5 a cognitive neuroscience perspective on confabulation: commentary by jorge canestri (rome)

Upload: maximiliano-portillo

Post on 27-Feb-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    1/6

    This article was downloaded by: [Gazi University]On: 18 August 2014, At: 22:50Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: MortimerHouse, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journalfor Psychoanalysis and the NeurosciencesPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20

    A Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective onConfabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri(Rome)Jorge Canestri

    a

    aVia Sesto Rufo 23, 00136 Rome, Italy, e-mail: . or

    Published online: 09 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article:Jorge Canestri (2000) A Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary byJorge Canestri (Rome), Neuropsychoanalysis: An Interdisciplinary Journal for Psychoanalysis and the Neurosciences, 2:2,

    144-148, DOI: 10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) containedin the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make norepresentations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose ofthe Content. Anyopinions and views expressedin this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be reliedupon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shallnot be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and otherliabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematicreproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in anyform to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/15294145.2000.10773297http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rnpa20
  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    2/6

    44

    McCarley, R. W. (1977), The brain as a dream state

    generator: An activation-synthesis hypothesis of the

    dream process. Amer.

    Psychiatry 134:1335 1348.

    Kernberg, O. (1984), Severe Personality Disorders. New

    Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Meltzer, D. (1984),

    Dream Life.

    Perthshire, Scotland: Clu

    nie Press.

    Mesulam, M.-M. (1998), F rom sensation to cognition.

    Brain 121:1013 1052.

    Moscovitch, M., Melo, B. (1997), Strategic retrieval and

    the frontal lobes: Evidence from confabulation and am

    nesia. Neuropsychologia 35:1017 1034.

    Nathaniel-James, D., Frith, C. (1996), Confabulation in

    schizophrenia. Psycholog. Med. 26:391 399.

    Perrett, D., Rolls, E., Caan, W. (1982), Visual neurones

    responsive to faces in the monkey temporal cortex. Ex-

    periment. Brain Res. 47:329 342.

    Reiser, M. (1990), Memory in Mind and Brain: What Dream

    Imagery Reveals. New York: Basic Books.

    Jorge Canestri

    Robinson, M., Freeman, W. (1954), Psychosurgery and

    the Self. New York: Grone Stratton.

    Schilder, P. (1930), Studies concerning the psychology and

    symptomatology

    of

    general paresis. In: Organization

    and

    Pathology

    of

    Thought ed. D. Rapaport. New York: Co

    lumbia University Press, 1951, pp.

    519-580.

    States, B. (1995), Dreaming

    accidentally

    of Harold

    Pinter: The interplay

    of

    metaphor

    and

    metonymy in

    dreams. Dreaming 5:229 245.

    Szalita, A. (1958), Regression and perception in psychotic

    states. Psychiatry 2 :53-63.

    Weinstein, E., Lyerly, O. (1968), Confabulation follow

    ing brain injury: Its analogues and sequelae. Arch. Gen.

    Psychiatry 18:348 354.

    Mark Blechner Ph.D.

    145 Central Park West

    New ork 10023

    A Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation

    Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    DeLuca's paper presents the psychoanalyst with sev

    eral interesting points: an accurate examination of a

    pathological phenomenon (confabulation) whose

    definition, uniqueness, and causality are still under

    discussion; an alternative model constructed on the

    cognitive neuroscience perspective emphasizing the

    differences between the various forms of confabula

    tion; and the possibility of comparison with psychoan

    alytic theories, specifically relative to this

    phenomenon as well as in a wider sense concerning

    the verisimilitude

    of

    certain statements of Freudian

    metapsychology.

    The neurosciences can offer to psychoanalysis

    some tools that allow one to verify the biological plau

    sibility of certain psychoanalytic hypotheses and to

    find confirmation or refutation of them in the experi

    mental field, while psychoanalysis can supply the neu

    rosciences with a heuristic potential that cannot be

    underestimated. In these brief notes I will try to illus

    trate this viewpoint.

