. Incumbency, Redistricting, and the Decline of

    Competition in U.S. House Elections.Journal of Politics 68: 75.

    25

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    26/30

    Adsera, A., C. Boix, & M. Payne. 2003. Are You Being Served? Political Accountability and Quality of

    Government.Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 19: 445-90.

    Anderson, C.J., A. Blais, S. Bowler, T. Donovan, & O. Listhaug. 2005.Losers Consent: Elections and

    Democratic Legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Oxford: Oxford Univ.

    Ansolabehere, S., & J.M. Snyder. 2002. The Incumbency Advantage: An Analysis of State and Federal

    Ofce, 1942-2000.Election Law Journal1: 315-38.

    Arel, D. 2001. Kuchmagate and the Demise of Ukraines Geopolitical Bluff. East European Constitutional

    Review 10.2: 54-59.

    Argersinger, P.H. 1985. New Perspectives on Election Fraud in the Gilded Age.Political Science

    Quarterly100: 669-87.

    Arnold, R.D. 2004. Congress, the Press, and Political Accountability. Princeton: Princeton Univ.

    Bachrach, P., & M.S. Baratz. 1962. Two Faces of Power.American Political Science Review 56: 947-52.

    Ball, R. 1999. Opposition Backlash and Platform Convergence in a Spatial Voting Model with Campaign

    Contributions.Public Choice 98: 269-86.

    Barro, R. 1973. The Control of Politicians: An Economic Model.Public Choice 14: 19-42.

    Berry, C.R., & W.G. Howell. 2007. Accountability and Local Elections: Rethinking Retrospective

    Voting.Journal of Politics 69: 844-58.

    Bjornlund, E. 2004.Beyond Free and Fair. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ.

    Borowiak, C.T. 2007. Accountability Debates: The Federalists, the Anti-Federalists, and Democratic

    Decits.Journal of Politics 69: 998-1014.

    Bovitz, G.L., & J.L. Carson. 2006. Position-Taking and Electoral Accountability in the U.S. House of

    Representatives.Political Research Quarterly59: 297-312.

    Bueno de Mesquita, B., J.D. Morrow, R.M. Siverson, & A. Smith. 1999. An Institutional Explanation of

    the Democratic Peace.American Political Science Review 93: 791-807.

    Carey, J.M. 2009.Legislative Voting and Accountability. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    26

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    27/30

    Chang, E.C.C., M.A. Golden, & S.J. Hill. 2010. Legislative Malfeasance and Political Accountability.

    World Politics 62: 177-220.

    Cheibub, J.A. & Przeworski, A. 1999. Democracy, Elections, and Accountability for Economic

    Outcomes.Democracy, Accountability, and Representation, eds. A. Przeworski, S.C. Stokes, & B.

    Manin. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    Cox, G.W., & J.N. Katz. 2002.Elbridge Gerrys Salamander: The Electoral Consequences of the Re-

    Apportionment Revolution. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Univ.

    Fearon, J.D. 1999. Electoral Accountability and the Control of Politicians.Democracy, Accountability, and

    Representation, eds. A. Przeworski, S.C. Stokes, & B. Manin. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    Ferejohn, J. 1986. Incumbent Performance and Electoral Control.Public Choice 50: 5-25.

    Ferejohn, J. 1999. Accountability and Authority: Toward a Theory of Political Accountability.

    Democracy, Accountability, and Representation, eds. A. Przeworski, S.C. Stokes, & B. Manin. New

    York: Cambridge Univ.

    Ferguson, T. 1995. The Golden Rule: The Investment Theory of Party Competition and the Logic of Money-

    Driven Political Systems. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago.

    Fiorina, M. 1981.Retrospective Voting in American National Elections. New Haven: Yale Univ.

    Fishkin, J.S. 1995. The Voice of the People: Public Opinion and Democracy. New Haven: Yale Univ.

    Gastil, J. 2000.By Popular Demand: Revitalizing Representative Democracy through Deliberative Elections.

    Berkeley: Univ. of California.

    Gerken, H. 2009. The Democracy Index: Why Our Election System Is Failing and How to Fix It. Princeton:

    Princeton Univ.

    Grant, R.W., & R.O. Keohane. 2005. Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics.American

    Political Science Review 99: 29-44.

    Grifn, J.D. 2006. Electoral Competition and Democratic Responsiveness: A Defense of the Marginality

    Hypothesis.Journal of Politics 68: 911-21.

    27

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    28/30

    Gutmann, A., & D.F. Thompson. 1996.Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ.

    Hardin, R. 2000. Democratic Epistemology and Accountability.Social Philosophy and Policy17: 110-26.

    Hellwig, T., & D. Samuels. 2008. Electoral Accountability and the Variety of Democratic Regimes.

    British Journal of Political Science 38: 65-90.

    Herrnson, P.S., R.G. Niemi, M.J. Hanmer, B.B. Bederson, F.C. Conrad, & M.W. Traugott. 2008. Voting

    Technology: The Not-So-Simple Act of Casting a Ballot. Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution.

