3 tsebelis garrett obl

28
Legislative Politics in the European Union George Tsebelis UCLA, USA Geoffrey Garrett Yale University, USA ABSTRACT This paper compares legislative dynamics under all procedures in which the Council of Ministers votes by quali- fied majority (QMV). We make five major points. First, the EU governments have sought to reduce the democratic deficit by increasing the powers of the European Parliament since 1987, whereas they have lessened the legislative influ- ence of the Commission. Under the Amsterdam treaty’s version of the codecision procedure, the Parliament is a co- equal legislator with the Council, whereas the Commission’s influence is likely to be more informal than formal. Second, as long as the Parliament acts as a pro-integration entre- preneur, policy outcomes under consultation, cooperation and the new codecision will be more integrationist than the QMV-pivot in the Council prefers. Third, the pace of Euro- pean integration may slow down if MEPs become more responsive to the demands of their constituents. Fourth, the EU is evolving into a bicameral legislature with a heavy status quo bias. Not only does the Council use QMV but absolute majority voting requirements and high levels of absenteeism create a de facto supermajority threshold for Parliamentary decisions. Finally, if the differences between the Council and the Parliament concern regulation issues on a traditional left–right axis, the Commission is more likely to be the ally of the Council than the Parliament. 9 European Union Politics [1465-1165(200002)1:1] Volume 1 (1): 9–36: 010841 Copyright© 2000 SAGE Publications London, Thousand Oaks CA, New Delhi KEY WORDS j democratic deficit j European Parliament j European Union j legislative institutions j spatial models

Upload: andreea-constantin

Post on 21-Apr-2015

34 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Legislative Politics in the

European Union

George Tsebelis

UCLA, USA

Geoffrey Garrett

Yale University, USA

A B S T R A C T

This paper compares legislative dynamics under all

procedures in which the Council of Ministers votes by quali-

fied majority (QMV). We make five major points. First, the

EU governments have sought to reduce the democratic

deficit by increasing the powers of the European Parliament

since 1987, whereas they have lessened the legislative influ-

ence of the Commission. Under the Amsterdam treaty’s

version of the codecision procedure, the Parliament is a co-

equal legislator with the Council, whereas the Commission’s

influence is likely to be more informal than formal. Second,

as long as the Parliament acts as a pro-integration entre-

preneur, policy outcomes under consultation, cooperation

and the new codecision will be more integrationist than the

QMV-pivot in the Council prefers. Third, the pace of Euro-

pean integration may slow down if MEPs become more

responsive to the demands of their constituents. Fourth, the

EU is evolving into a bicameral legislature with a heavy

status quo bias. Not only does the Council use QMV but

absolute majority voting requirements and high levels of

absenteeism create a de facto supermajority threshold for

Parliamentary decisions. Finally, if the differences between

the Council and the Parliament concern regulation issues on

a traditional left–right axis, the Commission is more likely to

be the ally of the Council than the Parliament.

9

European Union Politics

[1465-1165(200002)1:1]

Volume 1 (1): 9–36: 010841

Copyright© 2000

SAGE Publications

London, Thousand Oaks CA,

New Delhi

K E Y W O R D S

j democratic deficitj European Parliamentj European Unionj legislative institutionsj spatial models

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 9

Page 2: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

1 Introduction

This paper analyzes the evolution of the European Union’s (EU) legislativeregime since the ratification of the Single European Act (SEA) in 1987. Wecompare legislative dynamics under the four procedures in which votes inthe Council of Ministers are subject to a qualified majority (QMV) formula –the most distinctive institutional feature of the post-SEA EU.1 These pro-cedures are:

• ‘consultation’ between the Council and the EU’s executive branch, theCommission (with advice from the European Parliament); it was intro-duced in the 1957 Rome Treaty but was essentially blocked by the‘Luxembourg compromise’ until the mid 1980s;

• ‘cooperation’ (introduced in the SEA), in which the directly-elected Euro-pean Parliament was given a substantive legislative role for the first time;

• ‘codecision I’ (introduced in the Treaty on European Union signed atMaastricht in 1992), in which a Conciliation Committee was introducedto resolve disagreements between the Council and Parliament; and,

• ‘codecision II’ (from the 1997 Amsterdam treaty) which modified arrange-ments following the convocation of Conciliation Committees.

Our analysis discusses several scenarios about how the EU might operate asa polity. These are based on different preference configurations among theCouncil, Commission and Parliament.

• The ‘supranational’ scenario represents how most observers believe theEU has operated from the mid-1980s to today. Here we assume that policyconflicts reflect different views about the appropriate level of integrationamong EU institutions, and both the Commission and Parliament aremore ‘pro-integration’ than the Council members are.

• The ‘national delegates’ scenario assumes that members of the EuropeanParliament (MEPs) – in addition to ministers in the Council – are subjectto significant domestic political constraints that reduce their latitude toact as pro-Europe policy entrepreneurs. This scenario may becomeincreasingly realistic over time as European citizens become more awareof the powers wielded by the Parliament.

• The ‘strong parties’ scenario assumes that coalitions in the Council andParliament are organized on partisan, rather than national, lines. Partygroupings are prominent in the Parliament today, but these would necess-arily be considerably loosened under the national delegates scenario.Over time, however, one would expect that even if citizens hold their

European Union Politics 1(1)1 0

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 10

Page 3: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

MEPs accountable, powerful efficiency incentives would arise for boththe Council and the Parliament to become organized into party group-ings.

• The ‘regulation’ scenario assumes that conflicts among EU institutionsdo not solely reflect different preferences for the extent of integration, butalso varying preferences about the regulatory environment at the Euro-pean level that may be arrayed on a traditional left–right dimension.

We analyze these scenarios heuristically on the basis of our previous workthat uses non-cooperative game theory applied to spatial models of politicalcompetition (Garrett, 1992, 1995; Garrett and Tsebelis, 1996; Tsebelis, 1994,1995; Tsebelis and Garrett, 1997). We offer numerous insights that refine orcontradict the ‘received wisdom’ about how the EU operates as a legislativebody, or that simply are not made in existing studies. The results can be inter-preted in terms both of the types of legislative outcomes we expect to obtainand of the influence of different actors under different combinations of prefer-ence scenarios and legislative procedures.

We make two sets of propositions concerning the transition from theLuxembourg compromise to the post-SEA world (i.e. the supranational scen-ario). The first concerns the extent to which new legislation under the variousQMV-based procedures has promoted European integration. As long as thedifferences among institutional actors are about the degree of integration, themost pro-integrationist results should be expected from cooperation orconsultation, the least integrationist from codecision I, with codecision II occu-pying an intermediate position. The second set of propositions concerns therelative influence of the EU’s three legislative institutions. We argue that theCommission’s role as a legislator has declined consistently from consultation,to cooperation, to codecision I, to codecision II. The relationships between theCouncil and Parliament are more complex, and significantly affected bywhether MEPs act as national delegates or supranational entrepreneurs. TheEP is a more representative institution than the Council because its votingweights are allocated in closer proportion to national population.2 It is alsomore democratic because most decisions are taken by simple (or absolute)majority and because MEPs are directly elected whereas members of theCouncil are also ministers in national governments.

Under the national delegates scenario, the median MEP is likely to beless integrationist than the pivotal government in the Council under QMV.This will have different effects depending upon whether the status quo wasgenerated under the Luxembourg compromise or under the supranationalscenario. In the former case, new legislation will be considerably more inte-grationist under consultation and cooperation (because of the influence of the

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 1 1

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 11

Page 4: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Commission) than under both versions of codecision. Where the status quois already integrationist because it was passed under consultation or cooper-ation when the Parliament was not subject to electoral constraint (i.e. supra-nationalism), new legislation to roll back the extent of integration would notbe possible without agreement of the EP.

