flickers of freedom and moral luck 1. introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/flickers.pdfall roads...

21
1 Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck * 1. Introduction The thought that too much moral luck is unacceptable has led some to shrink the locus of our moral responsibility. For example, following the Kantian tradition of the “good will” as the only thing that has moral worth, some have suggested that all that we can be responsible for is mental acts like decisions, or for the character traits issuing in those decisions, given that these are less dependent on external influences and thus less vulnerable to certain forms of luck than other things (see, e.g., Richards 1986, Thomson 1989, Graham 2014, and Rivera-López 2016). The literature on the free will problem contains a similar movement in support of shrinking the locus of our responsibility. On these views, what we are truly or ultimately responsible for is, not what we decide to do per se, but something more fine-grained and arguably even more immune to luck than our decisions: what we decide on our own to do. In what follows, I’ll refer to this view as the Triple O view. The Triple O view comes up in a defense of the classical model of freedom (which understands freedom in terms of alternative possibilities) from Frankfurt’s famous objection (Frankfurt 1969), as a version of the so-called “flickers of freedom” reply to that objection (see, e.g., van Inwagen 1983, Naylor 1984, O’Connor 2000, Speak 2002, Timpe 2006, Robinson 2012, and Capes and Swenson 2017). 1 Although the connection with the moral * Thanks to Justin Capes, Andrew Khoury, Michael McKenna, Michael Robinson, and Philip Swenson for helpful comments and discussion. 1 The term “flickers of freedom” is from Fischer 1994: 137-47, and it refers to those alternative possibilities that allegedly remain open to agents in Frankfurt-style cases.

Upload: others

Post on 10-Aug-2020

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

1

FlickersofFreedomandMoralLuck*

1.Introduction

Thethoughtthattoomuchmoralluckisunacceptablehasledsometoshrinkthelocusofour

moralresponsibility.Forexample,followingtheKantiantraditionofthe“goodwill”astheonly

thingthathasmoralworth,somehavesuggestedthatallthatwecanberesponsibleforis

mentalactslikedecisions,orforthecharactertraitsissuinginthosedecisions,giventhatthese

arelessdependentonexternalinfluencesandthuslessvulnerabletocertainformsofluckthan

otherthings(see,e.g.,Richards1986,Thomson1989,Graham2014,andRivera-López2016).

Theliteratureonthefreewillproblemcontainsasimilarmovementinsupportofshrinkingthe

locusofourresponsibility.Ontheseviews,whatwearetrulyorultimatelyresponsibleforis,

notwhatwedecidetodoperse,butsomethingmorefine-grainedandarguablyevenmore

immunetoluckthanourdecisions:whatwedecideonourowntodo.Inwhatfollows,I’llrefer

tothisviewastheTripleOview.TheTripleOviewcomesupinadefenseoftheclassicalmodel

offreedom(whichunderstandsfreedomintermsofalternativepossibilities)fromFrankfurt’s

famousobjection(Frankfurt1969),asaversionoftheso-called“flickersoffreedom”replyto

thatobjection(see,e.g.,vanInwagen1983,Naylor1984,O’Connor2000,Speak2002,Timpe

2006,Robinson2012,andCapesandSwenson2017).1Althoughtheconnectionwiththemoral

*ThankstoJustinCapes,AndrewKhoury,MichaelMcKenna,MichaelRobinson,andPhilipSwensonforhelpfulcommentsanddiscussion.1Theterm“flickersoffreedom”isfromFischer1994:137-47,anditreferstothosealternativepossibilitiesthatallegedlyremainopentoagentsinFrankfurt-stylecases.

Page 2: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

2

luckproblemissomewhathiddeninthesedebates,thereisclearlyaconnection,andoneworth

exploringinmoredetail.

Thegoalofthispaperistoexaminethisissue,bylookingataseriesofinterrelated

questions.Firstofall,whatmightbemeantbythecentralclaimoftheTripleOview:theclaim

thattheultimatelocusofourresponsibilityismakingdecisions“onourown”?Also,what

motivationcouldtherebeforthisview,andhowplausibleisit,attheendoftheday?In

particular,howplausibleisitasanapplicationoftheideathatourmoralresponsibility

shouldn’tbetoovulnerabletoluck?

2.TheTripleOView

Let’sstartwithabriefoverviewofhowtheTripleOviewcameintoexistence.vanInwagenfirst

suggestedaviewofthiskindinresponsetoFrankfurt’sargumentagainsttheclassicalmodelof

freedom(theconceptionthatunderstandsfreedomintermsofalternativepossibilities).

Frankfurt’sargumentappealedtospecificcounterexamplestothatconception—examplesthat

sincethenhavebeencalled“Frankfurt-style”cases.AFrankfurt-stylecaseisascenariowhere

anagentseemstomakeadecisionfreely,completelyonhisownandonthebasisofhisown

reasons,butitisadecisionthathecouldn’thaveavoidedmaking.Thereasontheagent

couldn’thaveavoidedmakingthedecision,thestandardstorygoes,isthataneuroscientist

whohadbeenmonitoringtheagent’sbrainwouldhaveensuredthathemadethesame

decision(bymanipulatinghisbrainintherequiredway)ifhehadn’tmadeitonhisown.

Frankfurtnotedthatscenariosofthiskindseemtounderminetheclassicalmodeloffreedom

Page 3: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

3

becausetheysuggestthatthekindoffreedomrelevanttoresponsibilitydoesn’trequirehaving

alternativepossibilities.