    Hogan, R.E. 2004. Challenger Emergence, Incumbent Success, and Electoral Accountability in State

    Legislative Elections.Journal of Politics 66: 1283-303.

    Huber, G.A., & S.C. Gordon. 2004. Accountability and Coercion: Is Justice Blind When It Runs for

    Ofce?American Journal of Political Science 48: 247-63.

    Hutchings, V.L. 2003.Public Opinion and Democratic Accountability: How Citizens Learn About Politics.

    Princeton: Princeton Univ.

    Jones, P.E. 2011. Accountability for Policy Positions and Policy Outcomes in Congress.Journal of

    Politics 73: 764-82.

    Kelly, J.M. 2003. Economic and Political Accountability in Fujimoris Peru.Journal of Politics 65: 864-80.

    Key, V.O. 1966. The Responsible Electorate: Rationality in Presidential Voting, 1936-60. Cambridge, Mass.:

    Harvard Univ.

    Kunicova, J., & S. Rose-Ackerman. 2005. Electoral Rules and Constitutional Structures as Constraints

    on Corruption.British Journal of Political Science 35: 573-606.

    Lehoucq, F. 2003. Electoral Fraud: Cases, Types, and Consequences.Annual Review of Political Science 6:

    233-56.

    Maloy, J.S. 2008. The Colonial American Origins of Modern Democratic Thought. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    Manin, B. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    Maravall, J.M. 1999. Accountability and Manipulation.Democracy, Accountability, and Representation, eds.

    A. Przeworski, S.C. Stokes, & B. Manin. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    28

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    29/30

    Matland, R.E., & D.T. Studlar. 2004. Determinants of Legislative Turnover.British Journal of Political

    Science 34: 87-108.

    Mayhew, D.R. 2004. Congress: The Electoral Connection, 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale Univ.

    McCormick, J.P. 2011.Machiavellian Democracy. New York: Cambridge Univ.

    McDonald, M.P., & J. Samples (eds.). 2006. The Marketplace of Democracy: Electoral Competition and

    American Politics. Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution.

    McDonald, M.D., S.M. Mendes, & I. Budge. 2004. What Are Elections For? Conferring the Median

    Mandate.British Journal of Political Science 34: 1-26.

    McMillan, J., & P. Zoido. 2004. How to Subvert Democracy: Montesinos in Peru.Journal of Economic

    Perspectives 18.4: 69-92.

    Paine, T. 2003. Common Sense, Rights of Man, and Other Essential Writings. New York: Signet.

    Pettit, P. 2008. Three Conceptions of Democratic Control. Constellations 15: 46-55.

    Powell, G.B., & G.D. Whitten. 1993. A Cross-National Analysis of Economic Voting.American Journal of

    Political Science 37: 391-414.

    Powell, G.B. 2000.Elections as Instruments of Democracy: Majoritarian and Proportional Visions. New Haven:

    Yale Univ.

    Przeworski, A. 1999. Minimalist Theory of Democracy: A Defence.Democracys Value, eds. I. Shapiro &

    C. Hacker-Cordon. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Univ.

    Przeworski, A., S.C. Stokes, & B. Manin (eds.). 1999.Democracy, Accountability, and Representation. New

    York: Cambridge Univ.

    Reiter, D., & E.R. Tillman. 2002. Public, Legislative, and Executive Constraints on the Democratic

    Initiation of Conict.Journal of Politics 64: 810-26.

    Rubenstein, J. 2007. Accountability in an Unequal World.Journal of Politics 69: 616-32.

    Saltman, R.G. 2006. The History and Politics of Voting Technology. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    29

  • 7/29/2019 The Fallacy of Electoral Accountability

    30/30

    Schedler, A., L. Diamond, & M.F. Plattner (eds.). 1999. The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability

    in New Democracies. Boulder: Lynne Riener.

    Simpser, A. n.d. Cheating Big: On the Logic of Electoral Corruption in Developing Countries. Unpub.

    ms., Univ. of Chicago.

    Stokes, S.C. 2001.Mandates and Democracy: Neoliberalism by Surprise in Latin America. Cambridge, U.K.:

    Cambridge Univ.

    Streb, M. 2008.Rethinking American Electoral Democracy. New York: Routledge.

    Tavits, M. 2007. Clarity of Reponsibility and Corruption.American Journal of Political Science 51: 218-29.

    Tsai, L.L. 2007.Accountability without Democracy: Solidary Groups and Public Goods Provision in Rural

    China. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge Univ.

    VandeHei, J., & M.A. Fletcher. 2005. Bush Says Election Ratied Iraq Policy. Washington Post, Jan. 16.

    Wootton, D. (ed.). 2003. The Essential Federalist and Anti-Federalist Papers. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Zielinski, J., K.M. Slomczynski, & G. Shabad. 2005. Electoral Control in New Democracies: The

    Perverse Incentives of Fluid Party Systems. World Politics 57: 365-95.

    30