In the strong parties scenario policy making dynamics would then resem-ble other bicameral legislatures, with more partisan policy under unifiedgovernment and with more gridlock under divided government. In the EU,however, the threshold for unified government is extremely high – around 70percent of the votes in both the EP (as we explain) and the Council (whichdecides by QMV). Since this is not likely, one would expect strong parties inthe EU to be quite effective in bringing legislative outcomes into the Paretoset of the Council and Parliament, but once inside this set the new legislativestatus quo would be very stable.

The regulation scenario anticipates that the Council and Parliament willhave different preferences that will vary over time in a predictable manner –when one of them is dominated by the right, the other is controlled by theleft, and vice versa. This scenario again produces high levels of stability oncepolicy has been brought inside the Pareto set of the Council and Parliament.

The remainder of this article develops these arguments. Section 2 out-lines the legislative rules laid out in the SEA, the Maastricht Treaty on Euro-pean Union (TEU) and the Amsterdam treaty. Section 3 presents the baseline– supranational – model with respect to the consultation and the cooperationprocedures using the supranational scenario and then analyzes the two iter-ations of codecision. Section 4 discusses the implications of a move towardsa national delegates scenario in which MEPs are more accountable to theirnational constituencies. Section 5 explores how legislative dynamics mightchange if the EU were to evolve into a bicameral legislative government forEurope with strong parties in both chambers. Section 6 discusses the regu-lation scenario in which the differences between the actors are assumed to bealong a left–right dimension. We conclude in section 7 with a discussion ofthe limitations in existing work on European integration that our analysishighlights.

2 QMV-based legislative procedures

The Luxembourg compromise effectively governed the legislative processin the EU from at least 1966 until the ratification of the SEA in 1987 (but,see Golub, 1999). Any member of the Council could block the passage ofnew legislation in any area it considered of national interest. Effective

European Union Politics 1(1)1 2

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 12

Page 5: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

decision-making power thus rested with the member government that hadleast desire to change the status quo. All of this changed with the passage ofthe SEA. Some policy areas – typically associated with contentious issues of‘high politics’ – remained subject to unanimous Council approval. But muchof the EU’s day-to-day legislative agenda was ‘un-blocked’ by the membergovernments’ commitments both to reaffirm the application of QMV to theissues originally intended in the Rome Treaty and to bring additional policyareas under QMV.

The scope of QMV-based legislation was expanded further at Maastricht,and still further at Amsterdam. For all intents and purposes, the EU todayoperates in a way that is closer to the majoritarian practices of democraticcountries than to the unit-veto rules that obtain in most international organiz-ations. Unlike the typical nation-state pattern, however, legislative rules inthe EU vary greatly across policy areas. The right to draft initial proposalsalways lies solely with the Commission, but it cannot keep issues off theagenda if requests for bills are made by the Council or (since Maastricht) theParliament. More importantly from an analytic standpoint, the fact that theCommission makes the first proposal does not mean that it can always affectthe content of legislation that is ultimately passed.

‘Consultation’ is the simplest and oldest procedure, applying today toissue areas such as the free movement of capital, competition policy andindustrial subsidies. Commission proposals become law if they are acceptedby a qualified majority of Council members. A unanimous Council, however,can amend Commission proposals (this is also the case with all other QMV-based procedures). The Parliament plays no substantive role (but it does havean advisory one) in consultation.

The ‘cooperation’ procedure was introduced in the SEA to govern inter-nal market reform. Today, cooperation (Article 189c, TEU) applies to areassuch as social policy, implementation of regional funds, research and techno-logical development, and a number of environmental issues – though its scopewas reduced at both Maastricht and Amsterdam in favor of more use of co-decision. The most important institutional innovation of cooperation was togive the Parliament a significant legislative role. The Parliament may amendCommission proposals. If the Commission accepts these amendments theyare presented to the Council, which can either accept them under QMV oramend them unanimously. The Parliament can also reject proposals that canonly be overridden by an agreement between the Commission and a unani-mous Council.

The codecision procedure (‘codecision I’) was added to the EU’s legis-lative arsenal at Maastricht (Article 189b, TEU). In addition to replacingcooperation for internal market matters, this procedure was also applied to

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 1 3

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 13

Page 6: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

new areas of EU jurisdiction in the treaty such as education, culture, publichealth and consumer protection. There are two major institutional differencesbetween the initial form of the codecision procedure and cooperation. First,the Council could not reject EP amendments accepted by the Commission,but had to request a Conciliation Committee (comprising all members of theCouncil and numerically equal representation from the Parliament) to discusssuch amendments. Second, if the Committee could not agree to a joint text,the Council could then reaffirm its prior common position, possibly withamendments proposed by the EP. This Council proposal became law unlessan absolute majority of MEPs vetoed it.

The codecision procedure was modified in the Amsterdam Treaty (‘co-decision II’, Article 189b as amended at Amsterdam). Additional policy areaswere brought under its aegis, including equal treatment of the sexes, adminis-tration of the European Social Fund, health and safety, some aspects ofenvironmental policy and fraud. From an institutional perspective, however,the most important development of the Amsterdam reforms is that the Con-ciliation Committee is now the last stage of the legislative game. If the rep-resentatives of the Council and Parliament cannot agree to a joint text, theproposed legislation lapses (Amsterdam Treaty, Article 189b[6]). That is, themember governments decided to remove the last two stages of codecision I– the Council’s final proposal to the Parliament, and Parliament’s decisionwhether to revert to the status quo.

What do we know about the effects of these QMV-based legislative pro-cedures? Almost everyone agrees that the move to QMV has helped create alarge corpus of new pro-integration legislation. There are, however, two ele-ments of the conventional wisdom that we challenge. The first concerns themove from consultation to cooperation. For many analysts, the legislativeroles given to the Parliament under cooperation were of no real consequenceto policy outcomes (Crombez, 1996; Moser, 1996; Steunenberg, 1994). In con-trast, we argue that the Parliament’s role as a ‘conditional agenda setter’under cooperation (Tsebelis, 1994) has been of considerable legislative effect.

The second element of the conventional wisdom holds that the power ofthe Parliament was significantly increased by the first version of codecisionagreed to at Maastricht (Jacobs et al., 1995; Crombez, 1997a; Scully, 1997). Thisview concentrates on Parliament’s ability unconditionally to veto proposalsafter the Conciliation Committee, which is considered to make it a far moreinfluential legislator than under cooperation. Our analysis is different. Severalof the EP’s powers certainly were increased at Maastricht. For example, it wasempowered to vote the Commission out of office. The treaty’s effects on theParliament’s legislative powers, however, were more complicated andambiguous than the conventional wisdom assumes.

European Union Politics 1(1)1 4

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 14

Page 7: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

The transition from cooperation to codecision entailed the Parliament’sexchanging its conditional agenda-setting power for unconditional vetopower. The impact of the exchange of conditional agenda setting (cooperation)for unconditional veto (codecision I) varies with the relationship between theParliament’s preferences and those of members of the Commission and theCouncil. Under the supranational scenario (and so long as the members of theCouncil have different preferences themselves) the swap of the conditionalagenda setting under cooperation for the unconditional veto of codecision Iwas a bad deal for the Parliament – and for the pro-integration agenda.3

Our second major claim is that the reforms made to codecision at Amster-dam finally made the Parliament a co-equal legislator with the Council, nowunambiguously more powerful than it was under cooperation. The reason isthat the Council can no longer overrule the EP (not even unanimously, as incooperation) and no longer can it present take-it-or-leave-it proposals to theParliament (as was effectively the case in the codecision I endgame). Rather,Council and Parliament must bargain on equal footing over the final legis-lative outcome, with no a priori bargaining advantage inhering to either insti-tution.