Inturn,vanInwagen(1983)respondedtoFrankfurtindefenseoftheclassicalmodel.

Hisresponseiscomplex,butpartoftheresponseappealedtotheideathatincertaincases

whereitmighthaveseemed,atfirst,thatagentsareresponsibleforunavoidablebehaviorsor

statesofaffairs,thoseagentsarenotactuallyresponsibleforthosebehaviorsorstatesof

affairs(sincetheywereunavoidable);instead,theyareresponsibleforhavingdonethemor

broughtthemaboutontheirown(wherethisissomethingthattheycouldhaveavoided).

AccordingtovanInwagen,onewaytomotivatethistypeofdistinctionisbyreflecting

onexamplesofthefollowingkind:

AllroadsleadtoRome:Ryderisridinganout-of-controlhorse,Dobbin,whenhegetsto

aforkinthepath.RydercannotstopDobbinbuthecanchoosewhichdirectionhewill

gobyusingthebridle.AlthoughheissurethatoneofthepathsleadstoRome,heis

unsureabouttheotherpaths.RyderhatesRomans,andpredictsthatsomeRomanswill

gethurtbythepassageofthehorse,sohemakesDobbingointhedirectionofthepath

heknowsleadstoRome,andsomeRomansgethurt,aspredicted.Asitturnsout,

however,allpathsledtoRome.(vanInwagen1983:176-7;thelabelismine)

AsvanInwagenpointsout,RyderseemsnottoberesponsibleforDobbin’spassingthrough

RomeorfortheRomansgettinghurt.ThesearebothoutcomesthatRydercouldn’thave

avoided.WhatRyderisclearlyresponsibleforisthehorse’stakingaparticularrouteorforthe

Page 4: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

4

Romansgettinghurtasaresultofthehorsetakingthatparticularroute.Butthesearemore

fine-grainedoutcomesthathecouldhaveavoided.Sothisexamplesuggeststhat,atleastin

somecaseswhereagentscouldhaveavoidedonlythemorefine-grainedoutcome,whatthey

areinfactresponsibleforisthemorefine-grainedoutcome(theonethattheycouldhave

avoided),andnotthemorecoarse-grainedoutcome(theonethattheycouldn’thaveavoided).

vanInwagenthensuggeststhatthisgeneralizestootherkindsofcases.Forexample,

thesamegoes,hesuggests,foracaselikethis:

GunnarandRidley:GunnardecidesonhisowntoshootRidley,butifhehadn’tdecided

thatonhisown,someexternalforcewouldhaveforcedhimtoshootRidley,andsohe

wouldhaveendedupshootinghimanyway.(vanInwagen1983:181;thelabelismine)

vanInwagensuggeststhatasimilaranalysisshouldbeofferedofthiscase:whatGunnaris

clearlyresponsibleforis,notthefactthatheshotRidley,whichissomethingthathecouldn’t

haveavoided,butthefactthatheshotRidleyonhisown,orwithouthavingbeencausedtodo

sobyanexternalforceoutsidehiscontrol(whichissomethingthathecouldhaveavoided).

AftervanInwagen,severalothershavemadesuggestionsalongsimilarlines.In

particular,Naylor(1984)offeredasimilaranalysisofthefollowingcase:

Honestchild:Achilddecidestotellthetruthonhisown,buthisparentswouldhave

forcedhimtotellthetruthifhehadchosentolie.(Naylor1984:251;thelabelismine)

Page 5: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

5

Naylorsuggestedthat,whereasitisobviousthatthechilddeservesmoralcreditfortellingthe

truthonhisown,itismuchlessobviousthatinthosecircumstanceshedeservesmoralcredit

fortellingthetruthsimpliciter.Inparticular,Naylornotedthatthechildcanberesponsiblefor

themannerinwhichhetoldthetruth(fordoingit“willingly”,or“bychoice”,or“justbecause

hewantedto”)withouttherebybeingresponsiblefortellingthetruth,whichhecouldn’thave

avoided.

Inturn,Robinson(2012)givesasimilaranalysisofthefollowingcase:

Box:Anevildemoncreatesaworldinwhichallthatexistsisalargeboxcontaininga

singlehumanbeing,Jack.ItisphysicallyimpossibleforJacktoleavethebox.However,

Jackneverattemptstoleavetheboxandspendshiswholelifehappilyinsidethebox.

(Robinson2012:181)

RobinsonsuggeststhatJackisnotresponsibleforstayinginthebox;whatheisresponsiblefor

isdecidingonhisowntostayinthebox,nottryingtoleavethebox,ortheparticularwayin

whichhestaysinsidethebox.

AndCapesandSwenson(2017:976)offerasimilaranalysisofacasediscussedin

FischerandRavizza(1998:125):

Sharks:Johnseesachilddrowningintheseaanddecidesnottojumpintosavehim.

Thechilddrowns.UnbeknownsttoJohn,somehungrysharkswouldhaveattackedhim

andpreventedhimfromsavingthechildifhehadtried.

Page 6: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

6

CapesandSwensonsuggestthat,althoughJohnisnotresponsiblefornotsavingthechildin

thiscase,heisresponsibleforfailingonhisowntosavethechild—thatistosay,withouthaving

beenforcedtodosobythesharks.