    My task in presenting these notes is greatly facili

    tated by Mark Solms's comment, which excuses me

    from describing the fundamental principles of the

    Freudian topographical model of the mind (Freud,

    1900, 1911, 1915). With the addition of examples

    taken from his clinical experience with bilateral ven

    tromesial frontal lesioned patients, Solms highlights

    what is essential to the Freudian task: the problem of

    the psychoanalyst is not only to construct a causal

    hypothesis, but above all to find meaning in the mani

    festations of psychic life. This is evidenced by the

    different consideration that the symptoms merit in De

    Luca's work and in the discussion by Solms. The latter

    emphasizes the fact that behind the positive (or

    productive'

    )

    manifestations of the organic lesions,

    there are underlying wishes, in consonance with

    the Freudian model of the mind. It is therefore clear

    that while DeLuca will put the accent

    on

    the deficit,

    the psychoanalyst will also emphasize the produc

    tive aspect of the symptom and its meaning.

    It might perhaps be useful to dwell for a while

    on this difference in the general line of thinking, which

    could be significant for the neurosciences also. As we

    know, Freud constructed a hypothetical model

    of

    a

    mental apparatus. Setting aside for the time being

    the verisimilitude of his construction, what is essential

    is to note the implicit general concept: in a complex

    system the global level of functioning

    of

    the system

    cannot legitimately be explained by reference to the

    atomic elements only. A deficit (in these cases due

    to an organic lesion) must be interpreted also as a

    function of the overall response of the system. This is

    true at the physical level as well as at the level of

    mental life. If, for example, we consider the (some-

  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    3/6

    Commentary on Confabulation

    times astonishing) cases

    of

    extensive malformations

    of one hemisphere requiring early radical hemi

    spherectomy (I recall a case with follow-up of left

    hemispherectomy in a 2-year-old child), we can see

    how the right hemisphere almost completely takes

    over all the functions of the other hemisphere, privi

    leging those higher functions that are essential from

    the adaptive point

    of

    view.

    Mental life operates no differently (and it could

    not be otherwise). This justifies considering the gap

    filling produced by the lesions in question as a function

    of

    the mind (as a system), and not necessarily or only

    as a response to embarrassment or feelings

    of

    inade

    quacy. Gazzaniga s observations (1998, quoted by De

    Luca) can be viewed from the same angle: the point

    is not so much in deciding whether this is confabula

    tion from unawareness or not, but rather that in split

    brain patients the left hemisphere contains a mecha

    nism (the Interpreter) that in any case tries to interpret

    information in a plausible manner, even

    if

    it is not

    correct. What I would say,

    if

    Gazzaniga is right, is

    that this is a function

    of

    the system as a whole. Mental

    life at the level

    of

    dreams (secondary elaboration),

    the narrative rewriting

    of one s own history, regularly

    works in the same way.

    Solms insists on the fact that mature cognitive

    functions (like the function that DeLuca described as

    strategical retrieval

    -which

    we would classify as an

    executive ego function) are built upon the founda

    tions

    of

    more primitive mental functions. This leads

    him to observe, rightly, that the symptomatology of

    his patients is in consonance with the fundamental

    principles of the Freudian topographical model of

    the mind.

    I would like to recall a Freudian concept that has

    been somewhat forgotten (Canestri, 1989) and that

    could prove useful in this context. The concept

    emerges for the first time in Freud s analysis of the

    Schreber case but reappears in other texts by Freud.

    This is not the occasion for a detailed study of its uses

    and applications, but I would only like to mention that

    the concept in

    question-reconciliation Versoh-

    nung was subsequently transformed by Melanie

    Klein into reparation thus modifying its original

    meaning. What did Freud mean by reconciliation?

    The Schreber case dealt with the fact that the patient

    could reconcile himself with his homosexual fan

    tasy because he was not able to eliminate it. Subse

    quently the concept broadened to include the

    reconciliation of the three mental agencies (ego,

    id, and superego) in Freud s structural model. In con

    clusion, through the deformations of the ego and the

    5

    use

    of

    different defense mechanisms, the entire system

    seeks states

    of

    equilibrium (which

    mayor

    may not be

    pathological) and this brings into consideration all the

    elements

    of

    the system.