Let us now develop these arguments and then move on to the questionsraised by the specter of moving from supranationalism to the national dele-gates, strong parties and regulation axis scenarios.

3 Supranational scenario

The setup

We begin our analysis using a one-dimensional spatial model in which thepreferences of a seven-member Council, the Commission and the Parliamentare arrayed on a continuum of more and less European integration (see Figure1). The seven-member Council (with equal voting weights) is the simplestway to present the EU’s QMV formula, which closely approximates five-sevenths of the member-weighted votes. Our analysis is derived from morecomplex models in multiple dimensions, which often generate conclusionsthat are different from the one-dimensional case.4 Here we report the resultsthat are unaffected by the dimensionality of the policy space.

In the supranational scenario, we assume that the Commission (strictlyspeaking, the median member of the College of Commissioners) is more inte-grationist than any member of the Council and just as pro-integration as (themedian member of) the Parliament. This set of assumptions requires somediscussion.

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 1 5

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 15

Page 8: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

First, Crombez (1997b) has recently argued against this position by contend-ing that the preferences of Commissioners are constrained by the membergovernments who choose them. He is right to point out that the existing litera-ture does not explain why the Commission adopts the positions it does. Hismodel, however, focuses on appointments alone and concludes that Com-missioners are pure national delegates. What is needed is a rational expla-nation for the integrationist behavior of Commissioners, not the identificationof non-integrationist equilibria generated by different models of Commissionselection.

We think that a series of filters and self-selection mechanisms enables theCommission to take pro-integrationist positions. National delegates of realpolitical power will likely prefer to stay in their country of origin. Moreover,appointments to different positions within the Commission are merit-based.A government may thus prefer to send to Brussels an important and inde-pendent personality who will likely exercise significant influence in the Com-mission rather than a less significant national delegate who may bemarginalized. This is not to deny, of course, that Commissioners may sharebroad political orientations with the governments that select them (as our dis-cussion of the regulation scenario discusses).

Second, considering the Parliament to be highly pro-integrationist alsoseems strange from an institutional standpoint. The Parliament is a directlyelected democratic body and citizens of the EU tend to be less supportive ofintegration than their governments are. However, citizen interest – and voterturnout – in European Parliament elections tend to be very low. Indeed, theseelections only seem to become politically visible when citizens view themessentially as mid-term referendums on (typically protest votes against) thenational government of the day (Van der Erik and Franklin, 1996). Of course,this may change as citizens become better informed about the powers of theParliament and hence about the importance of their electoral choices (thoughthis was clearly not the case in the 1999 EP elections). We discuss this possi-bility in Section 5. In addition, we also consider in Section 7 the possibility

European Union Politics 1(1)1 6

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 CommQ EP

Figure 1 The supranational scenario.Notes:1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7 – member governments in a seven-member Council of MinistersComm – the CommissionEP – the European ParliamentQ – the legislative status quo under the Luxembourg compromise

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 16

Page 9: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

that the Parliament’s preferences are significantly different from those of theCommission – with respect to regulatory reform at the European level.

Third, the supranational scenario assumes the status quo was generatedunder the Luxembourg compromise system of national vetoes and hence islocated at the ideal point of the least integrationist government in the Council.All the other relevant actors – the other members of the Council, the Com-mission and (the median voter on the floor of) the Parliament – prefer toincrease the level of integration in the EU. This captures well the politicaldynamics of the EU in the post-1987 period, during which the primary legis-lative objective has been to ‘harmonize’ Union-wide laws.

Moreover, all of our scenarios rely on an additional set of assumptions.First, we always assume that the Council members have different policypreferences. In contrast, Jacobs et. al. (1995) have argued that the Council oftenacts like a unified body. One might think the identical positions scenario isjust a special case captured by our general representation, although this is notthe case. The reason is that the ability of a unanimous Council to overruleother actors is a frequent feature of EU decision making. Clearly, identity ofpreferences equates to unanimity voting.

Second, we assume complete information for the final steps of the EU’sdifferent legislative procedures (i.e. all actors know each other’s preferencesand the location of the status quo). We do not extend this assumption to theentire structure of the procedures because this would lead to erroneousempirical conclusions. Most importantly, the decision-making game wouldnever (or almost never) reach the final stages under complete information.All actors would accept the initial proposal and the game would end, but inpractice many deliberations reach the final stage of a given procedure. Webelieve the complete information assumption to be reasonable at the end ofthe game because by this time the relevant actors have exchanged consider-able information.

Finally, we analyze the passage of specific pieces of legislation as one-shot games. Introducing the possibility of indefinite iteration would compli-cate matters considerably – involving non-cooperative bargaining betweenthe agenda setter and the actor that must accept or reject the agenda setter’sproposal. This complication is unwarranted, however, because it is rare forany legislative initiative to end in a stalemate with no decision reached. Whenthis does happen, there is no evidence of re-introductions of similar bills at alater stage (Koenig and Schulz, 1997).

Using this analytic framework, it is the last two stages of each legislativeprocess that are pivotal: Which actor makes the final proposal? To whom?Under what voting rules? Critics (Moser, 1996; Crombez, 1996, 1997a) haveargued that answering such questions is not enough. Our response is that we

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 1 7

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 17

Page 10: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

calculate subgame perfect equilibria for the final subgames of the variouslegislative games. The overall subgame perfect equilibrium strategies for allstages of the games must include these moves. In other words, no rationalactor would choose to end the game earlier unless they would receive at leastas much as our calculations suggest they would in the final play (in presentdiscounted value).

Consultation and cooperation

Under the supranational scenario, the Commission wants to make the mostpro-integrationist proposal that will be supported by a qualified majority inthe Council (see Figure 1). This coalition is clearly 34567. Government 3 is thepivotal player in the Council. The Commission will make the proposal thatis closest to its ideal point that government 3 prefers to anything the Councilcan do unanimously. Under the preference configuration in Figure 1, the Com-mission would thus make a proposal just to the left of the ideal point ofgovernment 5 and government 3 would support this proposal.

This simple example shows how the revival of QMV-based legislatingpromoted European integration. Recalcitrant governments such as 1 and 2could be outvoted. The example also demonstrates the importance of agenda-setting power – the ability to make proposals that are more difficult to amendthan to accept. The pivotal player in the Council cannot ensure that outcomesare at its ideal point. Rather, the Commission has the ability under consul-tation to choose among the policies that government 3 prefers to the statusquo.5

The primary institutional difference between consultation and cooper-ation is that the Parliament may amend Commission proposals. If these areaccepted by the Commission, the newly amended proposal returns to theCouncil which then faces the same decision as under consultation – acceptthe proposal QMV, amend under unanimity, or reject. The Parliament can alsoreject proposals that are accepted by a qualified majority in the Council’s firstreading of a bill. Only a unanimous Council can override this rejection. Thispower of the Parliament, however, is not very significant so long as it is morepro-integration than any member of the Council is. We discuss the operationof cooperation under different scenarios in subsequent sections.

The situation depicted in Figure 1 reflects the simplest case concerningcooperation. Assuming that the Parliament and the Commission are equallypro-integration, the outcome of cooperation will be the same as under consul-tation. This would also hold if the Parliament’s ideal point were anywhere tothe right of government 5. If it were between 5 and the Commission, anyParliament amendment would be acceptable to the Commission. If the

European Union Politics 1(1)1 8

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 18

Page 11: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Parliament were more integrationist than the Commission, the Parliamentcould not successfully alter the Commission’s proposal.

Under complete information, we would expect that the Commission’sinitial proposal would be at government 5, that a qualified majority in theCouncil would support this, and that the Parliament would make no amend-ments. In practice, however, Parliamentary amendments under cooperationare widespread (over 4500 from 1987 to 1993). The question then becomes,why does the Commission accept them? Tsebelis and Kalandrakis (1999)provide an answer to this question: by introducing amendments along adifferent dimension the EP can make the Commission better off if it adoptsthe amendments. Corroborating these arguments is the fact that the Com-mission subsequently accepts two-thirds of parliamentary amendments, andabout half are accepted by the Council (Tsebelis and Garrett, 1997: 87).