Thecommonideabehindalloftheseresponsesseemstobethethoughtthat,onceone

distinguisheshavingdonesomething(amorecoarse-grainedbehaviororfact)fromhaving

doneitonourown(amorefine-grainedbehaviororfact),itbecomesmuchlessclearthat

agentscanberesponsibleforinevitablebehaviors.Onthatbasis,then,wecanbuildadefense

oftheclassicalmodeloffreedomfromFrankfurt’sattackbyarguingthatFrankfurthasn’t

successfullyshownthatwecanactfreelywhilelackingalternativepossibilities.Whatis

sufficientlyclearaboutFrankfurt-stylecases,theargumentgoes,isthattheagentsinthose

casesareresponsibleforhavingmadethedecisionontheirown,orwithoutthehelpofthe

intervener(whichissomethingthattheycouldhaveavoided).Itismuchlessclear,however,

thattheyareresponsibleforhavingmadethedecisionsimpliciter.Thus,itismuchlessclear

thattheyareresponsibleforanyunavoidablebehaviors.

Actually,therearedifferentwaysofcashingthisideaoutmoreprecisely,andthus

differentversionsorformulationsoftheTripleOview.Theseareallwaysofexpressingthe

thoughtthatthe“ultimatelocus”ofourresponsibility,atleastincasesofthiskind,ismaking

decisionsonourown,notmakingdecisionssimpliciter.Inthefirstplace,theoriginaland

simplestversionoftheview,suggestedbybothvanInwagenandNaylor,isthatanagentina

Frankfurt-stylecaseisonlyresponsibleformakingthedecisiononhisown,andnotatallfor

makingthedecision,sincehecouldn’thaveavoidedmakingit.TheresponsetoFrankfurt’s

Page 7: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

7

argumentofferedbythisviewissimplythatFrankfurtiswronginthinkingthatanagentina

Frankfurt-stylecaseisresponsibleforhisunavoidablebehavior;whatheisresponsibleforisa

morefine-grainedstateofaffairsorfactthathecouldhaveavoided:havingmadethedecision

onhisown.

Inturn,asecondandmorerecentversionofthisview,onesuggestedbyCapesand

Swenson(2017),agreeswiththesejudgments,butatthesametimedrawsonadistinctionthat

isfamiliarintheliteratureonmoralluck:thedistinctionbetweenthescopeandthedegreeof

one’sresponsibility(see,e.g.,Zimmerman2002).Accordingtothisview,eventhoughtheagent

inaFrankfurt-stylecaseis,again,notresponsibleformakingthedecisionthathemade,forit

wasinevitable,thisiscompatiblewithclaimingthatheisjustasblameworthyashewouldhave

beenintheabsenceoftheintervener.Theunderlyingthoughtisthatluckcanaffectwhatyou

areresponsibleforwithoutaffectingthedegreeofyourresponsibility,whichwouldremainthe

sametotheextentthatyoumadethedecisiononyourown.Thisviewhasthepotential

advantagethatitallowsaproponentoftheTripleOviewtocapturemoreofFrankfurt’s

originalintuitionsaboutFrankfurt-stylecases,whichmanypeoplehavefoundconvincing.Forit

allowsustosaythatthereisasenseinwhichagentsinFrankfurt-stylecasesarejustas

blameworthyasiftheyhadbeeninordinarycircumstances,althoughtheyareresponsiblefor

fewerthings.

Finally,athirdandinsomewaysimportantlydifferentversionoftheTripleOview,

whichisformulatedanddefendedinRobinson(2012,2014,andForthcoming),istheviewthat

anagentinaFrankfurt-stylecaseisinfactresponsiblebothformakingthedecisionandfor

makingitonhisown,butheisonlybasicallyresponsibleformakingitonhisown,andonly

Page 8: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

8

derivativelyresponsibleformakingthedecision.AsRobinsonnotes,themostplausible

interpretationoftheprincipleofalternativepossibilities(theprincipleaccordingtowhich

responsibilityrequiresalternativepossibilitiesofaction)isonethattakesittobeaprinciple

aboutbasicresponsibilityonly.Otherwise,forexample,drunkdriverswouldbeoffthehookfor

causinganaccidentsimplyonthegroundsthattheycouldn’thaveavoidedcausingitatthe

timeoftheaccident,whentheywerealreadydrunk.Byrestrictingtheprincipleofalternative

possibilitiestobasicresponsibility,weavoidthisunacceptableresult(for,evenifdrunkdrivers

couldn’thavedoneotherwiseatthetimeoftheaccident,theycanstillbederivatively

responsiblefortheharmtheycausedbecauseoftheirearlierdecisiontodrinkanddrive,ifthey

couldhaveavoidedmakingthatdecision).Giventhis,Robinsonsuggests,ifwhatanagentina

Frankfurt-stylecaseisbasicallyresponsibleforisonlyhavingmadethedecisiononhisown,it

followsthatFrankfurt-stylecasesdon’tunderminetheprincipleofalternativepossibilitiesthus

understood(sincethoseagentscouldhaveavoidedmakingthedecisionontheirown).Notice

thatthisviewhastheaddedpotentialadvantagethatitallowsproponentsoftheTripleOview

tocaptureevenmoreofFrankfurt’soriginalintuitionsaboutFrankfurt-stylecases,ascompared

totheversionssuggestedbyvanInwagenandNaylor,andbyCapesandSwenson.Foritallows

themtoagreewithFrankfurtconcerningtheagents’responsibilityfortheirdecisions;the

disagreementonlyconcernsthelocusoftheirbasicresponsibility.