    In my opinion, the general outline

    of

    Luria s

    work (1973) in relation to confabulation is similar to

    the one I have attempted to describe here. In fact,

    whether he was analyzing attention disorders or mem

    ory disorders (in patients with ventromesial frontal le

    sions), Luria constantly emphasized that the classical

    basic

    concepts of neuropsychology needed to be

    reexamined. Thus, from the concept of function we

    pass to the notion

    of

    whole functional systems,

    from single abilities to systemic organization, from

    the cerebral zones to the articulation and hierarchical

    organization of complex functional systems, from

    the symptom to the collapse of the system in its en

    tirety. In the same way, Luria s conceptualizing of the

    structures within the ventromesial frontal region of the

    brain as being an executive system with the task

    of

    organizing the available subroutines at lower hierar

    chical levels, are congruent with some central aspects

    of

    Freudian metapsychology. This has already been

    effectively pointed out by Solms when he quotes Lu

    ria, but I would like to return to some particular as

    pects, especially those concerning the function of

    attention.

    Freeman s (1992) paper Psychiatric Perspec

    tives on Freud s Metapsychology, is pertinent to our

    topic. Even though DeLuca expressly leaves aside

    confabulatory psychopathology of psychiatric origin,

    many of Freeman s examples, including those of

    schizophrenia and chronic brain syndrome, demon

    strate the value in studying confabulation in a broad

    rather than a narrow sense, as Solms also recommends.

    In these disorders Freeman identifies a failure

    of

    selec

    tive attention (described by many authors, Luria in

    particular) that, from a psychological point

    of

    view,

    would result in the essential feature:

    In the chronic brain syndrome reality has largely lost

    its value

    The loss

    of

    reality has not occurred be

    cause it had become too frightening (Rosenfeld,

    1952), too exciting (Katan, 1979), hated (Bion, 1959),

    as is postulated in the case of schizophrenias. The

    clinical phenomena suggest other causes for the break

    with reality-namely the disorder

    of

    selective atten

    t ion and the amnesic phenomena. Attention can no

    longer be purposely directed to thoughts and percepts

    although they have achieved mental registration [po

    498].

  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    4/6

    6

    I will later return to the problem of the (associated)

    role that certain defense mechanisms-denial or dis

    avowal Verleunung -----ean also play in these pathol

    ogies.

    What is specifically interesting in this case is that

    Freeman (and also Solms) resorts to the Freudian the

    ory of attention, another metapsychological concept

    not always taken sufficiently into account. Freeman s

    synopsis of the Freudian theory of attention highlights

    the fact

    that

    selective attention is a function of the

    ego system Pcpt-Cs which acts as a sense organ (p.

    499). This implies that unconscious mental processes

    (wishes) have to make contact with preconscious ver

    bal representations to find conscious expression, and

    this, in turn, requires that the Pcpt.-Cs. system should

    have an adequate cathexis (activation). What hap

    pens with pathology of the vetromesial frontal region

    of

    the brain? Luria and others emphasize that the

    voluntary or selective attention-arousal systems of

    the brain are defective, adding that the frontal lesion

    disturbs only the higher cortical forms of such activa

    tion, formed with the help of language, while the ele

    mentary forms not only remain intact

    ut

    m y actually

    be increased. Returning to the Freudian hypothesis;

    on the one hand, we are brought back to what Solms

    clearly explained when he writes that:

    ] defining property of the deficit in question must

    be that it deprives the mental apparatus of something

    that is fundamental to the whole mode

    of

    functioning

    of

    the system

    Pcs.-Cs.-and

    therefore to the second

    ary process (and the reality principle) in general. This

    implies that structures within the ventromesial frontal

    region

    of

    the brain subserve functions that are prereq

    uisite for the secondary process mode of functioning

    that characterizes the system Pcs.-Cs.

    On the other hand, there also appears to be a

    deficit in the filtering of information and in its reg

    ulation, as Luria describes (i.e., an increase in elemen

    tary forms of arousal). In Freudian language, this is

    attributed to absence

    of

    the

    countercathectic barrier

    that protects the operations linked to voluntary atten

    tion from undesirable interference (or restated in terms

    of primary and secondary processes: protects thought

    from continuous invasion by the procedural forms of

    the primary process).