These data suggest three things. First, assuming complete informationthroughout the cooperation procedure is inappropriate – under completeinformation there would have been no amendments. Second, by the timeParliament makes its amendments, all actors are better informed. Parliamenttends to make amendments that the Commission will accept, and the newproposal tends to be accepted under QMV in the Council. Finally, the Parlia-ment’s conditional agenda-setting power is far from trivial. The Commissionapparently often overlooks pro-integration items when writing initial pro-posals. When the Parliament proposes these in amendments, it can often sig-nificantly change the content of legislation. We should also note, of course,that some of Parliament’s amendments are unacceptable to the Council orCommission. This could reflect mistakes in Parliament as to the preferencesof the other institutions, position taking or efforts to influence future piecesof legislation (which Tsebelis and Kalandrakis (1999) have called ‘indirectagenda setting’).

Codecision before and after Amsterdam

How did codecision I affect legislative dynamics? How were these altered bythe reformed codecision II? We provide straightforward answers to thesequestions. First, codecision I failed to make the Parliament a co-equal legis-lator with the Council – in many instances Parliament was likely to be moreinfluential under cooperation. Second, the Amsterdam reforms were sufficientto bring about the objective of Council–Parliament equality in the legislativerealm.

There are four significant institutional differences between cooperationand codecision:

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 1 9

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 19

Page 12: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

• Parliament has unconditional veto power in (both iterations of) the co-decision procedure, but it needs an alliance with the Commission or onemember of the Council in order to have its veto sustained under cooper-ation.

• Only a unanimous Council can modify those amendments made by theParliament and accepted by the Commission under cooperation. Anyamendment that the Council does not support by QMV triggers the Con-ciliation Committee.

• Under codecision I, if the Conciliation Committee failed to agree to a jointtext, the Council was able to make a ‘take-it-or-leave-it’ proposal to Parlia-ment. In contrast, this agenda-setting power lay with the Commissionand Parliament (in alliance) under cooperation.

• The Commission’s support is necessary for a proposal to become lawunder cooperation. Under codecision, however, the Commission’s formalsupport is not necessary for a proposal that garners the appropriatemajorities in the Council and Parliament.

We will address each of these institutional innovations in turn. The first twoentail a comparison of agenda-setting and veto power under cooperation andcodecision. We then move to the Amsterdam reforms to show why the Parlia-ment is a co-equal legislator under codecision II. Finally, we highlight thedecline of the Commission’s agenda setting power from consultation to co-decision II.

Agenda-setting versus veto powerBefore engaging the intricacies of the codecision procedure we wish to estab-lish the dominance of agenda-setting over veto power in legislative environ-ments. Comparing national regimes, there is a clear institutional differencebetween parliamentary and presidential systems. In presidentialism, the leg-islature is essentially given the power to make proposals that the president(the executive branch) can either veto or accept. These roles are reversed inparliamentary systems, where the cabinet government (now the executive)makes proposals to the legislature that it can accept or veto. Presidents oftenwant to gain more control over legislatures through line item vetoes. Legis-latures in parliamentary regimes complain that they operate in executivedictatorships. Why do they think that agenda-setting power is important?

The effects of agenda setting can be illustrated using a one-dimensionalspatial model, but the advantages of being the agenda setter only increase inhigher dimensions (Tsebelis, 1997). Figure 2 presents a simple illustration withtwo unitary actors, the executive (E) and the legislature (L). Both must agreefor a new proposal to become law. The content of winning proposals,

European Union Politics 1(1)2 0

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 20

Page 13: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

however, depends on which actor is the agenda setter (and on the location ofthe status quo).

Consider two different scenarios. In the parliamentary model, E makes aproposal to L that it can either veto or accept. If the policy status quo is at Q,the executive branch can propose its ideal point, Pe, and this will be acceptedby the legislature. But if L were the agenda setter (i.e. the regime were presi-dential), it could successfully propose P1 – closer to its ideal point than Pe.The same logic holds for a status quo to the right of L (Q’); the parliamentaryoutcome would be Pe’, whereas P1’ would be the presidential outcome.Indeed, the only situation in which there is no advantage to being the agendasetter is when the policy status quo is located on the E–L contract curve (e.g.Q’’). Such a policy status quo is invulnerable because there is no policy changethat would gain the support of both E and L. It should be noted, however,that the probability of an outcome already lying on the contract curve is ofmeasure zero in issues spaces of higher dimensionality.

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 2 1

Pe1 Pe1’

P1P1’

Pe Pe’

Q E Q’’ L Q’

Figure 2 Agenda setting and veto power.

EU is ‘parliamentary’ under consultation: E = Commission, L = Council, legislation = Pe or Pe’EU is ‘presidential’ under cooperation: E = Council, L = Commission & Parliament,

legislation = P1 or P1’EU is ‘parliamentary’ under codecision I: E = Council, L = Parliament, legislation = Pe or Pe’EU is ‘bicameral’ under codecision II: E = Council, L = Parliament, legislation possibly

= Pe1 or Pe1’Notes:Q, Q’, Q’’ – possible legislative status quosE – the executive branchL – the legislative branchP – winning proposalse, 1 – agenda setters

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 21

Page 14: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Agenda setting under consultation, cooperation andcodecision IIn terms of the preceding model, the EU operates as a ‘parliamentary’ regimeunder consultation procedure (the Commission acts as the executive branchand the Council is the legislature). This is the situation that seems to informmany neofunctionalist and journalistic accounts of decision making in Europe– in which the Commission is deemed the EU’s ‘government’. But things arequite different when the Parliament can amend the Council’s common posi-tion. We have already noted the frequency and influence of Parliament’samendments under cooperation. The trend continued under codecision I.Between 1993 and 1995, for example, Parliament proposed over 1000 codeci-sion amendments. Around three-quarters of these amendments were acceptedby the Commission; and more than half were subsequently accepted QMVby the Council.

Amendments are a fact of life under cooperation and codecision I (andcodecision II, we presume), but their effects differ under the various legis-lative procedures. When legislation is governed by cooperation, Parliamentcan use amendments to give it significant agenda-setting powers. But undercodecision I, we believe that the existence of Parliament amendments allowedthe Council to exercise effective agenda-setting authority for the first timeunder QMV.

Consider the cooperation procedure first and assume that the Parliamenthas made 10 amendments to the Council’s common position (and that theCommission has accepted them). These amendments then return to theCouncil, which must decide whether to accept them by QMV. There are 210

(=1024) possible sets of amendments that the Council could support (of theform 0000000001, 0000000010, etc. where the ones represent included amend-ments). Only one of these could be passed by QMV – 1111111111; the remain-ing 1023 require Council unanimity. In cases where the Commission acceptsits amendments, the Parliament has considerable agenda-setting power underthe cooperation procedure.

Now consider the same scenario under codecision I, but taking intoaccount this procedure’s institutional differences from cooperation. Assumefor the moment, by backwards induction, that the Conciliation Committeedid not agree to a joint text because one of the actors – we argue, the Council– knew it could do better by moving to the final stages of the procedure. Therehas been considerable disagreement about what the clause of the MaastrichtTreaty (Article 189b[6]) that governs the codecision I endgame meant. Recallthat if the Conciliation Committee broke down, the Council made a proposalthat became law unless an absolute majority of the Parliament voted againstit.