ThecentraltenetoftheTripleOview,then,istheclaimthat,atleastinthesekindsof

cases,theultimatelocusofourresponsibilityisnotmakingdecisionsbutmakingthemonour

own.Aswehaveseen,thiscanbeinterpretedeitherastheclaimthat(atleastinthesekindsof

cases)makingdecisionsonourownistheonlythingthatwecanberesponsiblefor,orasthe

Page 9: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

9

claimthatthisiswhatfixesthedegreeofourresponsibility,orastheclaimthatthisiswhatwe

arebasicallyresponsiblefor.Ourfocus,then,isafamilyofviewsratherthanasingleview.

Notethatalloftheauthorsthatwehavereviewedarespecificallyconcernedwith

responsibilityinscenarioswithinevitableoutcomes(Frankfurt-stylecasesbeingjustonetypeof

exampleofthatkind).Onenaturalquestionthatarises,then,iswhetherthoseauthorswould

wanttoextendtheirclaimstootherkindsofscenarios.Thatistosay,arewesupposedto

concludefromtheiranalysesthatitisingeneralthecasethatallthatwecanbetruly

responsibleforismakingdecisionsonourown,andnotmakingdecisions?Orthatthisiswhat

fixesthedegreeofourresponsibility?Orthatthisiswhatwearebasicallyresponsiblefor?Of

course,iftheseclaimsholdgenerally,thepositiononFrankfurt-stylecasesjustfollowsasa

specialcase.Asaresult,ifthegeneralclaimweresufficientlywellmotivated,thiscouldhelp

reinforcetheplausibilityofthisstyleofresponsetoFrankfurt’sargument.

Now,Iamnotclaimingthatalloftheseauthorswouldnecessarilybetemptedto

embracethemoregeneralclaims.2But,assuggestedabove,itisinterestingtonotethatthe

generalclaimcanatleastbemotivatedbymoralluckconsiderations.3Frankfurt-stylecases

seemtosuggestthatwecansometimesbemoreincontrolofwhetherwewillmakeadecision

onourownthanoverwhetherwewillmakethatdecision.So,bylimitingtheultimatelocusof

ourresponsibilitytowhatwedecideonourowntodo,astheTripleOviewdoes,wecan

2Infact,CapesandSwenson(personalcommunication)rejectthegeneralizationofatleastsomeoftheirviewstoothercases.3ThemoralluckconsiderationsIhaveinmindarediscussedinRobinson2012:187,CapesandSwenson2017:974-5,andRobinsonForthcoming:n.16.

Page 10: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

10

protectourresponsibilityfromcertainformsofluckthatsomemayfindproblematic.Thisisthe

kindofmotivationfortheTripleOviewthatIaminterestedinexamininghere.

3.Responsibilityfordeciding“onourown”

Now,howexactlyshouldweunderstandtheproposalthattheultimatelocusofour

responsibilityisnotmakingdecisionsbutmakingdecisionsonourown?Whatarethe

conditionsforbeingresponsibleformakingadecisiononourown?

The“onourown”locutionmightmeandifferentthingsindifferentcases.4Butnote

that,onaverynaturalinterpretation,inthiscontextdoingsomethingonyourownhastodo

withyourdoingitasaresultofacertainsetofmotivationsorcausalinfluences.Whenyoudo

somethingonyourown,youracthasaparticularkindofcausalhistory:onethatcontainsyour

owndeliberationandreasons,andonethatdoesn’tcontainexternalforcesormanipulatorsof

acertainsort.Forexample,inNaylor’sexampleofthehonestchild,thechildtellsthetruth“on

hisown”inthesensethatheismotivatedbyhisownreasonstotellthetruth,andisnotforced

byhisparentstodoso.Thatistosay,hetellsthetruthonhisowninthesensethathistelling

thetruthhastherelevantkindofcausalhistory.Arguably,thesamegoesfortheother

exampleswehavereviewedandthatwerediscussedbytheproponentsoftheTripleOview:in

vanInwagen’sGunnarandRidleyexample,GunnardecidestoshootRidley“onhisown”inthe

sensethatheismotivatedbyhisownreasonstoshoothimandnotbyexternalcoerciveforces;

inRobinson’sBoxexample,Jackdecidestostayintheboxmotivatedbyhisownreasonstostay

4Forexample,insomecontextsitseemstomeansomethinglike“alone,orunaccompaniedbyothers”,aswhenwesayofashypersonthatwhatshelikesmostisspendingtimeonherown.

Page 11: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

11

andnotcausedtodosobyexternalphysicalforces;etc.Thisisinlinewithwhatmostofthe

advocatesoftheTripleOviewexplicitlysay.Forexample,CapesandSwensonidentifytheclaim

thattheagentmakesthedecisiononherownwith“anobservationabouttheetiologyof[the

agent’s]decision,viz.,thatitwasnottheresultofoutsidecoercionorforce”(Capesand

Swenson2017:978;seealsoCapes2014:433).AndRobinsonsaysthatwhatitmeanstosay

thatanagentdecidesonhisowntoAis“simplythathedecidestoAandthathedoesso

withoutbeingcausallyforcedorinterferedwith”(RobinsonForthcoming:n.31).