    In the same way as the functioning of the mental

    apparatus presupposes the constant and simultaneous

    presence of primitive functions, it also implies an

    adequate control and filtering

    of

    these functions in the

    development

    of

    higher cognitive capacities.

    Jorge Canestri

    In Freeman s words:

    s

    the Pes contents are hypercathected, a counterca

    thectic barrier arises simultaneously to insulate di

    rected thinking and perceiving from extraneous and

    internal stimuli

    In terms of Freud s theory (1900),

    patients suffering from chronic brain syndrome can

    not voluntarily recall preconscious ideas and percepts

    because the system Pcpt-Cs is deprived of that

    (bound) cathexis which would enable it to bring these

    representations to consciousness. The accompanying

    distractibility occurs because of the cathectic deple

    tion of the barriers which protect consciousness from

    excessive stimuli

    the loss of functions served by

    the system Pcpt-Cs leads to the appearance of an ele

    mentary form of cognition (primary process)

    po

    499].

    This is consistent with Luria s observations

    (quoted by Solms) concerning a sharp decrease in

    cortical tone and with the statements of Solms (and

    psychoanalysis in general)

    on

    the importance of con

    sidering not only the deficit but alsothe productive

    aspects of pathology. If what I briefly mentioned

    above, regarding the brain and the mental apparatus

    as a complex system, is plausible, then these aspects

    simultaneously reveal the

    work

    of the primary process

    in terms of wishful states; but they also reveal the

    striving toward a reconciliation with the new con

    dition of the entire mental apparatus.

    One

    of

    my patients with severe cyclical pathol

    ogy, at a certain point in the analysis, had a partial

    occlusion of the carotid. The excessive deficits that

    ensued led to the suspicion of a second pathology.

    Radiological investigations revealed diffuse atrophy

    of the cortex, the extent of which amazed everybody

    as it was difficult to imagine how the patient could

    have led quite a normal life (at least from the neu

    rological point of view) considering the extent of the

    cortical atrophy. A surgical intervention to clear the

    carotid (endartorectomy) brought the situation back to

    the stato quo ante, but the following months of analy

    sis provided a good opportunity to observe a complex

    and articulated assemblage of productive symptoms,

    deficits, and compensatory efforts by the patient

    (pseudo-explanations, confabulations, rationaliza

    tions, etc.) to reconcile himself to his state. The psy

    chiatric pathology did not disappear, rather i t was

    enriched by the intersection of organic symptoms and

    psychiatric symptoms. The definition of denial by Pri

    gatano and Klonoff (1998, quoted by DeLuca) could

    be applied to some manifestations of this point: de

    nial after brain injury reflects the individual s attempt

  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    5/6

    Commentary on Confabulation

    to use previous coping strategies to deal with impair

    ments that are only partially recognized. This defini

    tion coincides with the above hypothesis on the

    function

    of

    reconciliation. But how do we trace a

    clear dividing line between denial

    of

    illness and un

    awareness

    of

    illness?

    Although itmay be reasonable to try to differenti

    ate between anosognosia and functional denial

    of

    illness, as DeLuca does in the section

    of

    his paper

    entitled Confabulation and Awareness, to me it

    seems unsatisfactory to state (following the American

    Psychiatric Association s definition) that the differ

    ence must be sought in the fact that denial

    of

    illness

    presupposes merely altered self-awareness rather than

    actual unawareness. Here we must take account

    of

    the

    fact that denial (in the Freudian sense

    of

    disavowal,

    i.e., erleunung or erweifung is a very powerful

    defense mechanism, the effects

    of

    which can produce

    total unawareness (rather than mere altered aware

    ness). Denial involves a cognitive alteration that can

    be very serious, including substitution of one reality

    with another. Theo Dorpat (1983), in hypothesizing

    four phases

    of

    denial; (1) preconscious appraisal

    of

    danger or trauma, (2) painful affect, (3) cognitive ar

    rest, and (4) screen behavior, describes how cogni

    tive arrest concerning the painful object and the need

    to adapt to the dangerous or traumatic situation stimu

    lates the need to create a cover story or screen to hide,

    as it were, the gap caused by the preceding phase. The

    cognitive arrest is usually followed by some kind

    of

    screen behaviour the content

    of

    which is often the

    opposite from what has just been negated (p. 54).

