pols 374 foundations of global politics people and justice lecture

54
POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

Post on 21-Dec-2015

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics

People and Justice Lecture

Page 2: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

2

People and Justice

• Is global justice possible?

• If it is, what would it involve?

• What would be required to achieve it?

Page 3: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

3

People and Justice

Defining justice• When thinking about how to define justice,

there are three basic approaches used by scholars, which we can classify as:

(1) Distributive justice

(2) Justice as fairness

(3) Justice as rights

Page 4: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

4

People and Justice

Normative arguments• Before we begin a discussion of justice it is

important to understand that any discussion of this issue is inherently normative, which means what?

Page 5: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

5

People and Justice

Normative arguments

• A normative discussion is a discussion of what is right or ethical. To put it simply, it’s about deciding what constitutes a “good place to live” or a “good society,” as opposed to merely accepting the world as it is. Normative arguments are, in this sense, about how we should go about building the best possible world.

Page 6: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

6

People and Justice

Normative arguments

• Normative arguments, not surprisingly, are generally controversial. They are controversial because reasonable people will almost always disagree on what is “moral,” “ethnical” or “good.” And, even if they can agree on basic principles, they may fundamentally disagree on how to achieve a better world.

Page 7: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

7

People and Justice

Normative arguments• Normative arguments are also controversial for a less

obvious reason: in the social sciences, many scholars are uncomfortable talking about what ought to be; instead, they are ostensibly only concerned with what is. That is, some scholars believe that their primary duty is to discover how the world really works, to identify purely objective forces and dynamics. They would prefer to leave normative questions to “philosophers.”

Page 8: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

8

People and Justice

Normative arguments• One more point: Normative questions have profound

political implications. As we’ll see in our discussion that follows, how we as a society answer normative questions has clear implications with regard to how resources are used and distributed and how power is exercised at the domestic, international, and global levels. This is one of the underlying points the authors are attempting to make in their chapter.

Page 9: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

9

People and JusticeJustice as distribution• This position is basically about the distribution of

material goods, and revolves around the question: Is it moral for some people to have much more than they need, while others don’t have enough to even survive?

• What do you think?

Page 10: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

10

People and Justice

Justice as distribution

• The answer to this question, of course, is subject to a great deal of debate. In the chapter, the authors give us two, somewhat exaggerated perspectives of this debate, one by Peter Singer the other by Garrett Hardin.

Page 11: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

11

People and Justice

Justice as distribution

• Singer’s Argument: Summed up in the following sentence: “If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it.”

Page 12: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

12

People and Justice

Justice as distribution

• Singer’s reasoning based on philosophical position of “marginal utilitarianism.”

• Definitional note: Utilitarianism is the doctrine or belief that the greatest good of the greatest number should be the purpose of human conduct (originally proposed by Jeremy Bentham.

Page 13: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

13

People and Justice

Justice as distribution

• What do you think of Singer’s basic position? Any problems? Any objections?

Page 14: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

14

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• What do the authors say?

• The authors point out a number of obvious practical and philosophical problems with Singer’s basic position, but they also agree that his argument raises troubling questions: What do we owe morally to those who are neither family nor members of any out communities of obligation, such as fellow citizens? We could rephrases this to say, “Do we have any moral obligations to those living outside our borders?”

Page 15: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

15

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• If we hem and haw on these questions—if we say, for example, that we have an obligation, but that we have more an obligation to our fellow citizens (none of whom we may know in any meaningful sense of the word), are we not just moral relativists? And aren’t we told by religious and even political leaders that moral relativism is wrong?

Page 16: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

16

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• On the other end of the spectrum is Garrett Hardin, who wrote a direct response to Singer’s position in an article called, “Lifeboat ethics: The case against helping the poor.”

Page 17: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

17

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• Hardin’s Argument: We cannot save everyone, so we must save ourselves. This is the responsible and the moral thing to do.