Arguably,then,theclaimthattheultimatelocusofourresponsibilityismakingdecisions

onourown(insteadofmakingdecisionssimpliciter)hastobeinterpretedastheclaimthat

whatweareultimatelyresponsibleforis(notourdecisionsbut)afactaboutthecausalhistory

ofourdecisions:thefactthatourdecisionswere(orwerenot)causedinacertainway.This

seemstobe,atleast,themostnaturalinterpretationofthesuggestionmadebyTripleOviews,

andthebestwayIseetomakesenseofit.5So,inwhatfollows,I’lladoptthisinterpretationand

examineitsprospectsofsuccess.(Ofcourse,ifI’mwrongandthisisnotwhatsomeofthese

5Naylorseemstobeexplicitlyembracingthisinterpretationwhenshesays:“Ifsomeoneismorallyresponsiblefordoingsomethingonhisown,thenevenifheisnotmorallyresponsiblefordoingwhathedid,hecanstillbemorallyresponsibleforthemannerinwhichhedidit.”(Naylor1983:257).Capesalsoseemstobeembracingthisinterpretationwhenheclaimsthatwhattheagentisresponsibleforisnotadecisionbutamorepreciseormorefine-grainedfact:thefactthathedoesitonhisown(Capes2014:433).Robinsonsayshewantstoremainneutralontheissueof“justwhatitmeanshereforanagenttodecideonhisowntoA”,butoneofthepossibleinterpretationshementionsistheinterpretationaccordingtowhichdecidingonone’sowntoAis“justawayofdecidingtoA”(RobinsonForthcoming:n.14).vanInwagenisaspecialcase,Ithink,inthatheembracesaformofcausalessentialismabouteventsthatentailsthatyourdecisionwouldhavebeenadifferenteventifithadbeencausedinadifferentway(vanInwagen1983:169).Onthisview,yourdecidingonyourowncouldjustbetheactualeventofyourdecision.(ThisviewisalsosuggestedinthefirstpartofRobinson2012.)Butmostpeoplefindcausalessentialismabouteventstobehighlyimplausible,andIagree.(Capesmakesthispointtooinhis2014:section3.)

Page 12: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

12

authorshaveinmind,thisshouldbetakenasaninvitationtosaymoreabouthowweshould

interpretthecentralclaimoftheTripleOviews.)

Let’sstartbyasking:Couldweberesponsibleforfactsaboutthecausalhistoryofour

decisions?And,ifso,how?

Thefirstthingtonoteisthatafactaboutthecausalhistoryofadecision(amentalact)

isnot,itself,anact(ofanykind).Itisnotsomethingthatwedo,butafactaboutsomethingthat

wedo:afactaboutwhyitisthatwedowhatwedo.Butaprettystandardassumptionof

theoriesofresponsibilityisthatwhatwearebasicallyresponsibleforis(ifanything)certainacts

ofours(perhapsincludingactsofomission);mostcommonly,thesearetakentobementalacts

suchasdecisions.Asaresult,thereisapotentiallyseriousproblemhere.Theproblemisthat

theTripleOviewwantstosituatetheultimatelocusofourresponsibilityinthingsthatarenot

acts(ofanykind),but“features”ofacts,orfactsconcerningthecausalhistoryofacts.And

thesearenottypicallyregardedasthekindsofthingsthatwecanbebasicallyresponsiblefor.

Asaresult,itishardtoseehowtheycanbetheultimatelocusofourresponsibility,asthe

TripleOviewsays.6

Toclarify,Iamnotdenyingthatwecanberesponsibleforthingsthataren’tacts.In

particular,Iamnotdenyingthatwecansometimesberesponsibleforfactsaboutthecausal

6Forarelatedobjection,seeStump1999:301-2.StumpsuggeststhattheTripleOviewcouldonlyworkifdoinganactonone’sownwereanact,andonethatisdifferentfromtheactthattheagentwouldhaveperformedotherwise(sheisskepticaloftheseassumptions).ForaresponsetoStump,seeCapes(2014).Therearesomeviewsaccordingtowhichwecanbebasicallyresponsibleforthingslikecharactertraitsormentalstatesthatarenotacts(see,e.g.,Adams1985,Smith2005,andGraham2014).Note,however,thatfactsaboutthecausalhistoryofourdecisionsareverydifferentfromthingsofthatkind.So,whatevermotivationtherecouldbeforacceptingcharactertraitsandthelikeasthingsthatwecanbebasicallyresponsibleforwouldn’tobviouslycarryovertocausal-historyfacts.

Page 13: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

13

historiesofouracts.Itcertainlyseemsthatwecanbe,inthesamewaywecanberesponsible

forothermoreordinaryeventshavingthecausalhistoriesthattheydo.Butthepointisthat

thesedon’ttendtobethingsthatwearebasicallyresponsiblefor;rather,ourresponsibilityin

thosecasesisinheritedfromotherthingsforwhichweareresponsible.

vanInwagen’s“AllroadsleadtoRome”caseisagoodillustrationofhowwecanbe

responsibleforafactaboutthecausalhistoryofanordinaryevent.Inthiscase,asvanInwagen

notes,RyderisnotresponsiblefortheeventoftheRomansbeinghurt.Butheisresponsiblefor

theRomanshavingbeenhurtasaresultofthehorsetakingacertainpath(theonlyonehe

recognizedasleadingtoRome).SoRyderisresponsibleforafactaboutthecausalhistoryof

theeventconsistingintheRomansbeinghurt.But,ofcourse,inthiscase,hisresponsibilityfor

thisfactisnotbasic,butinheritedfromtheearlierdecisiontoturnthehorseinthatdirection.