    Moreover, this operation clearly shows how the

    needs of the primary process (realization of a desire

    through its opposite, screen behavior, etc.) are articu

    lated alongside those of the entire system ( need to

    adapt, neutralization

    of

    the trauma, consequent dis

    tortion

    of

    the perception

    of

    reality, misidentification,

    misrecognition); in other words, alongside distortions

    of

    the ego and alteration

    of

    its functions.

    I think it will seem obvious to DeLuca that all

    these observations invite a nuancing

    of

    the differ

    ences, while his approach is to emphasize

    them-to

    consider only neurogenic confabulation and to set

    aside psychiatric pathology, to differentiate un

    awareness from denial

    of

    illness, to discriminate con

    fabulation in a narrow sense from that in a broad sense.

    This different orientation partly reflects a disparity be

    tween the disciplines. It is difficult, and would be con

    tradictory from the analyst s point

    of

    view, not to take

    into account the premobid personality features, the

    productive aspects

    of

    the illness, and the fact that they

    7

    express unconscious tendencies. From the DeLuca s

    viewpoint, on the other hand, the search for clarity in

    definitions and for precision in delimiting the field is

    paramount. I do not think, however, that these two

    orientations need necessarily be incompatible. From

    the neurologist s viewpoint, the proposal DeLuca il

    lustrates in Figure 1 could be useful, provided that

    DeLuca also accepts that although it is useful in neuro

    logical practice, it probably is not really accurate when

    one deals with confabulatory phenomena as a whole.

    Moreover, a radical separation between all these phe

    nomena can risk impoverishing our understanding of

    the overall functioning

    of

    the mental apparatus as well

    as

    of

    the brain itself.

    In his section reviewing the Neurobehavioral

    Models

    of

    Confabulation, DeLuca adheres to the

    third model, hypothesizing that the expression of con

    fabulation requires

    both

    amnesia and executive dys

    function. Solms on the other hand thinks that the

    memory disorder is an executive disorder, that a

    spe

    cial type of executive disorder necessarily pro

    duces a confabulatory amnesia, thus associating

    himself with the second model. From this point of

    view, Ptak and Schnider s (1999) observations

    (quoted by DeLuca in support

    of

    the third model) seem

    to lead in the direction proposed by Solms; in fact

    Ptak and Schnider attribute a core role to the orbito

    frontal cortex in the maintenance

    of

    temporal order in

    memory, and it is mainly this (temporal order) that is

    altered in memory confabulation, rather than memory

    content

    itself. We could therefore hypothesize that the

    maintenance

    of

    temporal order is one

    of

    the executive

    functions of the frontal cortex and that the amnesia,

    as Solms says, is only the inevitable consequence.

    However, some contradictory cases could be found;

    for example, the case reported by Wheatly and

    McGrath (1997, quoted by DeLuca)

    of

    confabulation

    in

    a

    non-ACoA patient

    with executive dysfunction and

    impaired memory secondary to a diencephalic lesion,

    and others. Such cases indicate that other nearby struc

    tures, connected to the ventromesial portion of the

    frontal lobes, are compromised (Damasio, Graff-Red

    ford, Eslinger, Damasio, and Kassel, 1985). In my

    opinion the argument remains open to further study

    and is

    of

    considerable interest from the neuroscientific

    and psychoanalytic point

    of

    view.

    I have already mentioned how psychoanalysis

    can have heuristic value for the neurosciences. Psy

    choanalysis, of necessity, works with a wider vision

    of

    subjective phenomena, with a perspective that must

    continuously take into consideration the phenomena

    of meaning as well as the phenomena of deficit, and

    with a viewpoint that must confront the mental appara

    tus in its totality alongside each

    of

    its manifestations.