Page 18: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

18

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• Hardin uses the metaphor of the lifeboat to illustrate his position: He asks you to imagine that you and several others are adrift at sea in a lifeboat. The lifeboat is basically full and has sufficient food and water to last until everyone in the boat is rescued. In the water around you are a large number of people who can still swim, but eventually will drown if they are not saved (i.e., pulled into your lifeboat). So what should be done? What will happen if the people in the lifeboat start to pull others in?

Page 19: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

19

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• According to Hardin, the situation is clear: pulling people in may result in the lifeboat sinking; then everyone will die. Alternatively, pulling only a few people in, means you will less food and water and thereby diminish everyone’s chances for survival. Beyond this, though, is the question of who should be saved?

Page 20: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

20

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• Connecting this metaphor to the real world, Hardin argues that the rich countries simply don’t have the resources to save the poorer countries; moreover, whatever help is extended will likely only exacerbate an already bad situation by encouraging poor countries to produce more children.

Page 21: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

21

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• What do you think of Hardin’s position? • Even if you disagree, isn’t it true that no

matter how uncomfortable we may be with his conclusions, most of us tacitly if not explicitly accept this his position?

Page 22: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

22

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• One more question: Even if Hardin is right about how most of us accept the position of protecting our own—of having no moral or other obligation to anyone who is not a bona fide, legal citizen of our country—is this really a justifiable moral position?

Page 23: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

23

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• One point on the logic of Hardin’s position: To a large extent, Hardin’s position is dependent on a zero-sum view of the world’s resources. He assumes, in other words, that the world’s resources are inherently limited and largely fixed, which implies that if the rich give something up, it means that we have less and somehow else has more

Page 24: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

24

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• Consider the metaphor of a sliced pie: If someone gets a bigger piece it necessarily leaves everyone else with less.

Page 25: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

25

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• The problem, however, is that wealth per se is not a limited resource, and food and other resources are not “fixed slices” either. For example, the production of food, over the past century, has more than kept up with the increase in people. It’s also important to understand that the world’s population, while it may be increasing, is increasing in part precisely because of poverty.

Page 26: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

26

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• In other words, as poverty in poor countries decreases, it is certainly possible that the growth rate in population will also decrease.

• On this point, consider the case of Japan: As the country’s prosperity increased, the birth rate declined dramatically. Today, in fact, Japan’s overall population is shrinking at a fairly fast rate.

Page 27: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

27

People and Justice

Page 28: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

28

People and JusticeJustice as distribution

• It is important to understand that defining justice simply in terms of the allocation of material resources is a limited, and some might say, fatally limited perspective.

• Others argue that, before we talk about distributive justice, we need to talk about why things are the way they are. That is, why do such vast inequalities in control over resources exist in the first place? What are the “rules” or practices that have created and maintained the obvious disparities that exist in the world?

Page 29: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

29

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• Some scholars, most notably John Rawls, argue that we need to understand that societies are organized in ways that tend to institutionalize injustices so that, for example, the unequal distribution of resources is largely pre-determined. That is, the rich have more because the rules of the system essentially guarantee that they’ll have more.

Page 30: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

30

People and JusticeJustice as fairness• To Rawls and others, then, it is not the unequal distribution of

resources per se that is the problem; instead, it is an unfair, highly biased system of rules that is.

• Recognizing this is important, for it allows us to take a different approach to justice. To Rawls, this approach centered on identifying the fundamental principles that would increase the level of fairness in society. Moreover, once its members recognized the centrality of such principles in seeking and achieving just outcomes, they would willingly accept those principles and the outcomes, however unequal the results.

Page 31: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

31

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• To see how this might be achieved, Rawls devised a thought experiment, which he called “decision-making from the original position, behind a veil of ignorance.”

Page 32: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

32

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• Imagine this: a situation in which no one knows anything about his own circumstances: his wealth, education, lineage, skin color, nationality, and so on. Rawls assumed that this set of circumstances would most clearly reflect an “original position,” that is a position in which no one had an advantage deriving from an “accident of birth”

• The situation of not knowing anything about your original circumstances also reflects the “veil of ignorance,” which guarantees that all decisions about distribution will be made “disinterestedly,” that is, people will make decisions based on what is right rather than on what would be best for themselves.