European Union Politics 1(1)2 2

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 22

Page 15: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

What proposal could the Council make? The Maastricht Treaty’s wordingwas that the Council could introduce the common position ‘to which it agreedbefore the conciliation procedure was initiated, possibly with amendmentsproposed by the European Parliament’. This provision could be interpretedin numerous ways. The most restrictive interpretation is that the Councileither could select the previously adopted common position or it could addsome of the EP amendments – but without any modifications to the particu-lar amendments (Moser, 1996). Elsewhere, we have used a looser interpre-tation: the Council could modify or combine amendments as it saw fit(Garrett, 1995; Garrett and Tsebelis, 1996; Tsebelis and Garrett, 1996). Sincethe Council could exclude any particular EP amendment, it could certainlyadopt a more pro-EP position and include this amendment in a modifiedform. In any event, the Council’s position would avoid an EP veto by absol-ute majority. This interpretation turns the Council into an unconstrainedagenda setter under codecision I because it could essentially propose to theParliament any variation of its common position that it wanted.

But even if one uses the more restrictive reading of 189b(6) from Maas-tricht, the Council’s latitude in the proposal made to the Parliament wouldstill have been considerable. Under codecision I, the Council could choosefreely – always voting by QMV – among the 210 possible modifications of thecommon position the one it most preferred to propose to the Parliament. Itis in this sense that agenda-setting power was taken from the Parliament andgiven to the Council by codecision I.

The implications of this change in the location of agenda-setting powerare clear. Applying the supranational scenario to Figure 2 – in which the statusquo (Q) is less integrationist than the QMV pivot in the Council (E) and theParliament (L) is more pro-integration – the EU acts as a ‘presidential’ regimeunder cooperation. The legislative outcome would be P1 rather than Pe. Butthe situation is reversed under codecision I: the EU was more ‘parliamentary’because the Council could successfully propose Pe to the Parliament after theConciliation Committee broke down. If the governments that signed theTreaty on European Union intended to make the Parliament a co-equal legis-lator at Maastricht, the procedure they created failed to achieve this objective.

Agenda setting under codecision IIThe reforms of the codecision procedure undertaken at Amsterdam entailedone crucial institutional change. With the recent ratification of the treaty, theConciliation Committee has become (for all intents and purposes) the finalstep in codecision II. As a result, agenda setting now resides with this Con-ciliation Committee, or (alternatively) with both the Council and the Parlia-ment. It seems that the EP understood the limitations of codecision I from the

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 2 3

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 23

Page 16: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

beginning. It tried to eliminate the final stage from the beginning by passingRule 78. This rule required the President of the Parliament to ask the Com-mission and the Council to withdraw the bill should an agreement not bereached in the Conciliation Committee, and then placed the Council text fora rejection vote (Hix, 1999b).

Decision making in the Committee resembles an unstructured non-cooperative bargaining game in which the agreement of the representativesfrom both the Council and the Parliament is necessary for a new law to bepassed, and representatives are able to make as many amendments andcounter-proposals as they wish.6 One could analyze this Conciliation Com-mittee bargaining game in two ways. The representatives of the two cham-bers could be considered as unitary actors, or we could think of them asindependent actors whose preferences are aggregated using QMV (forCouncil members) and simple majority (for the Parliament’s representatives)decision rules. Which is more appropriate depends on the internal organiz-ation of the representatives from the Council and Parliament in the Concili-ation Committee. If (as we think likely) commitments made within each ofthese small delegations are likely to be credible, there is little to be gainedfrom moving to the far more complex environment in which bargaining issimultaneously taking place among the Council and Parliament representa-tives and between the two groups (Tsebelis and Money, 1997).

In terms of the simple representation in Figure 2, legislation approved bythe Conciliation Committee under codecision II will be somewhere on theinterval E–L. If the status quo is Q (i.e. under the supranational scenario), thelegislative outcome must be at least as good for the Parliament (L) as undercodecision I (where legislation would be passed at Pe). Moreover, Parliamentmay do better under codecision II than cooperation because it can now vetoCouncil proposals unconditionally, whereas under cooperation it needed thesupport of either the Commission or one member of the Council.

In the supranational scenario, the Parliament’s position is thereforestronger under codecision II than it was under codecision I because theCouncil is no longer the effective agenda setter in the endgame. In insti-tutional terms, the Council and the Parliament are now co-equal legislatorsand the EU’s legislative regime is truly bicameral. Legislative outcomes, as aresult, will tend to be more integrationist under the reformed codecision thanunder its initial design at Maastricht – so long as the supranational scenariois appropriate.

Making more precise predictions about legislation passed under codeci-sion II is a hazardous enterprise. The simplest way to think about bargainingin the Conciliation Committee under codecision II would be to use Nash’scooperative approach – predicting an outcome half way between Pe (Pe’) and

European Union Politics 1(1)2 4

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 24

Page 17: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

P1 (P1’), that is Pe1 (Pe1’) in Figure 2. The same result would be obtained usingnon-cooperative game theory either if both actors were infinitely patient(Rubinstein, 1982) or if they were equally patient and a random draw deter-mines which actor makes the initial proposal (Baron and Ferejohn, 1989).

This ‘split-the-difference’ prediction about codecision II can only be sus-tained, however, if one believes that neither of the legislative ‘chambers’ inthe EU – the Council and Parliament – possesses any bargaining advantagesover the other. In our single dimension model if the status quo is not locatedbetween the Parliament and the Council, one of the two institutions will belocated closer to the status quo than the other. This institution may be ableeffectively to present the other with a ‘take-it-or-leave-it’ offer. But if there areany such positional advantages, they will lessen as the dimensionality of thepolicy space increases and any institutional advantages will come to play amore significant role.

As the codecision procedure is now written, there is no clear institutionaladvantage for one chamber over the other. But, for example, if one were tothink that generating an absolute majority in the Parliament is harder thanforming a qualified majority in the Council, this would give a bargainingadvantage to Parliament’s delegation in the Conciliation Committee. Con-versely, if getting an agreement in the Council is more difficult, the Councilcould turn this difficulty into a bargaining advantage (for alternative analy-ses, see Crombez, 2000 and Steunenberg and Dimitrova, 1999).

The changing role of the commission as a legislator

We have devoted considerable attention to the changing balance of legislativeinfluence between the Council and the Parliament in the EU since 1987because the fate of the Parliament is central to many arguments about thedemocratic deficit. But attention to the Council–Parliament relationshipshould not obscure the other clear consequence of the move from consultationto codecision II. The formal agenda-setting powers of the Commission havebeen systematically degraded in the past decade. Under codecision (I and II),the Commission plays a significantly smaller role in determining the finalcontent of legislation than under consultation or cooperation. Crombez (2000),based on the fact that the Commission does not have a vote in the concilia-tion committee, goes so far as to claim that the Commission plays no legis-lative role at all under codecision II. This is an overstatement. Under completeinformation, for example, the Commission can still identify proposals thatrepresent an improvement over the status quo for both the required majori-ties in the EP and the Council, and which the two actors cannot modify at

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 2 5

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 25

Page 18: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

all.7 Nonetheless, such details should not obscure the fact that the Commis-sion’s legislative role has declined appreciably since the mid-1980s.

This change in the role of the Commission as a legislator has significantimplications for neofunctionalist approaches to European integration. Thepower of the Commission as a legislator has been eroded in each one of therevisions of the Rome treaty. In the EU’s founding treaty, the Commissionalone had agenda-setting power (in the consultation procedure). The Com-mission had to share its agenda-setting role with the Parliament under cooper-ation. Codecision I effectively shifted agenda setting to the Council; theCouncil and the Parliament share agenda setting under codecision II. More-over, the lessening of the Commission’s legislative influence will only beexacerbated in the future if, as seems likely, more issue areas will be broughtunder the reformed codecision.