Sharksisasimilarcase:theagent,John,isnotresponsibleforfailingtosavethedrowningchild,

andheisresponsibleforthefactthatthesharkswerenotpartofthecausalhistoryofhis

failuretosavethechild.Butthisisbecauseheisresponsibleforhisdecisionnottoattempta

rescue,whichinturnresultedinthesharksnotpreventingtherescue.7

Similarly,therecouldbecaseswhereweareresponsibleforafactaboutthecausal

historyofourdecisions.But,inthosecasestoo,ourresponsibilitywouldhavetobederived

fromotherthingswedid(orfailedtodo)andforwhichwearebasicallyresponsible.For

example,athiefcouldberesponsibleforthefactthathisdesiretostealcausedhisdecisionto

7Inmyview,exampleslikevanInwagen’sGunnarandRidleycasearedifferent,inthatIthinkGunnarisresponsibleforRidley’sdeath,andnotjustforafactaboutthecausalhistoryofRidley’sdeath.ThebasicdifferenceisthatGunnarcausesRidley’sdeath;incontrast,theagentinSharksdoesn’tcausethechild’sdeath,andRyderdoesn’tcausetheharmtotheRomans.IdiscussthesignificanceofdifferencesofthiskindinSartorio2016,chapter2.

Page 14: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

14

steal,butthiscouldbebecausehefailedtoresistthat(resistible)desire.Inthatcase,Isubmit,

heisbasicallyresponsibleforhisfailuretoresistthedesiretosteal,andonlyderivativelyfor

thefactaboutthecausalhistoryofhisdecision.Asanillustration,imaginethatthethiefknows

thatheisgenerallyabletoresisttheurgetostealifhelooksatapassageonKantianphilosophy

fromamoralphilosophytextbook,andonthatparticularoccasionhedecidednottolookatthe

passage,whichresultedinhisstealingact.Clearly,whatheisbasicallyresponsibleforinthis

caseishisdecisionnottolookatthepassage.Healsoseemsresponsibleforthefactthathis

desiretostealwascausallyefficacious;however,hisresponsibilityforthisfactisinheritedfrom

hisresponsibilityforthedecisionnottolookatthepassage.

Ingeneral,then,itishardtoseehowwecouldbebasicallyresponsibleforfactsabout

thecausalhistoriesofourdecisions,sincethesearefactsthatwetendtoberesponsibleforina

derivativeway.ButthismakestroublefortheTripleOview.Forimaginethatwewantedtosay

thattheagentinaFrankfurt-stylecaseisnotresponsible,ornotbasicallyresponsible,for

havingmadethedecisionthathemade,butonlyforhavingmadeitonhisown.Howcouldthis

be,ifthisisafactaboutthecausalhistoryofhisdecision?Presumably,ifhewereresponsible

forthatfact,hisresponsibilitywouldhavetobeinherited,asintheexamplesabove,fromother

thingsforwhichheisbasicallyresponsible.Butthereisn’tanysuchthing;afterall,theseare

supposedtobecasesofbasicmoralresponsibility.(Recallthattheyhavetobe;otherwisethey

wouldhavenobearingontheprincipleofalternativepossibilities,sincethisprincipleis

restrictedtobasicresponsibilityonly.)

Atthispoint,theproponentoftheTripleOviewmightprotest:But,surely,theagentin

aFrankfurt-stylecaseisresponsibleformakingthedecisiononhisown!Thismuchseemsclear.

Page 15: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

15

So,giventhatmyreasoningabovesuggeststhatheisnot(giventhatthereisnothingfrom

whichthatresponsibilitycouldbederived),theremustbeaflawinthatreasoning.

Itis,indeed,temptingtothinkinthisway.But,asIgoontosuggestinthenextsection,

thiswayofthinkingreliesonaconfusion.Uncoveringthatconfusionwillallowustocomeup

withadiagnosisthatwillhelpusseemoreclearlybothwhytheTripleOviewfails,andalsowhy

itmayhaveseemedattractive.

4.Adiagnosis

Therootoftheconfusion,itseemstome,couldbethatinthesecasesofbasicresponsibilityit’s

easytoconflatewhatweareresponsibleforwithwhyweareresponsible—thatistosay,with

thegroundsofourresponsibility.Recallthat,onwhatseemstobethemostnatural

interpretationofthe“onourown”locution,beingresponsibleformakingadecisiononour

ownamountstobeingresponsibleforafactaboutthecausalhistoryofthedecision.Thecausal

historyofthedecisionmadebyagentsinFrankfurt-stylecasesisonethatincludestheirown

deliberationandtheirownreasons.So,inorderforagentsinFrankfurt-stylecasestobe

responsibleformakingthedecisionontheirown,theywouldhavetoberesponsibleforthe

factthattheirdecisionhadthatcausalhistory.But,dowereallythinkthatagentsinFrankfurt-

stylecasesareresponsibleforthisfact?Thatis,dowereallythinkthattheyareresponsiblefor

thefactthattheirownreasonsanddeliberationbroughtabouttheirdecision?

It’snotatallclearthatwedo.Whatmostpeoplewouldcertainlywanttosayisnotthis

but,instead,thattheagentisresponsibleforhisdecisionbecausehisownreasonsand

deliberationbroughtabouthisdecision.Thatistosay,thefactaboutthecausalhistoryofthe

Page 16: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

16

agent’sdecisionisnotsomethingthattheagentisresponsibleforbut,instead,somethingthat

groundshisresponsibilityforthedecision.IfanagentinaFrankfurt-stylecasemayhave

seemedresponsibleformakingthedecisiononhisown,then,perhapsthiswasjusttheresult

ofconflatingthegroundsofhisresponsibilitywithsomethingthatheisresponsiblefor.