Page 33: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

33

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• With this in mind, a group is asked to divide the riches of a society or the world. How would this be done?

• Rawls argues that it is likely that such a group would decide to divide the wealth equally. Everyone would consider this the fairest distribution of resources, and because of this, inequalities that may arise after the original distribution of resources are also considered fair and just.

Page 34: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

34

People and JusticeJustice as fairness• Of course, the real world is nothing like the situation Rawls describes:

We all start off in different original positions: some of us are born into wealthy families, some into poor families, some of us are born in rich countries, some in utterly poor countries; some of us born with intelligence or good looks, or some other genetic endowments that give us tremendous advantages or disadvantages over others.

• These original endowments will, over time, result in inequality; some of us can also use our endowments to increase inequality (to get more for ourselves at the expense of others). At the same time, these circumstances are not necessarily considered unfair; after all, the people who were lucky enough to be born in the right place at the right time with the right attributes didn’t do anything wrong. Why should they then suffer just because others weren’t quite as lucky?

Page 35: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

35

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• This wasn’t the point Rawls was trying to make in his thought experiment; rather his goal was to derive principles of justice about which everyone could agree, regardless of their original positions.

• Rawls concluded that two principles follow from this exercise: first, an equality of basic rights, and second, what he called the “difference principle.” The difference principle regards any inequality as unjust unless its removal makes worse the situations of the worst-off members of society.

Page 36: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

36

People and JusticeJustice as fairness

• Rawls, it is important to understand, is a philosopher first and foremost; for this reason, perhaps, he didn’t offer any concrete ways to achieve a just society; instead, he only hoped that recognition of these rules of fairness would stimulate discussion and lead to practical principles that would create a more just society. To a large extent, he was successful: since he originally published his ideas 30 years ago, there has been an immense amount of debate on the principles of justice and fairness

Page 37: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

37

People and Justice

• A few aspects of this debate are covered in the remaining sections of the chapter, which cover such issues as “Justice as rights,” “justice as opportunity,” and “justice as recognition, respect, and dignity”

Page 38: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

38

People and Justice

• There is a lot of stuff covered in these three sections, probably too much for us to digest in class (really, we could devote a whole quarter to a discussion of justice)

• So instead of covering each of these three sections in detail, let me highlight a few general points.

Page 39: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

39

People and Justice

• First, it is important to understand that, in any discussion of justice, there are a number of underlying tensions or contradictions that can complicate the discussion immensely.

• Consider the question of human rights: Human rights are based on two kinds of rights, “positive liberty,” that is the freedom to do as we please, and “negative liberty,” that is, the freedom from control by outsiders.

Page 40: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

40

People and Justice

• Yet, to have positive liberty, there have to be rules that control what individuals can do. How, for example, can you have freedom of expression if someone else immediately beats you up for speaking your mind? Yet, in controlling the freedom of others to “beat up” whomever they please, we are limiting liberty. At the extremes, positive liberty erases negative liberty and vice versa.

• This tells us that “rights” and “justice” can never be absolute.

Page 41: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

41

People and Justice

• Second, and in a strongly related vein, justice or rights require some sort of coercive entity(that is, states) capable of enforcing law. This creates a paradox: states are often the worst offenders of rights, but they are also necessary for rights to exist

• This creates all sorts of practical as well as philosophical questions. How, for example, is it possible to transcend national borders to achieve a sort of universal rights? Is this even desirable?

Page 42: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

42

People and Justice• Consider this example: What happens when one

country’s definition of justice contradicts a supposedly universal standard of human rights? On this point, consider the issue of the death penalty, which is considered just punishment in the United States but a violation of human rights by most other countries in the world. Or how about torture? Torture is condemned by international laws, norms, and treaties, but the Bush administration continues to insist that has a right and duty to use any means necessary to extract information from enemy combatants.