Of course, neofunctionalist arguments about the Commission’s influencedo not depend solely on legislative agenda setting. They also emphasize theCommission’s autonomy in the implementation of EU legislation, as well asthe ability of the Commission to shape the preferences of other actors (suchas the governments in the Council) in virtue of their expertise and informationadvantages. Elsewhere, we explore the interrelationships between legislationand implementation – and the impact of changes in legislative procedures onthe Commission’s overall influence on European integration (Tsebelis andGarrett, 1999). For present purposes, however, we only wish to point out thesecular decline in the Commission’s legislative influence since the passage ofthe SEA.

The remaining influence of the Commission over legislation is thus likelyto rely more on informal channels – asymmetries of information, persuasion,deal-brokering – than on the formal roles written into the various procedures.But it should also be pointed out that even these informal powers may wellbe damaged permanently by the resignation of the Santer Commission underthe threat of Parliamentary removal.

4 The national delegates scenario

The preceding two sections have been based on the supranational scenariothat we consider to be a reasonable characterization of much EU legislativepolitics in the past decade. Let us now speculate about potential changes inthe underlying structure of EU politics and their effects on the legislativeprocess.

Moving to the national delegates scenario entails two modifications fromsupranationalism. These concern the policy status quo and the preferences of

European Union Politics 1(1)2 6

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 26

Page 19: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

the Parliament relative to those of the Council. Our analysis thus far hasassumed that the policy status quo was less integrationist than the ideal pointof the QMV-pivot in the Council (reflecting the logic of the Luxembourg com-promise). In cases where new areas are brought under the QMV-based pro-cedures (as was the case at both Maastricht and Amsterdam) this assumptionwill remain appropriate. But in areas where an issue is shifted from one QMV-based procedure to another (such as the shift of internal market matters fromcooperation to codecision), it may be more appropriate to assume that thepolicy status quo is already considerably more integrationist (i.e. generatedsince 1987).

If the post-1987 legislative status quo lies on the contract curve betweenthe ideal points of the pivotal government in the Council and those of theCommission (under consultation), the Commission and the Parliament (undercooperation), and the Parliament (under codecision), it will be stable – so longas the preferences of the relevant actors remain similar. This would hold trueeven for policy areas in which the legislative decision rules have been changed(for example from cooperation to codecision) because under all the QMV-based procedures outcomes are generated between the ideal points of the rel-evant institutional actors.8

Policy stability, however, is only guaranteed so long as the relative pos-itions of institutional actors remain the same. Perhaps the most likely changeto this constellation in the coming years is that the preferences of MEPs willbecome less integrationist relative to those of Council members. The supra-national assumption about the Parliament depends on the freedom of MEPsto act independently of the constituencies that elect them – in virtue of thegeneral public’s disinterest in politics at the European level. Today, this is stillan entirely reasonable assumption – as the June 1999 elections show. But ascitizens come to understand the power of the Parliament, they may well takeEP elections more seriously. If and when this happens, Parliament’s medianvoter would likely become less integrationist. European citizens on averageare much less integrationist than their MEPs; they are also less integrationistthan their own national governments. As a result, one might reasonablyexpect that the preferences of the median MEP under a national delegatesmodel might be less integrationist than most of the governments in theCouncil.

Our definition of the national delegates scenario is thus a situation inwhich the median MEP is less integrationist than the QMV pivot in theCouncil. The legislative effects of this scenario, however, depend upon thepolicy status quo. For new issue areas brought under QMV-based proceduresin the future, the status quo will be that under the Luxembourg compromise(i.e. less integrationist than both the median MEP and the QMV-pivot). In this

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 2 7

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 27

Page 20: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

case, the extent of integration would clearly decrease the greater the Parlia-ment’s legislative role.

Things would be different, however, where the policy status quo wasgenerated under QMV-based procedures with a supranational Parliament.Legislation first passed under consultation and still governed by this pro-cedure would be stable. The status quo would be invulnerable under cooper-ation because if the Parliament has incentives to make amendments that areless integrationist than those preferred by the Commission, the Commissionwould not agree to any of them. In this case, however, the Parliament’samendments would still become law if they were supported unanimously inthe Council. If legislation was passed under codecision I but then reassessedunder codecision II, the QMV-pivot in the Council could block less integra-tionist proposals made by the Parliament. This could apply, for example, tointernal market legislation passed between 1993 and the ratification of theAmsterdam treaty in 1999.

Legislative rollback by a Parliament of national delegates would be poss-ible, however, where the status quo was generated under either consultationor cooperation – but is now subject to codecision II. This scenario is likely tobe particularly important in the future as more and more legislation comesto be governed by the post-Amsterdam version of codecision.

Thus, there is a potential tradeoff in empowering the European Parlia-ment, that most of its supporters have not seen. The goal of increasing thepower of the Parliament has been to reduce the democratic deficit in Europe.With the ratification of the Amsterdam treaty, this was achieved in the legis-lative arena by making the EU bicameral. But one consequence of empower-ing the Parliament is likely to be European citizens taking MEP elections moreseriously. In turn, this may lead Parliament to use its new powers in waysthat slow down or roll back the pace of European integration. Increaseddemocracy has long been thought of as a central part of the European inte-gration project. But ironically, reducing the democratic deficit may in factretard integration in the future.

5 The strong parties scenario

This section discusses the potential for the evolution of strong party organiz-ations in the EU and the effects of this on legislative dynamics. Several analy-ses of the EU have focused on the role of the supranational party systemgenerated inside the EP (Hix, 1999a; Hix and Lord, 1997; Hooghe and Marks,1999; Kreppel, 1998; Raunio, 1997). In our national delegates scenario, boththe Council and the Parliament are responsive to the interests of their

European Union Politics 1(1)2 8

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 28

Page 21: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

constituents ‘back home’, but in different ways. The Council is indirectlyelected and citizens are unlikely to vote their representatives out of officepurely on the basis of their EU activities. In contrast, MEPs are directly electedand hence should be more responsive to their constituents. In this importantsense, the Parliament under national delegates would be a more democraticinstitution than the Council. But indirect election of the Council has clearlybeen essential to making European integration possible. Direct representationof national governments in the Council is the quid pro quo required for sov-ereign states to accept the pooling of their sovereignty at the supranationallevel.

If the EU is to move further in the direction of federation in the comingyears, one likely institutional feature of this transition would be the buildingof strong party organizations, both within the Council and the Parliament,and between the two chambers. There are powerful incentives for legislativeentrepreneurs to promote party organizations within individual chambers(Cox and McCubbins, 1993). But similar arguments could also be made aboutcoordination across chambers in bicameral legislatures.

This section speculates about the legislative consequences of a movetowards strong parties in the Council and the Parliament. Our basic intuitionis that the strengthening of parties would both make it easier to pass newlegislation within the Pareto set of the Council and the Parliament, and torender such legislation less vulnerable to challenge over time. We do not con-centrate on the different rules for selecting members of both chambers becausestrong parties would tend to take and enforce the same positions across del-egations in both the EP and the Council. Rather, we focus on the differencesin the institutional rules that govern behavior within the chambers, and theeffects of party organization on the relationship between these rules and legis-lative outputs.

The Council is an institution with a built in status quo bias. Decisionsrequire at least a qualified majority. The strengthening of parties would notbreak up such an impasse unless a new party organization (or coalition ofparties) could control over 70 percent of Council votes. Such supermajoritiesare rare in the history of parliamentary politics.

A similar supermajoritarian picture emerges with respect to the EuropeanParliament if we consider two factors. First, in the second round of all legis-lative procedures, an absolute majority of MEPs is required for the passageof legislation. Second, the absentee rate among Parliamentarians is high.Tsebelis (forthcoming) has argued that the combination of these two factorscreates a ‘qualified majority equivalent’ because the 50 percent of the votesnecessary has to be found among the (say, 70 percent of) MEPs present onthe floor.