Inacoupleofrecentpapers,Robinsonofferedanargumentthatisrelevantforour

purposeshere(seeRobinson2012andForthcoming).Thisisanargumentforthethirdversion

oftheTripleOviewdiscussedabove:theviewthat,althoughagentsinFrankfurt-stylecasesare

responsiblebothformakingthedecisionandformakingthedecisionontheirown,theyare

onlybasicallyresponsibleformakingthedecisionontheirown.Thatistosay,althoughtheyare

responsibleformakingthedecision,theirresponsibilityforthedecisionisderivedfromtheir

responsibilityformakingthedecisionontheirown,whichisthe“ultimatelocus”oftheir

responsibility.Robinsonnotesthat,ifthoseagentsareresponsibleforboththings,makingthe

decisionandmakingitontheirown,thenthesefactsmustbeeitherunrelatedoronemust

explaintheother(hedoesn’tconsiderthepossibilitythattheymaybothbeexplainedbythe

agent’sbeingresponsibleforathirdthing,probablybecauseit’sunclearwhatthatthirdthing

couldbe).AsRobinsonnotes,itseemsimplausibletosuggestthattheyareunrelated.Sothat

leavestwopossibilities:either(i)theagent’sresponsibilityforthedecisionexplainshis

responsibilityformakingthedecisiononhisown,orit’stheotherwayaround:(ii)theagent’s

responsibilityformakingthedecisiononhisownexplainshisresponsibilityforthedecision.

But,Robinsonargues,(ii)ismuchmoreplausiblethan(i).Fordecidingonourownseemstobe

morebasic,ormorewithinourcontrol,thandecidingsimpliciter.So,inthesamewaythatour

responsibilityforovertbodilyactionsisderivedfromourmorebasicresponsibilityforour

Page 17: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

17

antecedentdecisionsormentalactions(whicharemorewithinourcontrol),itseemsthatwe

wouldhavetoconcludethatourresponsibilityforourdecisions,too,isderivedfromourmore

basicresponsibilityformakingdecisionsonourown.(AccordingtoRobinson,thisgoesatleast

forFrankfurt-stylecases,ifnotmoregenerally,foranycasewhereweareresponsiblefora

decision.)

Asexplainedabove,IthinkthatRobinson’sinitialassumptionisnotquiteright:itisnot

thecasethatagentsinFrankfurt-stylecasesareresponsibleforboththings,makingadecision

andmakingitontheirown.Instead,theyareonlyresponsibleformakingthedecision.Still,we

canexplainawaytheappearancethatisarguablydrivingRobinson’sargumentinthefollowing

way.ItistrueofFrankfurt-stylecasesthatagentsmakethedecisionsthattheymakeontheir

own.Anditistruethat,insomesense,thisisa“morebasic”ormorefundamentalfactthan

theirresponsibilityforthosedecisions.Itisamorebasicormorefundamentalfactinthatit

groundstheirresponsibilityforthedecisions.Butitdoesn’tfollowfromthisthatitismorebasic

orfundamentalinthesensethattheagents’responsibilityfortheirdecisionsisderivedfrom

theirresponsibilityforthoseotherthings,whichiswhatRobinsonwantstosay.

Inotherwords,basicresponsibilityfactscan(ofcourse)begroundedinotherfacts.But

thoseotherfactsarenot,themselves,responsibilityfacts(otherwisetheywouldnotbebasic

responsibilityfactsbutderivativeresponsibilityfacts).Whatkindsoffactsarethey?Thisis

somewhatcontroversialbut,attheveryleast,itisclearthattheymustincludesomecausal

historyfacts(sincehowyoumakeadecision,orthecausalhistoryofyourdecision,isclearly

Page 18: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

18

relevanttowhetheryouareresponsibleforit).8So,inparticular,factsconcerningthecausal

historyofdecisionswillhaveanimportantroletoplayingroundingtheagent’sbasic

responsibilityforthosedecisions,withoutbeingfactsthattheagentisresponsiblefor.9

Ontheotherhand,notethatifonefollowsRobinsoninsayingthattheagent’s

responsibilityformakingthedecisionderivesfromher(basic)responsibilityformakingthe

decisiononherown,thenthequestionarises:Whatcouldpossiblygroundthatbasic

responsibilityfact?Weseemtobeleftwithoutananswertothisquestion.10Whichmakesme

thinkthatwehavegonetoofar:weshouldhavestoppedearlier,atthegroundsoftheagent’s

responsibilityforherdecision.Inotherwords,whatweshouldhavesaidis,again,thatalthough

theagentisresponsibleforherdecisionbecauseofthewayshemadethatdecision,thisisn’t

aninstanceofderivedresponsibility,butafactaboutthegroundsofbasicresponsibility.

8Onmyview(developedinSartorio2016),causalhistoryfacts(togetherwiththegroundsofthosecausalhistoryfactsthemselves)areactuallytheonlyfactsthatarerelevanttothetypeofcontrolthatisrelevanttoanagent’sresponsibility.9AtonepointRobinsonraisesthechallenge:“Ifapersonisnotmorallyresponsiblefordoingathingonherown,itisdifficulttoseehowshecouldbemorallyresponsiblefordoingitsimpliciter.”(Robinson2012:186-7).AsIhaveargued,Ithinkthatthechallengecanbeansweredbypointingoutthatshecanstillbemorallyresponsiblefordoingitsimpliciter,aslongasherdoingitonherowngroundsherresponsibilityfordoingitsimpliciter.10Swenson(personalcommunication)notesthatonepossibilitywouldbetosaythatthecausalhistoryfactitself(thefactthattheagentmadethedecisiononherown)groundsthebasicresponsibilityfact(thefactthattheagentisbasicallyresponsibleformakingthedecisiononherown).Accordingtothissuggestion,therearesomefactsconcerningthewayinwhichdecisionsaremade,whentheyaremadeintherightway,thataresuchthatsimplybyobtainingtheycangroundtheagent’sbasicresponsibilityforthoseveryfacts.Althoughthisisaninterestingsuggestion,Iremainunconvinced.For,again,althoughit’sveryplausibletosaythatthefactabouthowthedecisionwasmadegroundstheagent’sresponsibilityforthedecision,itseemsmuchlessplausibletosaythatthefactabouthowthedecisionwasmadegroundstheagent’sresponsibilityforthatveryfactabouthowthedecisionwasmade.