Page 43: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

43

People and Justice• Third, discussions of justice cannot be divorced

from the larger social context. For example, there are a number of scholars who say that justice does not require equality in outcomes (re “justice as opportunities” or “justice as fairness”). In the abstract, these are reasonable arguments, but they cannot hold water in the real world. On this point, consider what John Isbister had to say (quoting from pp. 135-6):

Page 44: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

44

People and Justice• “This reasoning [about justice] leads to the possibility that

equality of opportunity actually requires equal outcomes. This possibility exists because we live our lives over a period of years, our generations overlap, and our societies continue over time. My opportunities are determined in large measure by the resources—including economic, educational, technological, and moral resources—given to me by my parents and by my society. If my parents and society are vastly different in their access to these resources from yours, you and I will be unequal at the starting blocks. Until each person has an equal opportunity to develop his or her talents—something that cannot exist while the distribution of outcomes in the world remains unequal—we cannot be equal at the starting line.

Page 45: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

45

People and Justice• While Isbister may make a good point, his

argument, too, has all sorts of practical and philosophical problems: Would making the starting line the same for all disadvantage others (i.e., those that already were in front)?

Page 46: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

46

People and Justice• Fourth, given the foregoing discussion, the last point I want to

highlight is simply this: Discussion about justice can make your head hurt because they end up becoming too complicated, too messy, and just too hard to resolve. Plus, as the authors note, too many philosophers fall into the old “ought-is” trap. That is, they argue about the need for social change without specifying how this might be accomplished. To be fair, this isn’t how many political philosophers see their job: their job is to conceptualize the conditions under which a particular objective might be achieved; it is the job of other social scientists to discover the lever that could “move the world.”

Page 47: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

47

People and Justice• What, then, is the solution?

Page 48: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

48

People and Justice• The authors don’t necessarily offer the solution, but

they offer us a map for finding the right path to a solution.

• They do this, ironically, by discussing another set of philosophical positions, between communitarianism and cosmopolitanism

Page 49: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

49

People and Justice• Cosmopolitanism is reflected in Singer’s position,

while communtarianism is reflected in the position of Hardin.

• In communitarian view, justice is something that is inherently limited to fellow citizens: people only have a right and duty to protect their own. This implies that we can, without shame, turn our back on injustice when it is committed by or against non-citizens. They are simply not our concern.

Page 50: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

50

People and Justice• In Singer’s extreme cosmopolitan view,

everyone is deserving of rights essentially without limits. But, according to the authors, this is a non-starter. It’s a non-starter, in part, because Singer’s view of rights is simply to abstract. Other cosmopolitans, however, provide a more grounded approach.

• On this point, the authors are particularly interested in the work of Onora O’Neill.

Page 51: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

51

People and Justice• Unlike Singer, O’Neill focuses on obligations as

opposed to rights. As O’Neill explains it, “There are reasons enough to show that obligations provide the more coherent and more comprehensive starting point for thinking about ethical requirements, including the requirements of justice. Although the rhetoric of rights has a heady power, and that of obligations and duties few immediate attractions, it helps to view the perspective of obligations as fundamental if the political and ethical implications of normative claims are to be taken seriously.

Page 52: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

52

People and Justice• Obligations, in short, are more personal.

When speaking of obligations, moreover, we immediately start to focus on agency: we must act in order to be just and achieve justice, and we must do so regardless of states, governments, or even co-nationals. Better yet, we should do so with others, as a collective political project.

Page 53: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

53

People and Justice• This last point, although not one the authors end

their chapter with, helps us tie everything discussed thus far to the relationship between justice and people. In an important sense, the authors are suggesting that justice, whether at the local, national, regional, international, or global levels starts with the actions of individuals acting alone and, better yet, in groups.

Page 54: POLS 374 Foundations of Global Politics People and Justice Lecture

54

People and Justice• Ultimately, as they put it, “Justice demands that we

believe all our fellow human beings are worthy of dignity and respect; that we act in ways that facilitate and foster dignity and respect among human beings; and that we provide the material necessities that enable people to live dignified lives worth of respect. Indeed, we are obligated to do these things and also to help to construct a discourse that will propagate justice and embed it in institutions at every level of life.”