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 2 9

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 29

Page 22: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Combining two supermajoritarian institutions and asking their agree-ment for new legislation creates a formidable bias in favor of the status quo.Indeed, only existing policies outside the Pareto set both of the Parliamentand of the Council could be modified regardless of the procedure used. Thesituation is likely to become more rigid than the USA where filibuster rulesrequire a three-fifths majority in the Senate for cloture (with simple majori-ties being used in the House.)9

6 The regulation scenario

Up until now, we have based our analyses of EU legislative dynamics on theassumption that the primary policy differences among the different Europeaninstitutions concerned the extent of integration each desires. This is the domi-nant assumption in the literature, but in this section we want to analyze a differ-ent scenario that reflects another set of common policy conflicts in the EU.

On the basis of voting records in the Parliament between 1989 and 1994,Kreppel and Tsebelis (1999) show that traditional left–right divisions charac-terized many issues, and that the Socialist group was very influential in thepassage of bills. They conjecture that the differences between the EP and theCouncil may often have occurred not on an integration axis so much as onan axis of regulation, with the left in the Parliament pushing for more commonregulations across Europe.

Kreppel and Tsebelis’s approach is consistent with the view that Euro-pean Parliament elections are second-order national elections (Marsh, 1998;Reif, 1997). Classical partisan differences in MEP behavior may arise not onlybecause the people of Europe do not understand what is going on in the Euro-pean Union; partisanship may also be important because citizens considerEuropean elections in the national framework. European elections usuallyoccur between national elections, when the popularity of the party/coalitionin government is typically relatively low. Consequently, the opposition at thenational level may gain in EP elections in the same way as the president’sparty loses seats in mid-term elections in the USA.

From the late 1980s to the mid-1990s, most EU member governments werecenter–right (with a clear move to the left in recent years). This allowed leftparties to take advantage of mid-term slumps in national governments’ popu-larity to perform very well in European Parliament elections. Thus, in thisperiod when the EU was taking on the core of the internal market agenda –transferring regulatory competencies from the national to supranational levels– the right dominated the Council, whereas the left was more powerful in theParliament.

European Union Politics 1(1)3 0

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 30

Page 23: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Analyzing the legislative process on the assumption of partisan politicswith clear differences between the Council and the Parliament requires anumber of changes to the scenarios previously discussed. First, the move fromsupranationalism to national delegates to strong parties essentially concernedchanges within the Parliament. The regulation scenario, in contrast, givesprimacy to the Council – or more precisely to national electoral politics withinmember states. For example, the shift in recent years of the center of politi-cal gravity from the right to the left in most EU countries would have noimpact on any of our previous scenarios, but we would have predicted (astranspired) a shift to the right in the 1999 EP elections.

Second, all our earlier analyses were premised on the existence of a con-stant coalition between Parliament and Commission. Since the Councilappoints it, we might expect that the Commission is more likely to side withthe Council on many matters. Alternatively, one might contend that the tech-nocrats in the Commission would tend to be quite conservative on most regu-latory matters, and hence that they would be more likely to side with theCouncil when it was dominated by right-wing governments (as opposed tointegration issues, where the Council and Commission are always likely todiffer considerably). In the period up to the mid-1990s, it is not possible todistinguish between these two interpretations, but this will change in thecoming years given the changed partisan composition of the Council andParliament in 1999 and beyond.

Third, in cases where the Commission’s preferences are closer to theCouncil’s than the Parliament’s, the conditional agenda-setting powers of theEP under cooperation are eliminated. This is because a coalition betweenCommission and Parliament is a necessary condition for conditional agendasetting. But this would have little effect on codecision because of the Com-mission’s greatly diminished role under both versions of the procedures.

In sum, this section has speculated about an organization of the Euro-pean political space that is more ‘mature’ in some senses than that envisagedpreviously. Instead of primarily concerning the scope of European integration,the regulation scenario analyzes how an integrated Europe should be gov-erned. It also entertains a political dynamic in which differences in electoralcycles tend to generate partisan-balancing behavior by citizens. This scenariomay already generate leverage over certain policy dynamics in the recent past(including regulation of the internal market), but it might become increas-ingly apposite in the future.

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 3 1

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 31

Page 24: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

7 Conclusion

This paper provides a comprehensive overview of EU legislative dynamics,with respect both to all the QMV-based procedures and to a range of plaus-ible scenarios for the future path of European integration. We have made fivebasic points, all of which can be best illustrated with respect to the legislativeregime settled on at Amsterdam. First, the collective will of the EU govern-ments in the past decade has manifestly been geared to democratizing de-cision making by empowering the Parliament. The Amsterdam revisions ofthe codecision procedure make the Parliament a coequal legislator with theCouncil and relegate the Commission to a more traditional bureaucratic rolein policy making.

Second, so long as the Parliament is a pro-integrationist entrepreneur thatis essentially unconstrained by the will of European citizens, the codecisionII regime will ensure that new legislation will advance the integration agendamore than is desired by the pivotal government in the Council under QMV.This was not the case with the initial Maastricht version of codecision becauseagenda-setting power reverted to the Council in the legislative endgame.Making the Conciliation Committee the final stage of codecision eliminatedthis Council bargaining advantage.

Third, if and when MEPs become more responsive to the demands oftheir constituents with respect to European integration, the power of theParliament may under some circumstances result in legislative rollback of theintegrationist agenda. Despite common assumptions to the contrary, reduc-ing the democratic deficit may actually slow down the pace of European inte-gration.

Fourth, the EU is evolving into a bicameral legislature with the bias infavor of the status quo that it entails. This tendency is strengthened by thefact that the Council decides not by simple majority but by QMV. In addition,a similar de facto qualified majority threshold exists for Parliamentary deci-sions because of absolute majority voting requirements and the high level ofabsenteeism inside the EP. As is the case in the USA, this configuration willnot permit policy changes that are not supported by an overwhelming major-ity of the actors involved.

Finally, if the differences between Council and EP are on issues of regu-lation, that is, along the traditional left–right axis, the Commission is morelikely to be the ally of the Council and not of the Parliament. In addition, thedifferences between the two actors may be structural rather than accidental.A right-(left-) wing Council (generated by national elections) will tend toappoint a right-(left-) wing Commission, but in turn this will tend to resultin swings to the left (right) in the next round of Parliament elections.

European Union Politics 1(1)3 2

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 32

Page 25: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Notes

We thank participants at a seminar at the University of Minnesota and two anony-mous reviewers for helpful comments. Tsebelis would like to acknowledge finan-cial support provided by NSF grant # SBA 9511485.

1 The Council is a body in which cabinet ministers from member governmentsdeliberate collectively on EU policy. QMV is a voting rule in which the votesof member governments are weighted and in which roughly five-sevenths ofthese weighted votes are required for passage. In the current 15-member EU,these weights are – France, Germany, Italy and the United Kingdom: 10;Spain: 8; Belgium, Greece, the Netherlands and Portugal: 5; Sweden andAustria: 4; Denmark, Finland and Ireland: 3; Luxembourg: 2. From the totalof 87, 62 votes constitute a qualified majority.

2 The current allocations of the 626 members of the Parliament are – Germany:99; France, Italy and the UK: 87; Spain: 64; the Netherlands: 31; Belgium,Greece and Portugal: 25; Sweden: 22; Austria: 21; Denmark and Finland: 16;Ireland: 15; and Luxembourg: 6.

3 This does not take into account issues where the Council is unanimous andconsequently the agenda-setting power of the Parliament and the Commis-sion does not exist. Issues of constitutional division of power (such as whomonitors implementation of legislation) would fall in this category.

4 For analyses in multiple dimensions, see Tsebelis (1994, 1995, 1997). One-dimensional models of the EU often report no agenda-setting role for theParliament. But higher dimensionality models reveal that such agenda-settingpower is significant (Tsebelis and Kalandrakis, 1999).

