theories of the good life shane ryan [email protected] 27/09/13

30
Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan [email protected] 27/09/13

Upload: sherilyn-greer

Post on 16-Dec-2015

215 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Theories of the Good Life

Shane Ryan

[email protected]

27/09/13

Page 2: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Seminar Goals

● Course Introduction

● Comments on analytic methodology

● Set out and offer critical evaluation of theories of the good life

Page 3: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Course Introduction

Themes in Ethics and Epistemology

● Ethics – topics include “Theories of the Good Life”, “Virtue Ethics”, “Why Be Moral?”.

● Epistemology – topics include “the Gettier case”, “Virtue Epistemology”, “the Value of Knowledge”.

● An underlying focus of the course is virtue approaches.

Page 4: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Course Introduction

Core Course Resources

● Shafer-Landau, R. Ethical Theory: An Anthology. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007.

● Pritchard, D. What is this Thing Called Knowledge?. London and New York: Routledge, 2006.

● The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu.

Page 5: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Analytic Methodology:some characteristic features

Intuitions

● Intuitions in analytic philosophy are generally treated as carrying prima facie evidential weight.

– A typical use of intuitions is in response to cases/examples.

Page 6: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Analytic Methodology:some characteristic features

Intuitions● It counts as a mark in favour of a philosophical

account if that account can make sense of our intuitions.

– Making sense of our intuitions can mean cashing out why our intuitions are right or diagnosing why they are misleading, or why some intuitions are right and others are misleading.

– A counterintuitive account, by virtue of its claims or conclusion, has more to do to persuade us.

● Literature on use of intuitions: See Goldman 2007, Sosa 2007, and Stich 1988.

Page 7: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Analytic Methodology: some characteristic features

Expression of Ideas

● Everyday words are used and technical terms tend to be avoided if practical.

● Papers tend to follow the structure of identifying an issue/problem and addressing that issue/problem by way of a clear, logical argument.

Page 8: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

Theories of the Good Life

Lecture Structure

● 1. The Issue● 2. Hedonism● 3. The Experience Machine● 4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory● 5. Objective List Theory● 6. Conclusion

Page 9: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

1. The Issue

● What makes someone's life go well for them? Or, what factors are relevant when considering how well someone's life has gone for them– Sometimes this topic also comes under the

heading of “well-being”.

● For example, what criterion or criteria should be used to say whether Sigmund Freud had a good life?

Page 10: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

1. The Issue

Preview of Possible Answers

● Is what's relevant the pleasure/happiness a person has over the course of their life? (Hedonism)

● Or is it the desires that were satisfied that is relevant? (Desire-fulfilment theory)

● Or is there an objective list of goods, including perhaps friendship, knowledge and achievement, that all bear on how well someone's life has gone. (Objective list theory).

Page 11: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

2. Hedonism

● What matters is pleasure and pain.

● Goods such as friendship and achievement are only valuable in so far as they contribute to a person's pleasure. (They are instrumentally valuable, whereas pleasure is intrinsically valuable.)

– One hedonist strategy is to say that aiming at such goods is a good way of bringing pleasure to a person's life. (Moore, 2004).

● But why, the hedonist may rhetorically ask, think that such goods are valuable, if a person derives no pleasure from them?

Page 12: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

2. Hedonism

General notes● Jeremy Bentham and J.S. Mill are proponents

– Mill (1859) agrees that in calculating how well someone's life has gone we should consider the duration and intensity of the pleasure (and pain) had.

● Mill adds that we should also consider the quality of the pain had.

– This provides a way for him to respond to the charge that “hedonism is the doctrine of the swine”.

● Feldman (2002) defends attitudinal hedonism – enjoying what you get.

Page 13: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

● “Suppose there were an experience machine that would give you any experience you desired. Superduper neuropsychologists could stimulate your brain so that you would think and feel you were writing a great novel, or making a friend, or reading an interesting book. All the time you would be floating in a tank, with electrodes attached to your brain. Should you plug into this machine for life, preprogramming your life's experiences?” (Nozick, 1974).

Page 14: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

Further points about the experience machine

● You can select from a broad catalogue of possible experiences.

● You can choose a lifetime of bliss. In other words, you can choose a lifetime of maximum pleasure.

● Once inside you won't know that you are inside the experience machine, “you'll think that it's all actually happening”. (Nozick, 1974.)