Page 19: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

19

5.Conclusions

Ihaveexaminedafamilyofviewsonresponsibilitythatwereoriginallyproposedinresponseto

Frankfurt’sargument,butthatcouldalsobemotivatedbygeneralconsiderationsofmoralluck.

Coulditbethat,astheseviewssuggest,theultimatelocusofourresponsibilityisnotmaking

decisionsbutmakingthemonourown?Ifso,thiswouldhelpprotectthesphereofour

responsibilityfromcertainformsofluckthatsomemayfindobjectionable(inadditionto

protectingtheclassicalmodeloffreedomfromFrankfurt’sobjection).Ihavearguedthatthose

viewsfailinthat,totheextentthatwecanmakesenseoftheconceptofbeingresponsiblefor

makingdecisionsonourown,itisnotsomethingthatcanconstitutethe“ultimatelocus”ofour

responsibility.

Still,Ihopetohavealsoshownthatthinkingabouttheseviewscanbeinstructiveinthat

itcanhelpshedsomelightonthestructurethatagoodtheoryofresponsibilitymusthave.One

thingthatcameupinourdiscussionistheimportanceofdrawingacleardistinctionbetween

twowaysinwhichresponsibilityfactscanbe“rootedin”otherfacts:oneiswhathappenswhen

ourresponsibilityisderivedfromotherthingsthatwearemorebasicallyresponsiblefor,and

anotheriswhathappenswhenourresponsibility(inparticular,ourbasicresponsibility)is

groundedinotherthings.Althoughthisshouldbearelativelyuncontroversialdistinction,itis

onethatcaneasilybeoverlookedinsomecontextsandthus,payingcloseattentiontoitcan

helpkeepourtheorizingaboutresponsibilityontherighttrack.11

11InSartorioMs.Iarguethatfocusingontheroleplayedbythenotionofgroundinourtheoriesofresponsibilitycanhelpusavoidotherimportantconfusionsconcerningtheconceptofresponsibility.

Page 20: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

20

References

Adams,R.1985.“Involuntarysins.”PhilosophicalReview94:3-31.

Capes,J.2014.“Theflickeroffreedom:AreplytoStump.”TheJournalofEthics18,4:427-35.

Capes,J.andP.Swenson.2017.“Frankfurtcases:thefine-grainedresponserevisited.”

PhilosophicalStudies174:967-81.

Fischer,J.1994.Themetaphysicsoffreewill:Anessayoncontrol.Cambridge:Blackwell

Publishers.

Fischer,J.andM.Ravizza.1998.Responsibilityandcontrol:Atheoryofmoralresponsibility.

NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Frankfurt,H.1969.“Alternatepossibilitiesandmoralresponsibility.”JournalofPhilosophy66,

23:829-39.

Graham,P.2014.“Asketchofatheoryofblameworthiness.”PhilosophyandPhenomenological

Research88,2:388-409.

Naylor,M.1984.“Frankfurtontheprincipleofalternatepossibilities.”PhilosophicalStudies46:

249-58.

O’Connor,T.2000.Personsandcauses:Themetaphysicsoffreewill.NewYork:Oxford

UniversityPress.

Richards,N.1986.“Luckanddesert.”Mind95:198-209.

Rivera-López,E.2016.“Howtorejectresultantmoralluckalone.”JournalofValueInquiry50:

415-23.

Robinson,M.2012.“ModifiedFrankfurt-typeexamplesandtheflickersoffreedom.”

PhilosophicalStudies157:177-94.

Page 21: Flickers of Freedom and Moral Luck 1. Introductionsartorio.arizona.edu/files/Flickers.pdfAll roads lead to Rome: Ryder is riding an out-of-control horse, Dobbin, when he gets to a

21

Robinson,M.2014.“Thelimitsoflimited-blockageFrankfurt-stylecases.”PhilosophicalStudies

169:429-46.

Robinson,M.Forthcoming.“Robustflickersoffreedom.”SocialPhilosophyandPolicy.

Sartorio,C.2016.Causationandfreewill.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Sartorio,C.Ms.“Thegroundsofourfreedom.”

Smith,A.2005.“Responsibilityforattitudes:activityandpassivityinmentallife.”Ethics115:

236-71.

Speak,D.2002.“Fanningtheflickersoffreedom.”AmericanPhilosophicalQuarterly39:91-105.

Stump,E.1999.“Alternativepossibilitiesandmoralresponsibility:Theflickeroffreedom.”The

JournalofEthics3:299-324.

Thomson,J.1989.“Moralityandbadluck.”Metaphilosophy20:203-21.

Timpe,K.2006.“AcritiqueofFrankfurt-libertarianism.”Philosophia34,2:189-202.

vanInwagen,P.1983.Anessayonfreewill.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.