  • 7/25/2019 5 a Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation: Commentary by Jorge Canestri (Rome)

    6/6

    148

    Moreover, I do not believe it is useful, or episte

    mologically correct, from the neuroscientific point of

    view, to reject as nonscientific the descriptive data

    resulting from subjective experience. First, they are

    not in themselves less scientific by definition than ex

    perimental data. Many disciplines-psychoanalysis

    among

    them are

    based on

    the accurate pro

    grammed and intersubjectively controlled collection

    o

    empirical data

    and this does not exclude them from

    the field

    of

    empirical science. The neurosciences could

    receive useful information from psychoanalysis rela

    tive to the complexity

    of

    the phenomena to be studied,

    for the reason that it possesses an overarching model

    of

    the mental apparatus still lacking in neuroscience.

    Psychoanalysis in its turn could receive valuable help

    from the neurosciences in order to test the empirical

    and experimental probity

    of

    its hypothetical and some

    times speculative concepts, derived from a particular

    experience in the treatment

    of

    mental illness.

    From this point

    of

    view, DeLuca's work provides

    an excellent opportunity for reconsidering some basic

    concepts

    of

    Freudian metapsychology, such as the dif

    ference between bound and freely mobile energy, pri

    mary process and secondary process, and the entire

    Freudian concept

    of

    attention, and the like. But Solms

    has already commented on these aspects.

    References

    Canestri,

    J

    (1989), Restauro, Riparazione, Riconciliazione.

    In: Piccolo Hans Vol. 61. Milan: Media Press.

    Neill Graff-Radford

    Damasio, A. R., Graff-Radford, P. J., Eslinger, H., Damasio,

    H., Kassel, N (1985), Amnesia following basal fore

    brain lesions. Arch. Neurol. 42:263-271.

    Dorpat, T. L. (1983), The cognit ive arrest hypothesis of

    denial.

    n

    ternat. J Psycho-Anal. 64:47-57.

    Freeman, T. (1992), Psychiatric perspectives

    o n F re ud s

    metapsychology. nternat Rev. Psycho-Anal.

    19:497-502.

    Freud, S (1900), The Interpretation of Dreams. Standard

    Edition 4 5. London: Hogarth Press, 1953.

    (1911), Formulations on the two principles of men

    tal function.

    Standard Edition

    12:213-226. London: Ho

    garth Press, 1958.

    (1915), The unconscious. Standard Editon

    14: 159-204. London: Hogarth Press, 1957.

    Gazzaniga, M. S (1998), The Mind s Past. Berkeley: Uni

    versity of California Press.

    Luria, A R (1973), The Working Brain: n Introduction

    to

    Neuropsychology. Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin

    Books.

    Prigatano, G. P., Klonoff, P. S (1998), A clinician's

    rating scale for evaluating impaired self-awareness and

    denial of disability after brain damage. Clin. Neuropsy

    chol. 12:56-67.

    Ptak, R., Schnider, A (1999), Spontaneous confabulation

    after orbitofrontal damage: The role of temporal context

    confusion and self-monitoring.

    Neurocase. 5:243-250.

    Wheatly, J., McGrath, J (1997), Co-occurrence of execu

    tive impairment and amnestic syndrome following suba

    rachnoid haemorrhage: A case study. Cortex

    33:711-721.

    Jorge Canestri

    Via

    Sesto Rufo 23

    00136 Rome Italy

    e-mail: [email protected]@mclink.it

    A Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective on Confabulation

    Commentary by Neill Graff-Radford (Jacksonville, FL)

    Dr. John DeLuca has written a scholary review

    of

    the

    cognitive neuroscience perspective

    of

    confabulation,

    while Dr.

    Mark

    Solms has made a compelling case

    that many

    of

    the features characterizing confabulation

    are found in Freud's model

    of

    the unconscious mind.

    With these articles in mind, and from a pragmatic

    point

    of

    view, it is important to ask the following ques

    tions about confabulations: What are they? What are

    Professor Graff-Radford is Chair, Department

    of

    Neurology, Mayo

    Clinic, Jacksonville, Florida.

    the known causes? Do we know the anatomy

    of

    the

    lesion(s) causing them? Why do they occur? What are

    the associated features?

    What

    Are They?

    Dr. DeLuca has used the Moscovitch and Melo (1997)

    definition

    of

    statements or actions that involve unin

    tentional but obvious distortions. This is an all-inclu

    sive definition and fits with the model in his Figure

    1