5 The situation would obviously be different if the status quo were betweenthe ideal points of government 3 and the Commission. Here, there would beno proposal the Commission would want to make that government 3 wouldsupport – the status quo would be invulnerable. Following the rapid pace oflegislating in the past decade, this may now characterize some policy areassubject to consultation.

6 Strictly speaking, any joint text produced by the Conciliation Committee mustbe passed in both parent chambers – QMV in the Council and by absolutemajority in the Parliament. Since all Council members are represented in theConciliation Committee and since the Parliament’s delegation can beexpected to mirror the sentiments of all its members, one should expect thisfinal ratification to be unproblematic. There is only one instance where a jointtext has not been passed into law: the conciliation committee report on legalprotection of biotechnological inventions was rejected by Parliament(Tsebelis, 1997: 37).

7 Technically speaking, the Commission can make a proposal that is located inthe winset of the status quo and in the ‘core’ of the qualified majority of theCouncil and the absolute majority of the EP. Such a proposal will pass withoutamendments: it will be accepted (because it belongs in the winset) and cannotbe modified (because it belongs to the core). The core does not always exist,but the required high thresholds for decisions in the Council and effectively

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 3 3

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 33

Page 26: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

in the EP make the existence of the core more likely. For a discussion of theissue, see Tsebelis and Garrett (1999).

8 This is only strictly true in a one-dimensional policy space. In multiple dimen-sions, stability will be defined more broadly in terms of the core and theuncovered set (Tsebelis, 1997).

9 Majorities of two-thirds are required to override presidential vetoes in theUSA, but this is still lower than the five-sevenths QMV requirement in theCouncil.

References

Baron, David P. and John A. Ferejohn (1989) ‘Bargaining in Legislatures’, AmericanPolitical Science Review 83: 1181–206.

Cox, Gary W. and Mathew D. McCubbins (1993) Legislative Leviathan. Berkeley:University of California Press.

Crombez, Christophe (1996) ‘Legislative Procedures in the European Community’,British Journal of Political Science 26: 199–228.

Crombez, Christophe (1997a) ‘The Co-Decision Procedure in the European Union’,Legislative Studies Quarterly 22: 97–119.

Crombez, Christophe (1997b) ‘Policy Making and Commission Appointment inthe European Union’, Aussenwirtschaft 52: 63–82.

Crombez, Christophe (2000, forthcoming) ‘The Treaty of Amsterdam and theCodecision Procedure’, in Mark D. Aspinwall and Gerald Schneider (eds) TheRules of Integration. Manchester: University of Manchester Press.

Garrett, Geoffrey (1992) ‘International Cooperation and Institutional Choice’,International Organization 46: 533–60.

Garrett, Geoffrey (1995) ‘From The Luxembourg Compromise to Codecision:Decision Making in the European Union’, Electoral Studies 14: 289–308.

Garrett, Geoffrey and George Tsebelis (1996) ‘An Institutional Critique of Inter-governmentalism’, International Organization 50: 269–99.

Golub, Jonathan (1999) ‘The Shadow of the Vote’, International Organization.Hix, Simon (1999a) ‘Dimensions and Alignments in European Union Politics:

Cognitive Constraints and Partisan Responses’, European Journal of PoliticalResearch 35: 69–106.

Hix, Simon (1999b) ‘Constitutional Agenda-Setting through Discretion in RuleInterpretation: Why the European Parliament Won at Amsterdam’. Paperpresented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association,Atlanta, GA.

Hix, Simon and Christopher Lord (1997) Political Parties in the European Union.London: Macmillan.

Hooghe, Liesbet and Gary Marks (1999) ‘The Making of a Polity’, in HerbertKitschelt et al. (eds) The Politics and Political Economy of Advanced IndustrialSocieties, pp. 70–97. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Jacobs, Francis, Richard Corbett and Michael Shackleton (1995) The EuropeanParliament, 3rd edn. Essex: Longman.

Koenig, Thomas and Heiner Schulz (1997) ‘The Efficiency of Legislative Decision

European Union Politics 1(1)3 4

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 34

Page 27: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

Making in the European Union’. Berkeley Working Paper 1.54, Center forGerman and European Studies, University of California.

Kreppel, A (1998) ‘The Evolution of the European Parliament and SupranationalParty System’. PhD dissertation, UCLA.

Kreppel, Amie and George Tsebelis (1999) ‘Coalition Formation in the EuropeanParliament’, Comparative Political Studies (December).

Marsh, Michael (1998) ‘Testing the Second-Order Election Model after FourEuropean Elections’, British Journal of Political Science 28: 591–607.

Moser, Peter (1996) ‘The European Parliament as a Conditional Agenda Setter:What are the Conditions?’, American Political Science Review 90: 834–8.

Raunio, Tapio (1997) The European Perspective: Transnational Party Groups in the1989–1994 European Parliament. London: Ashgate.

Reif, Karlheinz (1997) ‘European Elections as Member State Second-OrderElections Revisited’, European Journal of Political Research 31: 115–24.

Rubinstein, Ariel (1982) ‘Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Game’, Econometrica50: 97–109.

Scully, Roger M. (1997) ‘The European Parliament and the Co-Decision Procedure:A Re-Assessment’, Journal of Legislative Studies 3(3): 58–73.

Steunenberg, Bernard (1994) ‘Decisionmaking under Different InstitutionalArrangements’, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 150: 642–69.

Steunenberg, Bernard and Antoaneta Dimitrova (1999) ‘Interests, Legitimacy andConstitutional Choice’. Mimeo, University of Twente.

Tsebelis, George (1994) ‘The Power Of the European Parliament as a ConditionalAgenda Setter’, American Political Science Review 88: 128–42.

Tsebelis, George (1995) ‘Conditional Agenda Setting and Decision Making insideThe European Parliament’, Journal of Legislative Studies 1: 65–93.

Tsebelis, George (1997) ‘Maastricht and the Democratic Deficit’, Aussenwirtschaft52: 29–56.

Tsebelis, George (forthcoming) ‘Veto Players and Institutional Analysis’, Govern-ance.

Tsebelis, George and Geoffrey Garrett (1996) ‘Agenda Setting Power, PowerIndices and Decision Making in the European Union’, International Review ofLaw and Economics 16: 345–61.

Tsebelis, George and Geoffrey Garrett (1997) ‘Agenda Setting, Vetoes and theEuropean Union’s Co-decision Procedure’, Journal of Legislative Studies 3(3):74–92.

Tsebelis, George and Geoffrey Garrett (1999) ‘The Institutional Determinants ofSupranationalism in the EU’. Mimeo, UCLA.

Tsebelis, George and Anastassios Kalandrakis (1999) ‘European Parliament andEnvironmental Legislation: The Case of Chemicals’, European Journal of PoliticalResearch 36(1): 119–54.

Tsebelis, George and Jeanette Money (1997) Bicameralism. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Van der Erik, Cees and Mark Franklin (1996) Choosing Europe? The European Elec-torate and National Politics in the Face of Union. Ann Arbor: University ofMichigan Press.

Tsebelis and Garrett Legislative Politics in the EU 3 5

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 35

Page 28: 3 Tsebelis Garrett OBL

About the authors

George Tsebelis is Professor of Political Science at UCLA, Los Angeles,CA 90095 USA. (http: //www.polisci.ucla.edu/tsebelis/ ).Fax: +1 310 825 0778E-mail: [email protected]

Geoffrey Garrett is Professor of Political Science at Yale University,New Haven, CT 06520 USA. (http: //www.pantheon.yale.edu/~gmg8).Fax: +1 203 432 1453E-mail: [email protected]

European Union Politics 1(1)3 6

02 Tsebelis (jr/d) 10/12/99 8:55 am Page 36