Page 15: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

● If hedonism is true, then it should follow that it's better to be inside the machine than not, and that there's nothing of value (non-instrumental) unavailable to a person inside the machine. (Shafer-Landau: 2009)

● It's taken to be intuitive that choosing a life inside the machine would be a mistake.

Page 16: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

● Implications, if that intuition is correct:

– How one's life feels from the inside is not the sole determinant of how well one's life has gone.

– A life of maximum pleasure and minimum pain inside the experience machine would not be a maximally good life.

Page 17: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

● What matters to us in addition to our experiences?

● Nozick's response:– We want to do certain things– We want to be a certain way– Not being limited to a man-made reality

● But, as Nozick notes, the first two could also be brought about by a similar types of machines.

Page 18: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

Nozick's diagnosis

● What is disturbing about such machines is their living our lives for us.

● Nozick suggests that we want to live in contact with reality.

Page 19: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

3. The Experience Machine

● A hedonist might respond by arguing that our intuitions in response to the experience machine thought experiment our misleading. (Crisp, 2013).

● Another possible hedonist response is to say that pleasure deservedly had is more valuable and that pleasure derived from the experience machine is not appropriately derived. For more, see Feldman (2002).

Page 20: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

● One response to the experience machine thought experiment might be to say that what matters is that we have our desires fulfilled.– In other words, it seems more likely that people

would desire to actually write a great novel rather than just have the experience of doing so.

Page 21: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

● On one version of desire-fulfilment theory “what matters to a person's well-being is the overall level of desire satisfaction in their life as a whole”. (Crisp, 2013).

Page 22: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

● Something is good for someone if and only if it fulfils their desires in their life as a whole.

● The implications– This means that the fulfilment of any such desires

will be good for a person.– And that anything that is not the satisfaction of

such a desire cannot be good for a person

Page 23: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

The Orphan Monk Case

● At a very early age a young man began training to become a monk. As a result he has led a very sheltered life. He is offered a choice of continuing to be a monk or becoming a cook or a gardener.

● He has no conception of what it would be like to be a cook or a gardener so he chooses (and desires) to remain a monk. (Crisp, 2013.)

– Yet it seems possible that he might live a better life if he choose one of the other two options.

Page 24: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

● One attempted response is to build into a desire fulfilment account that the relevant agent desires contribute toward the good life if and only if those desires are informed.

● This version of the theory faces a challenging case articulated by John Rawls (in Crisp, 2013).

– “Imagine a brilliant Harvard mathematician, fully informed about the options available to her, who develops an overriding desire to count blades of grass on the lawns of Harvard.”

Page 25: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

4. Desire-Fulfilment Theory

Response

● The desire-fulfilment theorist might insist that, if the mathematician lives a life in which her desires are fulfilled, even if that includes counting blades of grass, then that's all that matters.

● Counterexamples to hedonism and desire fulfilment theory:

– something beyond a subject's experiential states or whether she satisfies her desires may contribute to how well her life has gone for her.

Page 26: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

5. Objective List Theory

● Aristotle: We should desire things because they’re good, not think things are good because we desire them.

● According to this theory there are a number of goods, possibly including knowledge and friendship, which contribute towards the good life.– Note, the list may also include pleasure.

Page 27: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

5. Objective List Theory ● Certain things are good or bad for us, whether

or not we want to have the good things, or to avoid the bad things

● But what things are they? How do we go about finding out what they are?

Page 28: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

5. Objective List Theory

● An objective list approach leaves so open what could contribute to the good life that can yield the right answer in a multitude of cases, but fails as a theory in providing specifics as to what should be included.

● But this objection is somewhat unfair.

– Various philosophers have been developing objective list theory in various directions. (e.g. the perfectionist approach of Thomas Hurka, 1993).

Page 29: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

6. Conclusion

● Objections to hedonism suggest:– Not all pleasure is good for us– Pleasure isn't the only thing that's good for us

● Objections to desire-fulfillment theory suggest:– Fulfilling our desires is not the only thing that is

good for us– The fulfillment of some desires may be not be

good for us.

Page 30: Theories of the Good Life Shane Ryan s.g.ryan@sms.ed.ac.uk 27/09/13

6. Conclusion

● Objective list theory looks like providing the most promising answer.– But is this just because in an under-developed

form we can imagine it satisfying all our intuitions to the various cases?

– How should we go about determining what should be included on any list?

– Are the goods that we might identify in any way connected?